Social Norms and Their Violations Essay

Norms and reactions to norm violations, how we learn social norms, observations of social norms in college, violation of social norms, works cited.

A norm is a complex concept traditionally defined as the standard of beliefs and understandings that control human behavior in society (Spillius 75). On the other hand, psychologists define norms as informal understanding that regulates people’s behavior in smaller units such as offices (Spillius 75).

In addition, psychologists accentuate two components of social norms, namely, the behavior exhibition and acceptance by the group. Specific norms may characterize expectations of the culture. Norms are important because they act as behavior guidelines and help maintain order in society.

Norms are classified into four dimensions, which are taboos, mores, laws, and folkways. Folkways constitute daily actions that accord to the custom. Violations of such rules usually do not amount to serious penalty.

A more is a set of norms that promotes moral values in the society, the violation of which is fraught with dire consequences. Laws are written norms enforceable by a state agency, the breach of which leads to criminal liability. As far as taboos are concerned, their violation leads to an extreme penalty such as condemnation from society.

Social norms shape the behaviors and actions of individuals to a considerable extent. They represent an unwritten policy concerning the expected human behavior. Social norms are fundamental in promoting order and control in society. These rules reflect the behavioral patterns of members of a certain group. The application of these norms can be achieved through sanctions or body language in case of unofficial enforcement.

Sanctions are the expressions constructed on the approval or disapproval of certain types of behavior that vary depending on the values of the society. Sanctions can either be positive or negative depending on the society’s thoughts (Spillius 175). Positive sanctions are rewarded with prizes such as gifts and money, while negative ones are heavily discouraged.

Socialization and internalization provide a framework for conformity to norms in the society (Spillius 205). In the event of nonconformity, social control tools such as punishments, fines, and ostracism are implemented to restore order and control.

The understanding of social norms begins with the individual’s upbringing. Socially acceptable behaviors become a part of the person’s values from childhood to adulthood. For example; I remember at my tender age, belching while eating was unacceptable in my family. But violations of such rules did not amount to moral punishment. Although the discovery did make me feel uncomfortable about my manners and culture, it only helped me become a decent member of society and learn to meet its standards.

Different settings have specific expectations on the behavior of individuals. A college is a place that brings people from all walks of life in terms of socio-economic and political backgrounds together (Spillius 65). Due to this cultural diversity, set rules and regulations help in restoring order and discipline.

Values like discipline, sharing, and trusts are highly valued at college and in any institution. During class work, students are expected to raise their hands before making contributions to the debate. I remember one of the students expressing her concern without the lecturer’s permission, which violated the provisions of the classroom norms.

Upon detection, the lecturer expelled the student from the classroom pending disciplinary action. Students reacted angrily because they felt that their peer had violated the classroom norms of the college. So I would say the behavior leading to ostracizing the students doing socially biased things is a negative social norm. The behavior resulted in a violation of mores. Secondly, the classroom rules should focus on promoting positive social norms.

Sharing information is encouraged through group discussions and joint assignments, and violations of such norms would amount to breaking norms of folkways. Sharing and respect are some of the norms that we practice in our daily activities, and violations of these social norms usually lead to stringent penalties.

Spillius, Elizabeth. Family and Social Network: Roles, Norms, and External Relationships in Ordinary Urban Families . New York, NY: Free Press, 1971. Print.

  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2022, May 2). Social Norms and Their Violations. https://ivypanda.com/essays/social-norms/

"Social Norms and Their Violations." IvyPanda , 2 May 2022, ivypanda.com/essays/social-norms/.

IvyPanda . (2022) 'Social Norms and Their Violations'. 2 May.

IvyPanda . 2022. "Social Norms and Their Violations." May 2, 2022. https://ivypanda.com/essays/social-norms/.

1. IvyPanda . "Social Norms and Their Violations." May 2, 2022. https://ivypanda.com/essays/social-norms/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Social Norms and Their Violations." May 2, 2022. https://ivypanda.com/essays/social-norms/.

  • American History: Colonial Backcountry Folkways
  • Effects of the SIR on Tradition and Social Mores
  • Albion’s Seed Four British Folkways in America
  • Present and Past Understanding of Home: Social Mores and Culture
  • Norms Assignment in Society
  • Aspects of Cultural Experience
  • Nature of Taboo Words
  • Eating Horse Is a Taboo in the US
  • Child Behavior Today and Ten Years Ago
  • Henry David Thoreau vs. Richard Brautigan
  • Divorce Rates in the United Arab Emirates
  • Young Generation Healthy Lifestyle
  • Respect for Elder's Wisdom
  • Aspirations, Attitudes, and Beliefs in the Social Environment
  • Environmental Factors Influence on Life Aspirations

helpful professor logo

102 Examples of Social Norms (List)

social norms examples and definition, explained below

Social norms are the unspoken rules that govern how people interact with each other. They can vary from culture to culture, and even from group to group within a culture.

Some social norms are so ingrained in our psyches that we don’t even think about them; we just automatically do what is expected of us. Social norms examples include covering your mouth when you cough, waiting your turn, and speaking softly in a library.

Breaking societal norms can sometimes lead to awkward or uncomfortable situations. For example, if you’re in a library where it’s considered rude to talk on your cell phone, and you answer a call, you’ll likely get some disapproving looks from the people around you.

Understanding the social norms of the place you’re visiting is an important part of cultural etiquette to show respect for the people around you.

Examples of Social Norms

  • Greeting people when you see them.
  • Saying “thank you” for favors.
  • Holding the door open for others.
  • Standing up when someone else enters the room.
  • Offering to help someone carrying something heavy.
  • Speaking quietly in public places.
  • Waiting in line politely.
  • Respecting other people’s personal space.
  • Disposing of trash properly.
  • Refraining from eating smelly foods in public.
  • Paying for goods or services with a smile.
  • Complimenting others on their appearance or achievements.
  • Asking others about their day or interests.
  • Avoiding gossip and rumors.
  • Volunteering to help others in need.
  • Saying “I’m sorry” when you’ve made a mistake.
  • Supporting others in their time of need.
  • Participating in group activities.
  • Respecting authority figures.
  • Being on time for important engagements.
  • Avoiding interrupting others when they are speaking.
  • Showing interest in other people’s lives and experiences.
  • Refraining from using offensive language or gestures.
  • Being honest and truthful with others at all times.
  • Treating others with kindness and respect, regardless of their social status or background.
  • Putting the needs of others before your own.
  • Participating in charitable works and activities.
  • Helping others whenever possible.
  • Welcoming guests into your home or place of business.
  • Nodding, smiling, and looking people in the eyes to show you are listening to them.
  • Following the laws and regulations of your country.
  • Respecting the rights and beliefs of others.
  • Cooperating with others in order to achieve common goals.
  • Being tolerant and understanding of different viewpoints.
  • Displaying good manners and etiquette in social interactions.
  • Waiting in line for your turn.
  • Taking your shoes off before walking into someone’s house.
  • Putting your dog on a leash in parks and other public spaces.
  • Letting the elderly or pregnant people take your seat on a bus.

Social Norms for Students

  • Arrive to class on time and prepared.
  • Pay attention and take notes.
  • Stay quiet when other students are working.
  • Raise your hand if you have a question.
  • Do your homework and turn it in on time.
  • Participate in class discussions.
  • Respect your teachers and classmates.
  • Follow the school’s rules and regulations.
  • Use appropriate language and behavior.
  • Ask permission to be excused if you need to go to the bathroom.
  • Go to the bathroom before class begins.
  • Keep your workspace clean.
  • Do not plagiarize or cheat.
  • Wait your turn to speak.
  • Ask permission to use other people’s supplies.
  • Include all your peers in your group when doing group work.

Related: Classroom Rules for Middle School

Social Norms while Dining Out

  • Wait to be seated.
  • Remain seated until everyone is served.
  • Don’t reach across the table.
  • Use your napkin.
  • Don’t chew with your mouth open.
  • Don’t talk with your mouth full.
  • Keep elbows off the table.
  • Use a fork and knife when eating.
  • Drink from a glass, not from the bottle or carton.
  • Request more bread or butter only if you’re going to eat it all.
  • Don’t criticize the food or service.
  • Thank your server when you’re finished.
  • Leave a tip if you’re satisfied with the service.

Social Norms while using your Phone

  • Keep your phone on silent or vibrate mode while in meetings.
  • Don’t answer your phone in a public place unless it’s an emergency.
  • Don’t talk on the phone while driving.
  • Don’t text while driving.
  • Don’t take or make calls during class.
  • Don’t use your phone in a movie theater.
  • Turn off your phone when you’re with someone else.
  • Place your phone on airplane mode while flying.
  • Do not look at someone else’s phone.
  • Ensure your ringtone is inoffensive when in public or around children.

Social Norms in Libraries

  • Be quiet and respect the other patrons.
  • Don’t talk on your phone.
  • Don’t bring food or drinks into the library.
  • Don’t sleep in the library.
  • Don’t bring pets into the library.
  • Return all books to the correct location.
  • Don’t mark or damage library books.
  • Make sure your cell phone is turned off.
  • Return your books on time.

Social Norms in Other Countries

  • In France, it is considered polite to kiss acquaintances on both cheeks when meeting them.
  • In Japan, it is customary to take your shoes off when entering someone’s home.
  • In India, it is considered rude to show the soles of your feet or to point your feet at someone else.
  • In Italy, it is common for people to give each other a light kiss on the cheek as a gesture of hello or goodbye.
  • In China, it is customary to leave some food on your plate after eating, as a sign of respect for the cook.
  • In Spain, it is customary to call elders “Don” or “Doña.”
  • In Iceland, it is considered polite to say “thank you” (Takk) after every meal.
  • In Thailand, it is customary to remove your shoes before entering a home or temple.
  • In Germany, it is customary to shake hands with everyone you meet, both men and women.
  • In Argentina, it is customary for people to hug and kiss cheeks as a gesture of hello or goodbye.

Social Norms that Should be Broken

  • “ Women should be polite” – Stand up for what you believe in, even if it makes you look bossy.
  • “Don’t draw attention to yourself” – Embrace your uniqueness and difference so long as you’re respectful of others.
  • “Don’t question your parents or your boss” – Protest bad behavior from people in authority if you know you’re morally right.
  • “Mistakes are embarrassing” – It’s okay to make mistakes and be seen to fail. It means you’re making an effort and pushing your boundaries.
  • “Respect your elders” – If your elders are engaging in bad behavior, stand up to them and let them know you’re taking note of what they’re doing.

Cultural vs Social Norms

Cultural norms are the customs and traditions that are passed down from one generation to the next. They’re connected to the traditions, values, and practices of a particular culture.

Societal norms, on the other hand, reflect the current social standard for appropriate behavior within a society. In modern multicultural societies, there are different groups with different cultural norms, but they must all agree on a common set of social norms for public spaces.

We also have a concept called group norms , which define how smaller groups – like workplace teams or sports teams – will operate. These might differ from group to group, and are highly dependant on the expectations and standards of the group/team leader.

Norms Change Depending on the Context

Norms are different depending on different contexts, including in different eras, and in different societies. What might be considered polite in one context could be considered rude in another.

For example, norms in the 1950s were much more gendered. Negative gender stereotypes restricted women because it was normative for women to be quiet, polite, and submissive in public. Today, women have much more equality.

Similarly, the norms and taboos in the United States will be very different from those in China. For example, Chinese businessmen are often expected to share expensive gifts during negotiations. In the United States, this could be considered bordering on bribery.

What are the Four Types of Norms?

There are four types of norms : folkways, mores, taboos, and laws.

  • Folkways are social conventions that are not strictly enforced, but are generally considered to be polite or appropriate. An example of a folkway is covering your mouth when you sneeze.
  • Mores are social conventions that are considered to have a moral dimension. Due to their moral dimension, they’re generally considered to be more important than folkways. Violation of mores can result in social sanctions so they often overlap with laws (mentioned below). An example of a more is not drinking and driving.
  • Taboos are considered ‘negative norms’, or things that you should avoid doing. If you do them, you’ll be seen as rude. An example of a taboo is using your phone in a movie theater or spitting indoors.
  • Laws are the most formal and serious type of norm. They are usually enforced by the government and can result in criminal penalties if violated. Examples of laws include not stealing from others and not assaulting others.

Conclusion: What are Social Norms?

Social norms are defined as the unspoken rules that help us to get along with others in a polite and respectful manner. It’s important to follow them so that we can maintain a positive social environment for everyone involved. Social norms examples include not spitting indoors, covering your mouth when you sneeze, and shaking hands with everyone you meet.

Chris

Chris Drew (PhD)

Dr. Chris Drew is the founder of the Helpful Professor. He holds a PhD in education and has published over 20 articles in scholarly journals. He is the former editor of the Journal of Learning Development in Higher Education. [Image Descriptor: Photo of Chris]

  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 5 Top Tips for Succeeding at University
  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 50 Durable Goods Examples
  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 100 Consumer Goods Examples
  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 30 Globalization Pros and Cons

Leave a Comment Cancel Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Social Norms

Social norms, the informal rules that govern behavior in groups and societies, have been extensively studied in the social sciences. Anthropologists have described how social norms function in different cultures (Geertz 1973), sociologists have focused on their social functions and how they motivate people to act (Durkheim 1895 [1982], 1950 [1957]; Parsons 1937; Parsons & Shils 1951; James Coleman 1990; Hechter & Opp 2001), and economists have explored how adherence to norms influences market behavior (Akerlof 1976; Young 1998a). More recently, also legal scholars have touted social norms as efficient alternatives to legal rules, as they may internalize negative externalities and provide signaling mechanisms at little or no cost (Ellickson 1991; Posner 2000).

With a few exceptions, the social science literature conceives of norms as exogenous variables. Since norms are mainly seen as constraining behavior, some of the key differences between moral, social, and legal norms—as well as differences between norms and conventions—have been blurred. Much attention has instead been paid to the conditions under which norms will be obeyed. Because of that, the issue of sanctions has been paramount in the social science literature. Moreover, since social norms are seen as central to the production of social order or social coordination, research on norms has been focused on the functions they perform. Yet even if a norm may fulfill important social functions (such as welfare maximization or the elimination of externalities), it cannot be explained solely on the basis of the functions it performs. The simplistic functionalist perspective has been rejected on several accounts; in fact, even though a given norm can be conceived as a means to achieve some goal, this is usually not the reason why it emerged in the first place (Elster 1989a, 1989b). Moreover, although a particular norm may persist (as opposed to emerge) because of some positive social function it fulfills, there are many others that are inefficient and even widely unpopular.

Philosophers have taken a different approach to norms. In the literature on norms and conventions, both social constructs are seen as the endogenous product of individuals’ interactions (Lewis 1969; Ullmann-Margalit 1977; Vandershraaf 1995; Bicchieri 2006). Norms are represented as equilibria of games of strategy, and as such they are supported by a cluster of self-fulfilling expectations. Beliefs, expectations, group knowledge and common knowledge have thus become central concepts in the development of a philosophical view of social norms. Paying attention to the role played by expectations in supporting social norms has helped differentiate between social norms, conventions, and descriptive norms: an important distinction often overlooked in the social science accounts, but crucial when we need to diagnose the nature of a pattern of behavior in order to intervene on it.

1. General Issues

2. early theories: socialization, 3. early theories: social identity, 4. early theories: cost-benefit models, 5. game-theoretic accounts, 6. experimental evidence, 7. evolutionary models, 8. conclusion, other internet resources, related entries.

Social norms, like many other social phenomena, are the unplanned result of individuals’ interaction. It has been argued that social norms ought to be understood as a kind of grammar of social interactions. Like a grammar, a system of norms specifies what is acceptable and what is not in a society or group. And, analogously to a grammar, it is not the product of human design. This view suggests that a study of the conditions under which norms come into being—as opposed to one stressing the functions fulfilled by social norms—is important to understand the differences between social norms and other types of injunction (such as hypothetical imperatives, moral codes, or legal rules).

Another important issue often blurred in the literature on norms is the relationship between normative beliefs and behavior. Some authors identify norms with observable, recurrent patterns of behavior. Others only focus on normative beliefs and expectations. Such accounts find it difficult to explain the complexity and heterogeneity of norm-driven behaviors, as they offer an explanation of conformity that is at best partial.

Some popular accounts of why social norms exist are the following. Norms are efficient means to achieve social welfare (Arrow 1971; Akerlof 1976), prevent market failures (Jules Coleman 1989), or cut social costs (Thibaut & Kelley 1959; Homans 1961); norms are either Nash equilibria of coordination games or cooperative equilibria of prisoner’s dilemma-type games (Lewis 1969; Ullmann-Margalit 1977), and as such they solve collective action problems.

Akerlof’s (1976) analysis of the norms that regulate land systems is a good example of the tenet that “norms are efficient means to achieve social welfare”. Since the worker is much poorer and less liquid than the landlord, it would be more natural for the landlord rather than the tenant to bear the risk of crop failure. This would be the case if the landlord kept all the crops, and paid the worker a wage (i.e., the case of a “wage system”). Since the wage would not directly depend on the worker’s effort, this system leaves no incentive to the worker for any effort beyond the minimum necessary. In sharecropping, on the contrary, the worker is paid both for the effort and the time he puts in: a more efficient arrangement in that it increases production.

Thibaut and Kelley’s (1959) view of norms as substitutes for informal influence has a similar functionalist flavor. As an example, they consider a repeated battle of the sexes game. In this game, some bargaining is necessary for each party to obtain, at least occasionally, the preferred outcome. The parties can engage in a costly sequence of threats and promises, but it seems better to agree beforehand on a rule of behavior, such as alternating between the respectively preferred outcomes. Rules emerge because they reduce the costs involved in face-to-face personal influence.

Likewise, Ullman-Margalit (1977) uses game theory to show that norms solve collective action problems, such as prisoner’s dilemma-type situations; in her own words, “… a norm solving the problem inherent in a situation of this type is generated by it” (1977: 22). In a collective action problem, self-centered rational choices produce a Pareto-inefficient outcome. Pareto-efficiency is restored by means of norms backed by sanctions. James Coleman (1990), too, believes that norms emerge in situations in which there are externalities, that is, in all those cases in which an activity produces negative (positive) effects on other parties, without this being reflected in direct compensation; thus the producer of the externality pays no cost for (reaps no benefit from) the unintended effect of their activity. A norm solves the problem by regulating the externality-producing activity, introducing a system of sanctions (rewards).

Also Brennan, Eriksson, Goodin, and Southwood (2013) argue that norms have a function. Norms function to hold us accountable to each other for adherence to the principles that they cover. This may or may not create effective coordination over any given principle, but they place us in positions where we may praise and blame people for their behaviors and attitudes. This function of accountability, they argue, can help create another role for norms, which is imbuing practices with social meaning. This social meaning arises from the expectations that we can place on each other for compliance, and the fact that those behaviors can come to represent shared values, and even a sense of shared identity. This functional role of norms separates it from bare social practices or even common sets of desires, as those non-normative behaviors don’t carry with them the social accountability that is inherent in norms. The distinctive feature of the Brennan et al. account of norms is the centrality of accountability: this feature is what distinguishes norms from other social practices.

All of the above are examples of a functionalist explanation of norms. Functionalist accounts are sometimes criticized for offering a post hoc justification for the existence of norms (i.e., the mere presence of a norm does not justify inferring that that norm exists to accomplish some social function). Indeed, a purely functionalist view may not account for the fact that many social norms are harmful or inefficient (e.g., discriminatory norms against women and minorities), or are so rigid as to prevent the fine-tuning that would be necessary to accommodate new cases. There, one would expect increasing social pressure to abandon such norms.

According to some authors, we can explain the emergence of norms without any reference to the functions they eventually come to perform. Since the norms that are most interesting to study are those that emerge naturally from individuals’ interactions (Schelling 1978), an important theoretical task is to analyze the conditions under which such norms come into being. Because norms often provide a solution to the problem of maintaining social order—and social order requires cooperation—many studies on the emergence and dynamics of norms have focused on cooperation. Norms of honesty, loyalty, reciprocity and promise-keeping are indeed important to the smooth functioning of social groups. One hypothesis is that such cooperative norms emerge in close-knit groups where people have ongoing interactions with each other (Hardin 1982). Evolutionary game theory provides a useful framework for investigating this hypothesis, since repeated games serve as a simple approximation of life in a close-knit group (Axelrod 1984, 1986; Skyrms 1996; Gintis 2000). In repeated encounters people have an opportunity to learn from each other’s behavior, and to secure a pattern of reciprocity that minimizes the likelihood of misperception. In this regard, it has been argued that the cooperative norms likely to develop in close-knit groups are simple ones (Alexander 2000, 2005, 2007); in fact, delayed and disproportionate punishment, as well as belated rewards, are often difficult to understand and hence ineffective. Although norms originate in small, close-knit groups, they often spread well beyond the narrow boundaries of the original group. The challenge thus becomes one of explaining the dynamics of the norm propagation from small groups to large populations.

If norms can thrive and spread, they can also die out. A poorly understood phenomenon is the sudden and unexpected change of well-established patterns of behavior. For example, smoking in public without asking for permission has become unacceptable, and only a few years ago nobody would have worried about using gender-laden language. One would expect inefficient norms (such as discriminatory norms against women and minorities) to disappear more rapidly and with greater frequency than more efficient norms. However, Bicchieri (2016) points out that inefficiency is not a sufficient condition for a norm’s demise. This can be seen by the study of crime and corruption: corruption results in huge social costs, but such costs—even when they take a society to the brink of collapse—are not enough to generate an overhaul of the system. Muldoon (2018a, 2018b, 2020) has argued that social norms are a challenging form of social regulation precisely because there is no simple way to intentionally modify a social norm, as one can with a law or institutional rule. Social norms can even shape one's understanding of how much agency one has (Muldoon 2017).

An influential view of norms considers them as clusters of self-fulfilling expectations (Schelling 1960), in that some expectations often result in behavior that reinforces them. A related view emphasizes the importance of conditional preferences in supporting social norms (Sugden 2000). In particular, according to Bicchieri’s (2006) account, preferences for conformity to social norms are conditional on “empirical expectations” (i.e., first-order beliefs that a certain behavior will be followed) as well as “normative expectations” (i.e., second-order beliefs that a certain behavior ought to be followed). Thus, norm compliance results from the joint presence of a conditional preference for conformity and the belief that other people will conform as well as approve of conformity.

Note that characterizing norms simply as clusters of expectations might be misleading; similarly, a norm cannot simply be identified with a recurrent behavioral pattern either. If we were to adopt a purely behavioral account of norms there would be no way to distinguish shared rules of fairness from, say, the collective morning habit of tooth brushing. After all, such a practice does not depend on whether one expects others to do the same; however, one would not even try to ask for a salary proportionate to one’s education, if one expected compensation to merely follow a seniority rule. In fact, there are behavioral patterns that can only be explained by the existence of norms, even if the behavior prescribed by the norm in question is currently unobserved. For example, in a study of the Ik people, Turnbull (1972) reported that starved hunters-gatherers tried hard to avoid situations where their compliance with norms of reciprocity was expected. Thus they would go out of their way not to be in the position of gift-taker, and hunted alone so that they would not be forced to share their prey with anyone else. Much of the Ik’s behavior could be explained as a way of eluding existing reciprocity norms.

There are many other instances of discrepancies between expectations and behavior . For example, it is remarkable to observe how often people expect others to act selfishly, even when they are prepared to act altruistically themselves (Miller & Ratner 1996). Studies have shown that people’s willingness to give blood is not altered by monetary incentives, but typically those very people who are willing to donate blood for free expect others to donate blood only in the presence of monetary rewards. Similarly, all the interviewed landlords answered positively to a question about whether they would rent an apartment to an unmarried couple; however, they estimated that only 50% of other landlords would accept unmarried couples as tenants (Dawes 1972). Such cases of pluralistic ignorance are rather common; what is puzzling is that people may expect a given norm to be upheld in the face of personal evidence to the contrary (Bicchieri & Fukui 1999). Furthermore, there is evidence suggesting that people who donate blood, tip on a foreign trip, give money to beggars or return a lost wallet often attempt to downplay their altruistic behavior (by supplying selfish motives that seemingly align their actions with a norm of self-interest; Wuthnow 1991, 77).

In a nutshell, norms refer to actions over which people have control, and are supported by shared expectations about what should or should not be done in different types of social situations. However, norms cannot be identified just with observable behavior, nor can they merely be equated with normative beliefs.

The varying degrees of correlation between normative beliefs and actions are an important factor researchers can use to differentiate among various types of norms. Such a correlation is also a key element to consider when critically assessing competing theories of norms: we begin by surveying the socialized actor theory, the social identity theory, and some early rational choice (cost-benefit) models of conformity.

In the theory of the socialized actor (Parsons 1951), individual action is intended as a choice among alternatives. Human action is understood within a utilitarian framework as instrumentally oriented and utility maximizing. Although a utilitarian setting does not necessarily imply a view of human motives as essentially egoistic, this is the preferred interpretation of utilitarianism adopted by Talcott Parsons and much contemporary sociology. In this context, it becomes crucial to explain through which mechanisms social order and stability are attained in a society that would otherwise be in a permanent Hobbesian state of nature. In short, order and stability are essentially socially derived phenomena, brought about by a common value system —the “cement” of society. The common values of a society are embodied in norms that, when conformed to, guarantee the orderly functioning and reproduction of the social system. In the Parsonian framework norms are exogenous: how such a common value system is created and how it may change are issues left unexplored. The most important question is rather how norms get to be followed, and what prompts rational egoists to abide by them. The answer given by the theory of the socialized actor is that people voluntarily adhere to the shared value system, because it is introjected to form a constitutive element of the personality itself (Parsons 1951).

In Parsons’ own words, a norm is

a verbal description of a concrete course of action, … , regarded as desirable, combined with an injunction to make certain future actions conform to this course. (1937: 75)

Norms play a crucial role in individual choice since—by shaping individual needs and preferences—they serve as criteria for selecting among alternatives. Such criteria are shared by a given community and embody a common value system. People may choose what they prefer, but what they prefer in turn conforms to social expectations: norms influence behavior because, through a process of socialization that starts in infancy, they become part of one’s motives for action. Conformity to standing norms is a stable, acquired disposition that is independent of the consequences of conforming. Such lasting dispositions are formed by long-term interactions with significant others (e.g., one’s parents): through repeated socialization, individuals come to learn and internalize the common values embodied in the norms. Internalization is conceived as the process by which people develop a psychological need or motive to conform to a set of shared norms. When norms are internalized norm-abiding behavior will be perceived as good or appropriate, and people will typically feel guilt or shame at the prospect of behaving in a deviant way. If internalization is successful external sanctions will play no role in eliciting conformity and, since individuals are motivated to conform, it follows that normative beliefs and actions will be consistent.

Although Parsons’ analysis of social systems starts with a theory of individual action, he views social actors as behaving according to roles that define their identities and actions (through socialization and internalization). The goal of individual action is to maximize satisfaction. The potential conflict between individual desires and collective goals is resolved by characterizing the common value system as one that precedes and constrains the social actor. The price of this solution is the disappearance of the individual actor as the basic unit of analysis. Insofar as individuals are role-bearers, in Parsons’ theory it is social entities that act: entities that are completely detached from the individual actions that created them. This consideration forms the basis for most of the criticisms raised against the theory of the socialized actor (Wrong 1961); such criticisms are typically somewhat abstract as they are cast in the framework of the holism/individualism controversy.

On the other hand, one may easily verify whether empirical predictions drawn from the socialized actor theory are supported by experimental evidence. For instance, the following predictions can be derived from the theory and easily put to test. (a) Norms will change very slowly and only through intensive social interaction. (b) Normative beliefs are positively correlated to actions; whenever such beliefs change, behavior will follow. (c) If a norm is successfully internalized, expectations of others’ conformity will have no effect on an individual’s choice to conform.

Some of the above statements are not supported by empirical evidence from social psychology. For example, it has been shown that there may not be a relation between people’s normative beliefs (or attitudes) and what people in fact do. In this respect, it should be noted that experimental psychologists have generally focused on “attitudes”, that is, “evaluative feelings of pro or con, favorable or unfavorable, with regard to particular objects” (where the objects may be “concrete representations of things or actions, or abstract concepts”; Insko & Schopler 1967: 361–362). As such, the concept of attitude is quite broad: it includes normative beliefs, as well as personal opinions and preferences. That said, a series of field experiments has provided evidence contrary to the assumption that attitudes and behaviors are closely related. LaPiere (1934) famously reported a sharp divergence between the widespread anti-Chinese attitudes in the United States and the tolerant behavior he witnessed. Other studies have pointed to inconsistencies between an individual’s stated normative beliefs and her actions (Wicker 1969): several reasons may account for such a discrepancy. For example, studies of racial prejudice indicate that normative beliefs are more likely to determine behavior in long-lasting relationships, and least likely to determine behavior in the transient situations typical of experimental studies (Harding et al. 1954 [1969]; Gaertner & Dovidio 1986). Warner and DeFleur (1969) reported that the main variable affecting discriminatory behavior is one’s belief about what society (e.g., most other people) says one should do, as opposed to what one personally thinks one should do.

In brief, the social psychology literature provides mixed evidence in support of the claim that an individual’s normative beliefs and attitudes influence her actions. Such studies, however, do not carefully discriminate among various types of normative beliefs. In particular, one should distinguish between “personal normative beliefs” (i.e., beliefs that a certain behavior ought to be followed) and “normative expectations” (i.e., what one believes others believe ought to be done, that is, a second-order belief): it then becomes apparent that oftentimes only such second-order beliefs affect behavior.

The above constitutes an important criticism of the socialized actor theory. According to Parsons, once a norm is internalized, members of society are motivated to conform by an internal sanctioning system; therefore, one should observe a high correlation among all orders of normative beliefs and behavior. However, experimental evidence does not support such a view (see also: Fishbein 1967; Cialdini et al. 1991). Another indication that the socialized actor theory lacks generality is the observation that norms can change rather quickly, and that new norms often emerge in a short period of time among complete strangers (Mackie 1996). Long-term or close interactions do not seem to be necessary for someone to acquire a given normative disposition, as is testified by the relative ease with which individuals learn new norms when they change status or group (e.g., from single to married, from student to faculty, etc.). Moreover, studies of emergent social and political groups have shown that new norms may form rather rapidly, and that the demise of old patterns of behavior is often abrupt (Robinson 1932; Klassen et al. 1989; Prentice & Miller 1993; Matza 1964). Given the aforementioned limitations, Parsons’ theory might perhaps be taken as an explanation of a particular conception of moral norms (in the sense of internalized, unconditional imperatives), but it cannot be viewed as a general theory of social norms.

It has been argued that behavior is often closely embedded in a network of personal relations, and that a theory of norms should not leave the specific social context out of consideration (Granovetter 1985). Critics of the socialized actor theory have called for an alternative conception of norms that may account for the often weak relation between beliefs and behavior (Deutscher 1973). This alternative approach takes social relations to be crucial in explaining social action, and considers social identity as a key motivating factor. (A strong support for this view among anthropologists is to be found in the work of Cancian 1975.)

Since the notion of social identity is inextricably linked to that of group behavior, it is important to clarify the relation between these concepts. By “social identity” we refer, in Tajfel’s own words, to

that part of an individual’s self-concept which derives from his knowledge of his membership of a social group (or groups) together with the value and emotional significance attached to that membership. (Tajfel 1981: 255)

Note that a crucial feature of social identity is that one’s identification with the group is in some sense a conscious choice: one may accidentally belong to a group, but we can meaningfully talk of social identification only when being a group-member becomes (at least in part) constitutive of who one is. According to Tajfel’s theory, when we categorize ourselves as belonging to a particular group, the perception and definition of the self—as well as our motives—change. That is, we start perceiving ourselves and our fellow group-members along impersonal, “typical” dimensions that characterize the group to which we belong. Such dimensions include specific roles and the beliefs (or actions) that accompany them.

Turner et al.’s (1987) “self-categorization theory” provides a more specific characterization of self-perception, or self-definition, as a system of cognitive self-schemata that filter and process information. Such schemata result in a representation of the social situation that guides the choice of appropriate action. This system has at least two major components, i.e., social and personal identity. Social identity refers to self-descriptions related to group memberships. Personal identity refers to self-descriptions such as individual character traits, abilities, and tastes. Although personal and social identities are mutually exclusive levels of self-definition, this distinction must be taken as an approximation (in that there are many interconnections between social and personal identities). It is, however, important to recognize that we often perceive ourselves primarily in terms of our relevant group memberships rather than as differentiated, unique individuals. So—depending on the situation—personal or group identity will become salient (Brewer 1991).

For example, when one makes interpersonal comparisons between oneself and other group-members, personal identity will become salient; instead, group identity will become salient in situations in which one’s group is compared to another group. Within a group, all those factors that lead members to categorize themselves as different (or endowed with special characteristics and traits) will enhance personal identity. If a group has to solve a common task, but each member is to be rewarded according to her contribution, personal abilities are highlighted and individuals will perceive themselves as unique and different from the rest of the group. Conversely, if all group-members are to equally share the reward for a jointly performed task, group identification will be enhanced. When the difference between self and fellow group-members is accentuated, we are likely to observe selfish motives and self-favoritism against other group-members. When instead group identification is enhanced, in-group favoritism against out-group members will be activated, as well as behavior contrary to self-interest.

According to Turner, social identity is basically a cognitive mechanism whose adaptive function is to make “group behavior” possible. Whenever social identification becomes salient, a cognitive mechanism of categorization is activated in such a way to produce perceptual and behavioral changes. Such categorization is called a stereotype, the prototypical description of what members of a given category are (or are believed to be). It is a cluster of physical, mental and psychological characteristics attributed to a “typical” member of a given group. Stereotyping, like any other categorization process, activates scripts or schemata, and what we call group behavior is nothing but scripted behavior. For example, the category “Asian student” is associated with a cluster of behaviors, personality traits, and values: we often think of Asian students as respectful, diligent, disciplined, and especially good with technical subjects. When thinking of an Asian student solely in terms of group membership, we attribute her the stereotypical characteristics associated with her group, so she becomes interchangeable with other group-members. When we perceive people in terms of stereotypes, we depersonalize them and see them as “typical” members of their group. The same process is at work when we perceive ourselves as group-members: self-stereotyping is a cognitive shift from “perceiving oneself as unique” to “perceiving oneself in terms of the attributes that characterize the group”. It is this cognitive shift that mediates group behavior.

Group behavior (as opposed to individual behavior) is characterized by features such as a perceived similarity between group-members, cohesiveness, a tendency to cooperate to achieve common goals, shared attitudes or beliefs, and conformity to group norms. Once an individual self-categorizes as member of a group, she will perceive herself as “depersonalized” and similar to other group-members in the relevant stereotypical dimensions. Insofar as group-members perceive their interests and goals as identical—because such interests and goals are stereotypical attributes of the group—self-stereotyping will induce a group-member to embrace such interests and goals as her own. It is thus predicted that pro-social behavior will be enhanced by group membership, and diluted when people act in an individualistic mode (Brewer 1979).

The groups with which we happen to identify ourselves may be very large (as in the case in which one self-defines as Muslim or French), or as small as a friends’ group. Some general group identities may not involve specific norms, but there are many cases in which group identification and social norms are inextricably connected. In that case group-members believe that certain patterns of behavior are unique to them, and use their distinctive norms to define group membership. Many close-knit groups (such as the Amish or the Hasidic Jews) enforce norms of separation proscribing marriage with outsiders, as well as specific dress codes and a host of other prescriptive and proscriptive norms. There, once an individual perceives herself as a group-member, she will adhere to the group prototype and behave in accordance with it. Hogg and Turner (1987) have called the process through which individuals come to conform to group norms “referent informational influence”.

Group-specific norms have (among other things) the twofold function of minimizing perceived differences among group-members and maximizing differences between the group and outsiders. Once formed, such norms become stable cognitive representations of appropriate behavior as a group-member. Social identity is built around group characteristics and behavioral standards, and hence any perceived lack of conformity to group norms is seen as a threat to the legitimacy of the group. Self-categorization accentuates the similarities between one’s behavior and that prescribed by the group norm, thus causing conformity as well as the disposition to control and punish transgressors. In the social identity framework, group norms are obeyed because one identifies with the group, and conformity is mediated by self-categorization as an in-group member. A telling historical example of the relationship between norms and group membership was the division of England into the two parties of the Roundheads and Cavaliers. Charles Mackay reports that

in those days every species of vice and iniquity was thought by the Puritans to lurk in the long curly tresses of the monarchists, while the latter imagined that their opponents were as destitute of wit, of wisdom, and of virtue, as they were of hair. A man’s locks were a symbol of his creed, both in politics and religion. The more abundant the hair, the more scant the faith; and the balder the head, the more sincere the piety. (Mackay 1841: 351)

It should be noted that in this framework social norms are defined by collective—as opposed to personal—beliefs about appropriate behaviors (Homans 1950, 1961). To a certain extent, this characterization of social norms is closer to recent accounts than it is to Parsons’ socialized actor theory. On the other hand, a distinct feature of the social identity framework is that people’s motivation to conform comes from their desire to validate their identity as group-members. In short, there are several empirical predictions one can draw from such a framework. Given the theory’s emphasis on identity as a motivating factor, conformity to a norm is not assumed to depend on an individual’s internalization of that norm; in fact, a change in social status or group membership will bring about a change in the norms relevant to the new status/group. Thus a new norm can be quickly adopted without much interaction, and beliefs about identity validation may change very rapidly under the pressure of external circumstances. In this case, not just norm compliance, but norms themselves are potentially unstable.

The experimental literature on social dilemmas has utilized the “priming of group identity” as a mechanism for promoting cooperative behavior (Dawes 1980; Brewer & Schneider 1990). The typical hypothesis is that a pre-play, face-to-face communication stage may induce identification with the group, and thus promote cooperative behavior among group-members. In effect, rates of cooperation have been shown to be generally higher in social dilemma experiments preceded by a pre-play communication stage (Dawes 1991). However, it has been argued that face-to-face communication may actually help group-members gather relevant information about one another: such information may therefore induce subjects to trust each other’s promises and act cooperatively, regardless of any group identification. In this respect, it has been shown that communication per se does not foster cooperation, unless subjects are allowed to talk about relevant topics (Bicchieri & Lev-On 2007). This provides support for the view that communication does not enhance cohesion but rather focuses subjects on relevant rules of behavior, which do not necessarily depend on group identification.

Cooperative outcomes can thus be explained without resorting to the concept of social identity. A social identity explanation appears to be more appropriate in the context of a relatively stable environment, where individuals have had time to make emotional investments (or at least can expect repeated future interactions within the same group). In artificial lab settings, where there are no expectations of future interactions, the concept of social identity seems less persuasive as an explanation of the observed rates of cooperation. On the other hand, we note that social identity does appear to play a role in experimental settings in which participants are divided into separate groups. (In that case, it has been shown that participants categorize the situation as “we versus them”, activating in-group loyalty and trust, and an equal degree of mistrust toward the out-group; Kramer & Brewer 1984; Bornstein & Ben-Yossef 1994.)

Even with stable environments and repeated interactions, however, a theory of norm compliance in terms of social identity cannot avoid the difficulty of making predictions when one is simultaneously committed to different identities. We may concurrently be workers, parents, spouses, friends, club members, and party affiliates, to name but a few of the possible identities we embrace. For each of them there are rules that define what is appropriate, acceptable, or good behavior. In the social identity framework, however, it is not clear what happens when one is committed to different identities that may involve conflicting behaviors.

Finally, there is ample evidence that people’s perceptions may change very rapidly. Since in this framework norms are defined as shared perceptions about group beliefs, one would expect that—whenever all members of a group happen to believe that others have changed their beliefs about core membership rules—the very norms that define membership will change. The study of fashion, fads and speculative bubbles clearly shows that there are some domains in which rapid (and possibly disruptive) changes of collective expectations may occur; it is, however, much less clear what sort of norms are more likely to be subject to rapid changes (think of dress codes rather than codes of honor). The social identity view does not offer a theoretical framework for differentiating these cases: although some norms are indeed related to group membership, and thus compliance may be explained through identity-validation mechanisms, there appear to be limits to the social identity explanation.

Early rational choice models of conformity maintained that, since norms are upheld by sanctions, compliance is merely a payoff-maximizing strategy (Rommetveit 1955; Thibaut & Kelley 1959): when others’ approval and disapproval act as external sanctions, we have a “cost-benefit model” of compliance (Axelrod 1986; James Coleman 1990). Rule-complying strategies are rationally chosen in order to avoid negative sanctions or to attract positive sanctions. This class of rational choice models defines norms behaviorally, equating them with patterns of behavior (while disregarding expectations or values). Such approach relies heavily on sanctions as a motivating factor. According to Axelrod (1986), for example, if we observe individuals to follow a regular pattern of behavior and to be punished if they act otherwise, then we have a norm. Similarly, Coleman (1990) argues that a norm coincides with a set of sanctions that act to direct a given behavior.

However, it has been shown that not all social norms involve sanctions (Diamond 1935; Hoebel 1954). Moreover, sanctioning works generally well in small groups and in the context of repeated interactions, where the identity of participants is known and monitoring is relatively easy. Still, even in such cases there may be a so-called second-order public goods problem. That is, imposing negative sanctions on transgressors is in everybody’s interest, but the individual who observes a transgression faces a dilemma: she is to decide whether or not to punish the transgressor, where punishing typically involves costs; besides, there is no guarantee that other individuals will also impose a penalty on transgressors when faced with the same dilemma. An answer to this problem has been to assume that there exist “meta-norms” that tell people to punish transgressors of lower-level norms (Axelrod 1986). This solution, however, only shifts the problem one level up: upholding the meta-norm itself requires the existence of a higher-level sanctioning system.

Another problem with sanctions is the following: a sanction, to be effective, must be recognized as such. Coleman and Axelrod typically take the repeated prisoner’s dilemma game as an example of the working of sanctions. However, in a repeated prisoner’s dilemma the same action (“C” or “D”) must serve as both the sanctioning action and the target action. By simply looking at behavior, it is unclear whether the action is a function of a sanction or a sanction itself. It thus becomes difficult to determine the presence of a norm, or to assess its effect on choice as distinct from the individual strategies of players.

A further consideration weakens the credibility of the view that norms are upheld only because of external sanctions. Often we keep conforming to a norm even in situations of complete anonymity, where the probability of being caught transgressing is almost zero. In this case fear of sanctions cannot be a motivating force. As a consequence, it is often argued that cases of “spontaneous” compliance are the result of internalization (Scott 1971): people who have developed an internal sanctioning system feel guilt and shame at behaving in a deviant way. Yet, we have seen that the Parsonian view of internalization and socialization is inadequate, as it leads to predictions about compliance that often run counter to empirical evidence.

In particular, James Coleman (1990) has argued in favor of reducing internalization to rational choice, insofar as it is in the interest of a group to get another group to internalize certain norms. In this case internalization would still be the result of some form of socialization. This theory faces some of the same objections raised against Parsons’ theory: norms that are passed on from parents to children, for example, should be extremely resistant to change; hence, one should expect a high degree of correlation between such norms and behavior, especially in those cases where norms prescribe specific kinds of actions. However, studies of normative beliefs about honesty—which one typically acquires during childhood—show that such beliefs are often uncorrelated with behavior (Freeman & Ataöv 1960).

Bicchieri (1990, 1997) has presented a third, alternative view about internalization. This view of internalization is cognitive, and is grounded on the assumption that social norms develop in small, close-knit groups where ongoing interactions are the rule. Once an individual has learned to behave in a way consistent with the group’s interests, she will tend to persist in the learned behavior unless it becomes clear that—on average—the cost of upholding the norm significantly outweighs the benefits. Small groups can typically monitor their members’ behavior and successfully employ retaliation whenever free-riding is observed. In such groups an individual will learn, maybe at some personal cost, to cooperate; she will then uphold the cooperative norm as a “default rule” in any new encounter, unless it becomes evident that the cost of conformity has become excessive. The idea that norms may be “sluggish” is in line with well-known results from cognitive psychology showing that, once a norm has emerged in a group, it will tend to guide the behavior of its members even when they face a new situation (or are isolated from the original group; Sherif 1936).

Empirical evidence shows that norm-abiding behavior is not, as the early rational choice models would have it, a matter of cost/benefit calculation. Upholding a norm that has led one to fare reasonably well in the past is a way of economizing on the effort one would have to exert to devise a strategy when facing a new situation . This kind of “bounded rationality” approach explains why people tend to obey norms that sometimes put them at a disadvantage, as is the case with norms of honesty. This does not mean, however, that external sanctions never play a role in compliance: for example, in the initial development of a norm sanctions may indeed play an important role. Yet, once a norm is established, there are several mechanisms that may account for conformity.

Finally, the view that one conforms only because of the threat of negative sanctions does not distinguish norm-abiding behavior from an obsession or an entrenched habit; nor does that view distinguish social norms from hypothetical imperatives enforced by sanctions (such as the rule that prohibits naked sunbathing on public beaches). In these cases avoidance of the sanctions associated with transgressions constitutes a decisive reason to conform, independently of what others do. In fact, in the traditional rational choice perspective, the only expectations that matter are those about the sanctions that follow compliance or non-compliance. In those frameworks, beliefs about how other people will act—as opposed to what they expect us to do—are not a relevant explanatory variable: however, this leads to predictions about norm compliance that often run counter to empirical evidence.

The traditional rational choice model of compliance depicts the individual as facing a decision problem in isolation: if there are sanctions for non-compliance, the individual will calculate the benefit of transgression against the cost of norm compliance, and eventually choose so as to maximize her expected utility. Individuals, however, seldom choose in isolation: they know the outcome of their choice will depend on the actions and beliefs of other individuals. Game theory provides a formal framework for modeling strategic interactions.

Thomas Schelling (1960), David Lewis (1969), Edna Ullmann-Margalit (1977), Robert Sugden (1986) and, more recently, Peyton Young (1993), Cristina Bicchieri (1993), and Peter Vanderschraaf (1995) have proposed a game-theoretic account according to which a norm is broadly defined as an equilibrium of a strategic interaction. In particular, a Nash equilibrium is a combination of strategies (one for each individual), such that each individual’s strategy is a best reply to the others’ strategies. Since it is an equilibrium, a norm is supported by self-fulfilling expectations in the sense that players’ beliefs are consistent, and thus the actions that follow from players’ beliefs will validate those very beliefs. Characterizing social norms as equilibria has the advantage of emphasizing the role that expectations play in upholding norms. On the other hand, this interpretation of social norms does not prima facie explain why people prefer to conform if they expect others to conform.

Take for example conventions such as putting the fork to the left of the plate, adopting a dress code, or using a particular sign language. In all these cases, my choice to follow a certain rule is conditional upon expecting most other people to follow it. Once my expectation is met, I have every reason to adopt the rule in question. In fact, if I do not use the sign language everybody else uses, I will not be able to communicate. It is in my immediate interest to follow the convention, since my main goal is to coordinate with other people. In the case of conventions, there is a continuity between the individual’s self-interest and the interests of the community that supports the convention. This is the reason why David Lewis models conventions as equilibria of coordination games . Such games have multiple equilibria, but once one of them has been established, players will have every incentive to keep playing it (as any deviation will be costly).

Take instead a norm of cooperation. In this case, the expectation that almost everyone abides by it may not be sufficient to induce compliance. If everyone is expected to cooperate one may be tempted, if unmonitored, to behave in the opposite way. The point is that conforming to social norms , as opposed to conventions, is almost never in the immediate interest of the individual. Often there is a discontinuity between the individual’s self-interest and the interests of the community that supports the social norm.

The typical game in which following a norm would provide a better solution (than the one attained by self-centered agents) is a mixed-motive game such as the prisoner’s dilemma or the trust game. In such games the unique Nash equilibrium represents a suboptimal outcome. It should be stressed that—whereas a convention is one among several equilibria of a coordination game—a social norm can never be an equilibrium of a mixed-motive game. However, Bicchieri (2006) has argued that when a norm exists it transforms the original mixed-motive game into a coordination one. As an example, consider the following prisoner’s dilemma game ( Figure 1 ), where the payoffs are B=Best, S=Second, T=Third, and W=Worst. Clearly the only Nash equilibrium is to defect (D), in which case both players get (T,T), a suboptimal outcome. Suppose, however, that society has developed a norm of cooperation; that is, whenever a social dilemma occurs, it is commonly understood that the parties should privilege a cooperative attitude. Should, however, does not imply “will”, therefore the new game generated by the existence of the cooperative norm has two equilibria: either both players defect or both cooperate.

Note that, in the new coordination game (which was created by the existence of the cooperative norm), the payoffs are quite different from those of the original prisoner’s dilemma. Thus there are two equilibria: if both players follow the cooperative norm they will play an optimal equilibrium and get (B,B), whereas if they both choose to defect they will get the suboptimal outcome (S,S). Players’ payoffs in the new coordination game differ from the original payoffs because their preferences and beliefs will reflect the existence of the norm. More specifically, if a player knows that a cooperative norm exists and has the right kind of expectations, then she will have a preference to conform to the norm in a situation in which she can choose to cooperate or to defect. In the new game generated by the norm’s existence, choosing to defect when others cooperate is not a good choice anymore (T,W). To understand why, let us look more closely to the preferences and expectations that underlie the conditional choice to conform to a social norm.

Bicchieri (2006) defines the expectations that underlie norm compliance, as follows:

Note that universal compliance is not usually needed for a norm to exist. However, how much deviance is socially tolerable will depend on the norm in question. Group norms and well-entrenched social norms will typically be followed by almost all members of a group or population, whereas greater deviance is usually accepted when norms are new or they are not deemed to be socially important. Furthermore, as it is usually unclear how many people follow a norm, different individuals may have different beliefs about the size of the group of followers, and may also have different thresholds for what “sufficiently large” means. What matters to conformity is that an individual believes that her threshold has been reached or surpassed. For a critical assessment of the above definition of norm-driven preferences, see Hausman (2008).

Brennan et al. (2013) also argue that norms of all kinds share in an essential structure. Norms are clusters of normative attitudes in a group, combined with the knowledge that such a cluster of attitudes exists. On their account, “A normative principle P is a norm within a group G if and only if:

  • A significant proportion of the members of G have P -corresponding normative attitudes; and
  • A significant proportion of the members of G know that a significant proportion of the members of G have P -corresponding attitudes” (Brennan et al. 2013: 29)

On this account, a “ P -corresponding normative attitude” is understood to be a judgment, emotional state, expectation, or other properly first personal normative belief that supports the principle P (e.g., Alice thinking most people should P would count as a normative attitude). Condition (i) is meant to reflect genuine first personal normative commitments, attitudes or beliefs. Condition (ii) is meant to capture those cases where individuals know that a large part of their group also shares in those attitudes. Putting conditions (i) and (ii) together offers a picture that the authors argue allows for explanatory work to be done on a social-level normative concept while remaining grounded in individual-level attitudes.

Consider again the new coordination game of Figure 1 : for players to obey the norm, and thus choose C, it must be the case that each expects the other to follow it. In the original prisoner’s dilemma, empirical beliefs would not be sufficient to induce cooperative behavior. When a norm exists, however, players also believe that others believe they should obey the norm, and may even punish them if they do not. The combined force of empirical and normative expectations makes norm conformity a compelling choice, be it because punishment may follow or just because one recognizes the legitimacy of others’ expectations (Sugden 2000).

It is important to understand that conformity to a social norm is always conditional on the expectations of what the relevant other/s will do. We prefer to comply with the norm as we have certain expectations. To make this point clear, think of the player who is facing a typical one-shot prisoner’s dilemma with an unknown opponent. Suppose the player knows a norm of cooperation exists and is generally followed, but she is uncertain as to whether the opponent is a norm-follower. In this case the player is facing the following situation ( Figure 2 ).

With probability p , the opponent is a norm-following type, and with probability \(1 - p\) she is not. According to Bicchieri, conditional preferences imply that having a reason to be fair, reciprocate or cooperate in a given situation does not entail having any general motive or disposition to be fair, reciprocate or cooperate as such. Having conditional preferences means that one may follow a norm in the presence of the relevant expectations, but disregard it in its absence. Whether a norm is followed at a given time depends on the actual proportion of followers, on the expectations of conditional followers about such proportion, and on the combination of individual thresholds.

As an example, consider a community that abides by strict norms of honesty. A person who, upon entering the community, systematically violates these norms will certainly be met with hostility, if not utterly excluded from the group. But suppose that a large group of thieves makes its way into this community. In due time, people would cease to expect honesty on the part of others, and would find no reason to be honest themselves in a world overtaken by crime. In this case, probably norms of honesty would cease to exist, as the strength of a norm lies in its being followed by many of the members of the relevant group (which in turn reinforces people’s expectations of conformity).

What we have discussed is a “rational reconstruction” of what a social norm is. Such a reconstruction is meant to capture some essential features of norm-driven behavior; also, this analysis helps us distinguish social norms from other constructs such as conventions or personal norms. A limit of this account, however, is that it does not indicate how such equilibria are attained or, in other terms, how expectations become self-fulfilling.

While neoclassical economics and game theory traditionally conceived of institutions as exogenous constraints, research in political economy has generated new insights into the study of endogenous institutions . Specifically, endogenous norms have been shown to restrict the individual’s action set and drive preferences over action profiles (Bowles 1998; Ostrom 2000). As a result, the “standard” economic framework positing exogenous (and in particular self-centered) preferences has come under scrutiny. Widely documented deviations from the predictions of models with self-centered agents have informed alternative accounts of individual choice (for one of the first models of “interdependent preferences”, see Stigler & Becker 1977).

Some alternative accounts have helped reconcile insights about norm-driven behavior with instrumental rationality (Elster 1989b). Moreover, they have contributed to informing the design of laboratory experiments on non-standard preferences (for a survey of early experiments, see Ledyard 1995; more recent experiments are reviewed by Fehr & Schmidt 2006 and Kagel & Roth 2016). In turn, experimental findings have inspired the formulation of a wide range of models aiming to rationalize the behavior observed in the lab (Camerer 2003; Dhami 2016).

It has been argued that the upholding of social norms could simply be modeled as the optimization of a utility function that includes the others’ welfare as an argument. For instance, consider some of the early “social preference” theories, such as Bolton and Ockenfels’ (2000) or Fehr and Schmidt’s (1999) models of inequity aversion. These frameworks can explain a good wealth of evidence on preferences for equitable income distributions; they cannot however account for conditional preferences like those reflecting principles of reciprocity (e.g., I will keep the common bathroom clean, if I believe my roommates do the same). As noted above, the approach to social norms taken by philosophically-inclined scholars has emphasized the importance of conditional preferences in supporting social norms. In this connection, we note that some of the social preference theories do account for motivations conditional on empirical beliefs, whereby a player upholds a principle of “fair” behavior if she believes her co-players will uphold it too (Rabin 1993; Dufwenberg & Kirchsteiger 2004; Falk & Fischbacher 2006; Charness & Rabin 2002). These theories presuppose that players are hardwired with a notion of fair or kind behavior, as exogenously defined by the theorist. Since they implicitly assume that all players have internalized a unique—exogenous—normative standpoint (as reflected in some notion of fairness or kindness), these theories do not explicitly model normative expectations. Hence, players’ preferences are assumed to be conditional solely on their empirical beliefs; that is, preferences are conditional on whether others will behave fairly (according to an exogenous principle) or not.

That said, we stress that social preferences should not be conflated with social norms. Social preferences capture stable dispositions toward an exogenously defined principle of conduct (Binmore 2010). By contrast, social norms are better studied as group-specific solutions to strategic problems (Sugden 1986; Bicchieri 1993; Young 1998b). Such solutions are brought about by a particular class of preferences (“norm-driven preferences”), conditional on the relevant set of empirical beliefs and normative expectations. In fact, we stress that “what constitutes fair or appropriate behavior” often varies with cultural or situational factors (Henrich et al. 2001; Cappelen et al. 2007; Ellingsen et al. 2012). Accounting for endogenous expectations is therefore key to a full understanding of social norms.

Relatedly, Guala (2016) offers a game-theoretic account of institutions, arguing that institutions are sets of rules in equilibrium. Guala’s view incorporates insights from two competing accounts of institutions: institutions-as-rules (perhaps best rendered by North 1990), and institutions-as-equilibria. From the first account, he captures the idea that institutions create rules that help to guide our behaviors and reduce uncertainty. With rules in place, we more or less know what to do, even in new situations. From the second, he captures the idea that institutions are solutions to coordination problems that arise from our normal interactions. The institutions give us reasons to follow them. The function of the rules, then, is to point to actions that promote coordination and cooperation. Because of the equilibrium nature of the rules, each individual has an incentive to choose those actions, provided others do too. Guala relies on a correlated equilibrium concept to unite the rules and equilibria accounts. On this picture, an institution is simply a correlated equilibrium in a game, where other correlated equilibria would have been possible.

Thrasher (2018) offers a comparative-functional analysis of norms that broadly aligns with the Bicchieri (2006) framework to help understand the durability of “bad norms.” Abbink et al. (2017) use public goods-like experiments to show how peer punishment can hold inefficient norms in place. This general framework can be helpful to understand why duels and honor killings can become stable (e.g. Thrasher and Handfield 2018, Handfield and Thrasher 2019). This work explores the signaling function of socially costly norms.

An alternative class of models explains norm compliance in terms of social image or self-image concerns (e.g., Andreoni and Bernheim 2009; Bénabou and Tirole 2006, 2011). These models assume that one tries to signal (to others or to one’s future self) that one has good “personal traits”, with such type-specific traits being imperfectly observed. More precisely, Bénabou and Tirole (2006) model the individual’s utility from contributing to a public good as a function of (i) material payoffs, (ii) intrinsic rewards from behaving altruistically, and (iii) reputational returns; in particular, the authors assume that reputational returns depend on the observers’ posterior expectations of the individual’s type. Bénabou and Tirole then consider (a refinement of) signaling equilibria, thereby allowing for multiple solutions to occur as a result of the interplay of individual motivations and of the level of observability of the actions. While models with reputational concerns do not explicitly define normative expectations, they generally posit that players care about their reputation under the assumption that acting altruistically is good or appropriate. Looking ahead, there is still work to do to fully formalize the interplay of (endogenous) normative expectations and empirical beliefs within a general model that is applicable to any game setting. Such a model should probably build on the “psychological game theory” framework (for discussion, see Battigalli and Dufwenberg 2022, p. 857; see also Bicchieri and Sontuoso 2015).

In what follows we focus on lab experiments that identify social norms by explicitly measuring both empirical and normative expectations.

Xiao and Bicchieri (2010) designed an experiment to investigate the impact on trust games of two potentially applicable—but conflicting—principles of conduct, namely, equality and reciprocity . Note that the former can be broadly defined as a rule that recommends minimizing payoff differences, whereas the latter recommends taking a similar action as others (regardless of payoff considerations). The experimental design involved two trust game variants: in the first one, players started with equal endowments; in the second one, the investor was endowed with twice the money that the trustee was given. In both cases, the investor could choose to transfer a preset amount of money to the trustee or keep it all. Upon receiving the money, the trustee could in turn keep it or else transfer back some of it to the investor: in the equal endowment condition (“baseline treatment”), both equality and reciprocity dictate that the trustee transfer some money back to the investor; by contrast, in the unequal endowment condition (“asymmetry treatment”), equality and reciprocity dictate different actions as the trustee could guarantee payoff equality only by making a zero back-transfer. Xiao and Bicchieri elicited subjects’ first- and second-order empirical beliefs (“how much do you think other participants in your role will transfer to their counterpart?”; “what does your counterpart think you will do?”) and normative expectations (“how much do you think your counterpart believes you should transfer to her?”). The experimental results show that a majority of trustees returned a positive amount whenever reciprocity would reduce payoff inequality (in the baseline treatment); by contrast, a majority of trustees did not reciprocate the investors’ transfer when doing so would increase payoff inequality (in the asymmetry treatment). Moreover, investors correctly believed that less money would be returned in the asymmetry treatment than in the baseline treatment, and most trustees correctly estimated investors’ beliefs in both treatments. However, in the asymmetry treatment empirical beliefs and normative expectations conflicted: this highlights that, when there is ambiguity as to which principle of conduct is in place, each subject will support the rule of behavior that favors her most.

Reuben and Riedl (2013) examine the enforcement of norms of contribution to public goods in homogeneous and heterogeneous groups, such as groups whose members vary in their endowment, contribution capacity, or marginal benefits. In particular, Reuben and Riedl are interested in the normative appeal of two potentially applicable rules: the efficiency rule (prescribing maximal contributions by all) and the class of relative contribution rules (prescribing a contribution that is “fair” relative to the contributions of others; e.g., equality and equity rules). Reuben and Riedl’s results show that, in the absence of punishment, no positive contribution norm emerged and all groups converged toward free-riding. By contrast, with punishment, contributions were consistent with the prescriptions of the efficiency rule in a significant subset of groups (irrespective of the type of group heterogeneity); in other groups, contributions were consistent with relative contribution rules. These results suggest that even in heterogeneous groups individuals can successfully enforce a contribution norm. Most notably, survey data involving third parties confirmed well-defined yet conflicting normative views about the aforementioned contribution rules; in other words, both efficiency and relative contribution rules are normatively appealing, and are indeed potential candidates for emerging contribution norms in different groups.

Bicchieri and Chavez (2010) designed an experiment to investigate norm compliance in ultimatum games. Specifically, their experiment involved a variant of the ultimatum game whereby the proposer could choose one of the following three options: ($5, $5) , ($8, $2) , or Coin (in which case one of the other two allocations would be selected at random). This design allows for two plausible notions of fairness: as an equal outcome ($5, $5) or as a fair procedure (Coin). The experimenters elicited subjects’ normative expectations about the actions they thought would be considered fair by most participants: proposers and responders showed a remarkable degree of agreement in their notions of fairness, as most subjects believed that a majority of participants deemed both ($5, $5) and Coin to be appropriate. Further, the experimenters had subjects play three instances of the above ultimatum game under different information conditions. In the “full information” condition, all participants knew that the Coin option was available, and that responders would know if their respective proposer had chosen Coin. In the “private information” condition, responders did not know that Coin was available to proposers, and proposers were aware of responders’ ignorance. In the “limited information” condition, participants knew that the Coin option was available, but responders would not be able to distinguish whether their respective proposer had implemented one of the two allocations directly or had chosen Coin instead. The experimental results show that when normative expectations supporting the Coin option were either absent (in the private condition) or could be defied without consequence (in the limited condition), the frequency of choice of ($5, $5) and ($8, $2), respectively, were considerably higher than those of Coin. Moreover, the frequency of Coin choices was highest in the public information condition, where such option was common knowledge and its outcome transparent: this shows that there proposers followed the rule of behavior that favored them most, and that such a rule was effectively a social norm. On the other hand, substantial norm evasion characterized proposers’ behavior in the limited information condition, where ($8, $2) was the most frequent choice.

In a subsequent study, Chavez and Bicchieri (2013) measured empirical and normative expectations (as well as behavior) of third parties who were given the opportunity to add to or deduct from the payoffs of subjects who had participated in an ultimatum game. Third parties tended to reward subjects involved in equal allocations and to compensate victims of unfair allocations (rather than punish unfair behavior); on the other hand, third parties were willing to punish when compensation was not an available option. The experimental results further show that third parties shared a notion of fairness (as indicated by their normative expectations), and that such notion was sensitive to contextual differences.

Krupka and Weber (2013) introduced an interesting procedure for identifying social norms by means of pre-play coordination games. In brief, using alternative (between-subjects) variants of the dictator game, Krupka and Weber had participants assess the extent to which different actions were collectively perceived as socially appropriate: subjects providing these ratings effectively faced a coordination game, as they were incentivized to match the modal response given by others in the same situation (such a pre-play coordination game was intended to verify the presence of shared normative expectations). Krupka and Weber went on to use these elicited assessments to predict other subjects’ compliance with the relevant social norm in each dictator game variant (for another application of the same elicitation procedure, see Gächter et al. 2013).

Similarly, Schram and Charness’ (2015) proposed a procedure for inducing a shared understanding of the relevant rule of behavior, in the lab. In short, Schram and Charness had participants in dictator games receive advice from a group of third parties. The information received simply revealed what a group of uninvolved subjects thought dictators ought to do : as such, the information received generated an exogenous variation in the dictators’ normative expectations. Schram and Charness’ results show that choices are indeed affected by this information.

Bicchieri and Xiao (2009) designed an experiment to investigate what happens when empirical and normative expectations conflict. To that end, participants in a dictator game were exposed to different pieces of information. Specifically, two groups of dictators were given some “descriptive information”; that is, they were told what other subjects had done in another session (i.e., one group was told that previous participants had made for the most part a generous offer, while the other group was told that most participants had made a selfish offer). Further, another two groups of dictators were given some “normative information”; that is, they were told what previous subjects said ought to be done (i.e., one group was told that most previous participants thought that one should make a generous offer, while the other group was told that most participants thought that one should make a selfish offer). Other groups were given both descriptive and normative information. The experimental results show that—whenever such information did not conflict—both descriptive and normative messages had a significant influence on dictators’ own expectations and subsequent choices. When messages conflicted in that one indicated generosity and the other indicated selfishness, only the descriptive information affected dictators’ behavior. This suggests that if people recognize that others are breaching the norm, then they will no longer feel compelled to follow the relevant rule of behavior themselves.

To conclude, the studies surveyed here provide evidence of the role played by expectations in affecting behavior in a variety of social dilemmas. In this regard, we note that in contrast to the vast literature on empirical beliefs, the number of lab studies that directly measure normative expectations is relatively limited: more research is clearly needed to investigate the interplay of empirical and normative information about applicable rules of behavior.

Thus far we have examined accounts of social norms that take for granted that a particular norm exists in a population. However, for a full account of social norms, we must answer two questions related to the dynamics of norms. First, we must ask how a norm can emerge. Norms require a set of corresponding beliefs and expectations to support them, and so there must be an account of how these arise. Second, we must investigate the conditions under which a norm is stable under some competitive pressure from other norms. Sometimes, multiple candidate norms vie for dominance in a population. Even if one norm has come to dominate the population, new norms can try to “invade” the existing norm’s population of adherents.

Let us now turn to the question of norm emergence. Here we can see three classes of models: first, a purely biological approach, second, a more cognitive approach, and third, a structured interactions approach. The most famous of the biological approaches to norms seek to explain cooperative behavior. The simplest models are kin selection models (Hamilton 1964). These models seek to explain altruistic tendencies in animals by claiming that, as selection acts on genes, those genes have an incentive to promote the reproductive success of other identical sets of genes found in other animals. This mode of explanation can provide an account of why we see cooperative behaviors within families, but being gene-centered, cannot explain cooperative behavior toward strangers (as strangers should not be sufficiently genetically related to merit altruistic behavior).

Models of “reciprocal altruism” (Trivers 1971, 1985), on the other hand, tell us that cooperative behavior has no chance of evolving in random pairings, but will evolve in a social framework in which individuals can benefit from building reputations for being nice guys. Reciprocal altruism, however, does not require an evolutionary argument; a simple model of learning in ongoing close-knit groups will do, and has the further advantage of explaining why certain types of cooperative behavior are more likely to emerge than others. All that matters in these models is that agents can properly identify other agents, such that they can maintain a record of their past behavior. This allows for the possibility of reputations: people who have the reputation of being cooperative will be treated cooperatively, and those who have a reputation of being unfair will be treated unfairly.

A variation on the idea of reciprocal altruism can be seen in Axelrod (1986). Axelrod presents a “norms game” in which agents probabilistically choose to comply with the norm, or deviate from it, and then other agents can probabilistically choose to punish any deviations at some cost to them. Agents can choose over time to be more or less “bold”, which determines the rate at which they attempt defections, and they can likewise choose to be more or less “vengeful”, which determines how often they punish. Axelrod noted that if the game is left like this, we find that the stable state is constant defection and no punishment. However, if we introduce a meta-norm—one that punishes people who fail to punish defectors—then we arrive at a stable norm in which there is no boldness, but very high levels of vengefulness. It is under these conditions that we find a norm emerge and remain stable. Axelrod’s model aims to illustrate that norms require meta-norms. That is, failure to retaliate against a defection must be seen as equivalent to a defection itself. What Axelrod does not analyze is whether there is some cost to being vigilant. Namely, watching both defectors and non-punishers may have a cost that, though nominal, might encourage some to abandon vigilance once there has been no punishment for some time.

Bicchieri, Duffy and Tolle (2004) present an alternative model of norm emergence to explain how a norm of impersonal trust/reciprocity can emerge and survive in a heterogeneous population. This model does not rely on a meta-norm of punishment; instead, it is purely driven by repeated interactions of conditional strategies. In their model, agents play anywhere from 1 to 30 rounds of a trust game for 1,000 iterations, relying on the 4 unconditional strategies, and the 16 conditional strategies that are standard for the trust game. After each round, agents update their strategies based on the replicator dynamic. As the number of rounds grows, a norm of impersonal trust/reciprocity emerges in the population. Most interestingly, however, the norm is not associated with a single strategy, but it is supported by several strategies behaving in similar ways. This model suggests that Trivers’ basic model works well in normal social contexts, but we can further enrich the story by allowing a social norm to supervene on several behavioral strategies.

Muldoon et al. (2012) explore a simpler approach to norm emergence that relies on individual reasoners weighing their individual interests against their social sensitivity. This is done across a number of model variants based on a simple standing ovation. A striking finding of their “symmetric” model is that norm emergence is fairly rare, but can also be distinguished from merely common behaviors. A more cognitively demanding approach was taken by Muldoon, Lisciandra and Hartmann (2012), in which bayesian reasoners can learn to “discover” norms that were not present, and have no particular value. This can happen when agents think there might be a social rule, and then over-interpret social evidence. These models combine to suggest that we should expect many arbitrary norms, rather than a functionalist argument for the presence of norms.

The third prominent model of norm emergence comes from Brian Skyrms (1996, 2004) and Jason Alexander (2007). In this approach, two different features are emphasized: relatively simple cognitive processes and structured interactions. Both have explored a variety of games (such as the prisoner’s dilemma, the stag hunt, divide the dollar, and the ultimatum game) as exemplars of situations that offer the possibility of the emergence of a moral norm. Though Skyrms occasionally uses the replicator dynamic, both tend to emphasize simpler mechanisms in an agent-based learning context. In particular, learning rules like “imitate the best” or best response are used, as they are much less cognitively demanding. Alexander justifies the use of these simpler rules on the grounds that, rather than fully rational agents, we are cognitively limited beings who rely on fairly simple heuristics for our decision-making. Rules like imitation are extremely simple to follow. Best response requires a bit more cognitive sophistication, but is still simpler than a fully Bayesian model with unlimited memory and computational power. These simpler learning rules provide the same function as the replicator dynamic: in between rounds of play, agents rely on their learning rule to decide what strategy to employ. Note that both Skyrms and Alexander tend to treat norms as single strategies.

The largest contribution of this strain of modeling comes not from the assumption of boundedly rational agents, but rather the careful investigation of the effects of particular social structures on the equilibrium outcomes of various games. Much of the previous literature on evolutionary games has focused on the assumptions of infinite populations of agents playing games against randomly-assigned partners. Skyrms and Alexander both rightly emphasize the importance of structured interaction. As it is difficult to uncover and represent real-world network structures, both tend to rely on examining different classes of networks that have different properties, and from there investigate the robustness of particular norms against these alternative network structures. Alexander (2007) in particular has done a very careful study of the different classical network structures, where he examines lattices, small world networks, bounded degree networks, and dynamic networks for each game and learning rule he considers. A final feature of Skyrms and Alexander’s work is a refinement on this structural approach: they separate out two different kinds of networks. First, there is the interaction network, which represents the set of agents that any given agent can actively play a game with. Second is the update network , which is the set of agents that an agent can “see” when applying her learning rule. The interaction network is thus one’s immediate community, whereas the update network is all that the agent can see. To see why this is useful, we can imagine a case not too different from how we live, in which there is a fairly limited set of other people we may interact with, but thanks to a plethora of media options, we can see much more widely how others might act. This kind of situation can only be represented by clearly separating the two networks.

Thus, what makes the theory of norm emergence of Skyrms and Alexander so interesting is its enriching the set of idealizations that one must make in building a model. The addition of structured interaction and structured updates to a model of norm emergence can help make clear how certain kinds of norms tend to emerge in certain kinds of situation and not others, which is difficult or impossible to capture in random interaction models.

Now that we have examined norm emergence, we must examine what happens when a population is exposed to more than one social norm. In this instance, social norms must compete with each other for adherents. This lends itself to investigations about the competitive dynamics of norms over long time horizons. In particular, we can investigate the features of norms and of their environments, such as the populations themselves, which help facilitate one norm becoming dominant over others, or becoming prone to elimination by its competitors. An evolutionary model provides a description of the conditions under which social norms may spread. One may think of several environments to start with. A population can be represented as entirely homogeneous, in the sense that everybody is adopting the same type of behavior, or heterogeneous to various degrees. In the former case, it is important to know whether the commonly adopted behavior is stable against mutations. The relevant concept here is that of an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS; Maynard Smith & Price 1973; Taylor & Jonker 1978): when a population of individuals adopts such a strategy, it cannot be successfully invaded by isolated mutants, since the mutants will be at a disadvantage with respect to reproductive success. An evolutionarily stable strategy is a refinement of the Nash equilibrium in game theory. Unlike standard Nash equilibria, evolutionarily stable strategies must either be strict equilibria , or have an advantage when playing against mutant strategies. Since strict equilibria are always superior to any unilateral deviations, and the second condition requires that the ESS have an advantage in playing against mutants, the strategy will remain resistant to any mutant invasion. This is a difficult criterion to meet, however. For example, a classic Tit-For-Tat strategy in the prisoner’s dilemma is not an ESS. Many strategies perform equally well against it, including the very simple “Always Cooperate” strategy, let alone Tit-For-Two-Tats, and any number of variations. Tit-For-Tat is merely an evolutionarily neutral strategy relative to these others. If we only consider strategies that are defection-oriented, then Tit-For-Tat is an ESS, since it will do better against itself, and no worse than defection strategies when paired with them.

A more interesting case, and one relevant to a study of the reproduction of norms of cooperation, is that of a population in which several competing strategies are present at any given time. What we want to know is whether the strategy frequencies that exist at a time are stable, or if there is a tendency for one strategy to become dominant over time. If we continue to rely on the ESS solution concept, we see a classic example in the hawk-dove game. If we assume that there is no uncorrelated asymmetry between the players, then the mixed Nash equilibrium is the ESS. If we further assume that there is no structure to how agents interact with each other, this can be interpreted in two ways: either each player randomizes her strategy in each round of play, or we have a stable polymorphism in the population, in which the proportion of each strategy in the population corresponds to the frequency with which each strategy would be played in a randomizing approach. So, in those cases where we can assume that players randomly encounter each other, whenever there is a mixed solution ESS we can expect to find polymorphic populations.

If we wish to avoid the interpretive challenge of a mixed solution ESS, there is an alternative analytic solution concept that we can employ: the evolutionarily stable state. An evolutionarily stable state is a distribution of (one or more) strategies that is robust against perturbations, whether they are exogenous shocks or mutant invasions, provided the perturbations are not overly large. Evolutionarily stable states are solutions to a replicator dynamic. Since evolutionarily stable states are naturally able to describe polymorphic or monomorphic populations, there is no difficulty with introducing population-oriented interpretations of mixed strategies. This is particularly important when random matching does not occur, as under those conditions, the mixed strategy can no longer be thought of as a description of population polymorphism.

Now that we have seen the prominent approaches to both norm emergence and norm stability, we can turn to some general interpretive considerations of evolutionary models. An evolutionary approach is based on the principle that strategies with higher current payoffs will be retained, while strategies that lead to failure will be abandoned. The success of a strategy is measured by its relative frequency in the population at any given time. This is most easily seen in a game theoretic framework. A game is repeated a finite number of times with randomly selected opponents. After each round of the game, the actual payoffs and strategies of the players become public knowledge; on the basis of this information, each player adjusts her strategy for the next round. The payoff to an individual player depends on her choice as well as on the choices of the other players in the game, and players are rational in the sense that they are payoff-maximizers. In an evolutionary model, however, players learn and adapt in a non-Bayesian way, that is, they do not condition on past experience using Bayes’ Rule. In this sense, they are not typical rational learners (Nachbar 1990; Binmore & Samuelson 1992).

In an evolutionary approach behavior is adaptive, so that a strategy that did work well in the past is retained, and one that fared poorly will be changed. This can be interpreted in two ways: either the evolution of strategies is the consequence of adaptation by individual agents, or the evolution of strategies is understood as the differential reproduction of agents based on their success rates in their interactions. The former interpretation assumes short timescales for interactions: many iterations of the game over time thus represent no more than a few decades in time in total. The latter interpretation assumes rather longer timescales: each instance of strategy adjustment represents a new generation of agents coming into the population, with the old generation dying simultaneously. Let us consider the ramifications of each interpretation in turn.

In the first interpretation, we have agents who employ learning rules that are less than fully rational, as defined by what a Bayesian agent would have, both in terms of computational ability and memory. As such, these rules tend to be classified as adaptive strategies: they are reacting to a more limited set of data, with lower cognitive resources than what a fully rational learner would possess. However, there are many different adaptive mechanisms we may attribute to the players. One realistic adaptive mechanism is learning by trial and error; another plausible mechanism is imitation: those who do best are observed by others who subsequently emulate their behavior (Hardin 1982). Reinforcement learning is another class of adaptive behavior, in which agents tweak their probabilities of choosing one strategy over another based on the payoffs they just received.

In the second interpretation, agents themselves do not learn, but rather the strategies grow or shrink in the population according to the reproductive advantages that they bestow upon the agents that adhere to them. This interpretation requires very long timescales, as it requires many generations of agents before equilibrium is reached. The typical dynamics that are considered in such circumstances come from biology. A standard approach is something like the replicator dynamic. Norms grow or shrink in proportion to both how many agents adhere to them at a given time, and their relative payoffs. More successful strategies gain adherents at the expense of less-successful ones. This evolutionary process assumes a constant-sized (or infinite) population over time. This interpretation of an evolutionary dynamic, which requires long timescales, raises the question of whether norms themselves evolve slowly. Norms can rapidly collapse in a very short amount of time. This phenomenon could not be represented within a model whose interpretation is generational in nature. It remains an open question, however, as to whether such timescales can be appropriate for examining the emergence of certain kinds of norms. While it is known that many norms can quickly come into being, it is not clear if this is true of all norms.

Another challenge in using evolutionary models to study social norms is that there is a potential problem of representation. In evolutionary models, there is no rigorous way to represent innovation or novelty. Whether we look at an agent-based simulation approach, or a straightforward game-theoretic approach, the strategy set open to the players, as well as their payoffs, must be defined in advance. But many social norms rely on innovations, whether they are technological or social. Wearing mini-skirts was not an option until they were invented. Marxist attitudes were largely not possible until Marx. The age at which one gets married and how many children one has are highly linked to availability of and education about birth control technologies. While much of the study of norms has focused on more generic concepts such as fairness, trust, or cooperation, the full breadth of social norms covers many of these more specific norms that require some account of social innovation.

This representational challenge has broad implications. Even when we can analytically identify evolutionarily stable states in a particular game, which is suggestive of norms that will be converged upon, we now have a problem of claiming that this norm has prospects for long-term stability. Events like the publication of the Kinsey report can dramatically shift seemingly stable norms quite rapidly. As the underlying game changes in the representation, our previous results no longer apply. In the face of this representational problem, we can either attempt to develop some metric of the robustness of a given norm in the space of similar games, or more carefully scope the claims that we can make about the social norms that we study with this methodology.

Although some questions of interpretation and challenges of representation exist, an important advantage of the evolutionary approach is that it does not require sophisticated strategic reasoning in circumstances, such as large-group interactions, in which it would be unrealistic to assume it. People are very unlikely to engage in full Bayesian calculations in making decisions about norm adherence. Agents often rely on cognitive shortcuts to determine when norms ought to be in effect given a certain context, and whether or not they should adhere to them. Evolutionary models that employ adaptive learning strategies capture these kinds of cognitive constraints, and allow the theorist to explore how these constraints influence the emergence and stability of norms.

The study of social norms can help us understand a wide variety of seemingly puzzling behaviors. According to some accounts, a social norm results from conditional preferences for conforming to a relevant behavioral rule. Such preferences are conditional on two different kinds of beliefs: empirical and normative expectations.

This and other accounts of social norms still leave much to be investigated. Explaining how normative expectations come to exist remains an open question. Another open question to consider is how one could intervene to change socially harmful norms. While there have been initial investigations into these questions (Bicchieri 2016, Muldoon 2018a, 2018b), there is much more work to be done. One frontier in this area is in deploying behavioral tools such as nudging for fostering norm changes (Bicchieri 2022, 2023).

Finally, we stress that different contextual factors (such as the framing and characteristics of the strategic problem, the role one is assigned, the social category with which one identifies, as well as historical and chance events) often come to be associated with different notions of “appropriate behavior”. Accounting for endogenous expectations is therefore key to a full understanding of norm-driven behavior. More research—both theoretical and experimental—is needed to further illuminate the impact of expectations on strategic decisions.

  • Abbink, K., Gangadharan, L., Handfield, T., et al., 2017, Peer punishment promotes enforcement of bad social norms. Nat Commun 8(609). doi:10.1038/s41467-017-00731-0
  • Akerlof, George A., 1976, “The Economics of Caste and of the Rat Race and Other Woeful Tales”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 90(4): 599–617. doi:10.2307/1885324
  • Alexander, Jason McKenzie, 2000, “Evolutionary Explanations of Distributive Justice”, Philosophy of Science , 67(3): 490–516. doi:10.1086/392792
  • –––, 2005, “The Evolutionary Foundations of Human Altruism”, Analyse & Kritik , 27(1): 106–113. [ Alexander 2005 available online ]
  • –––, 2007, The Structural Evolution of Morality , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511550997
  • Andreoni, James and B. Douglas Bernheim, 2009, “Social Image and The 50–50 Norm: A Theoretical and Experimental Analysis of Audience Effects”, Econometrica , 77(5): 1607–1636. doi:10.3982/ECTA7384
  • Arrow, Kenneth J., 1971, “A Utilitarian Approach to the Concept of Equality in Public Expenditure”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 85(3): 409–15. doi:10.2307/1885930
  • Axelrod, Robert, 1984, The Evolution of Cooperation , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 1986, “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms”, American Political Science Review , 80(4): 1095–1111. doi:10.1017/S0003055400185016
  • Battigalli, Pierpaolo & Dufwenberg, Martin, 2009, “Dynamic Psychological Games”, Journal of Economic Theory , 144(1): 1–35. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2008.01.004
  • –––, 2022, “Belief-Dependent Motivations and Psychological Game Theory”, Journal of Economic Literature , 60(3): 833–882. doi:10.1257/jel.20201378
  • Bénabou, Roland and Jean Tirole, 2006, “Incentives and Prosocial Behavior”, American Economic Review , 96(5): 1652–1678. doi:10.1257/aer.96.5.1652
  • –––, 2011, “Identity, Morals, and Taboos: Beliefs as Assets”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 126(2): 805–855. doi:10.1093/qje/qjr002
  • Bicchieri, Cristina, 1990, “Norms of Cooperation”, Ethics , 100(4): 838–861. doi:10.1086/293237
  • –––, 1993, Rationality and Coordination , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second Edition, 1996.
  • –––, 1997, “Learning to Cooperate”, in Cristina Bicchieri, Richard C. Jeffrey, and Brian Skyrms, The Dynamics of Norms , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2002, “Covenants Without Swords: Group Identity, Norms, and Communication in Social Dilemmas”, Rationality and Society , 14(2): 192–228. doi:10.1177/1043463102014002003
  • –––, 2006, The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511616037
  • –––, 2016, Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure, and Change Social Norms , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190622046.001.0001
  • –––, 2022, “Norm Nudging: How to Measure What We Want to Implement” in Behavioral Science in the Wild (pp. 82–107). University of Toronto Press.
  • –––, 2023, “Norm nudging and twisting preferences”, Behavioural Public Policy , 1–10.
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Alex Chavez, 2010, “Behaving as Expected: Public Information and Fairness Norms”, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making , 23(2): 161–178. doi:10.1002/bdm.648
  • Bicchieri, Cristina, John Duffy, and Gil Tolle, 2004, “Trust Among Strangers”, Philosophy of Science , 71(3): 286–319. doi:10.1086/381411
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Yoshitaka Fukui, 1999, “The Great Illusion: Ignorance, Informational Cascades and the Persistence of Unpopular Norms”, Business Ethics Quarterly , 9(1): 127–155. doi:10.2307/3857639
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Azi Lev-On, 2007, “Computer-Mediated Communication and Cooperation in Social Dilemmas: An Experimental Analysis”, Politics, Philosophy and Economics , 6(2): 139–168. doi:10.1177/1470594X07077267
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Alessandro Sontuoso, 2015, “I Cannot Cheat on You After We Talk”, in The Prisoner’s Dilemma , Martin Peterson (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 101–114. doi:10.1017/CBO9781107360174.007
  • –––, 2020, “Game-Theoretic Accounts of Social Norms”, in M. Capra, R. Croson, T. Rosenblatt, and M. Rigdon (eds.), The Handbook of Experimental Game Theory , Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing. doi:10.4337/9781785363337.00017
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Erte Xiao, 2009, “Do the Right Thing: But Only If Others Do So”, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making , 22(2): 191–208. doi:10.1002/bdm.621
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Jiji Zhang, 2012, “An Embarrassment of Riches: Modeling Social Preferences in Ultimatum Games”, in Philosophy of Economics , ( Handbook of the Philosophy of Science , Volume 13), Uskali Mäki (ed.), Amsterdam: Elsevier.
  • Binmore, Ken, 2010, “Social Norms or Social Preferences?”, Mind & Society , 9(2): 139–157. doi:10.1007/s11299-010-0073-2
  • Binmore, Kenneth G. and Larry Samuelson, 1992, “Evolutionary Stability in Repeated Games Played by Finite Automata”, Journal of Economic Theory , 57(2): 278–305. doI:10.1016/0022-0531(92)90037-I
  • Bolton, Gary E. and Axel Ockenfels, 2000, “ERC: A Theory of Equity, Reciprocity, and Competition”, American Economic Review , 90(1): 166–193. doi:10.1257/aer.90.1.166
  • Bornstein, Gary and Meyrav Ben-Yossef, 1994, “Cooperation in Intergroup and Single-Group Social Dilemmas”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology , 30(1): 52–67. doi:10.1006/jesp.1994.1003
  • Bowles, Samuel, 1998, “Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Markets and Other Economic Institutions”, Journal of Economic Literature , 36(1): 75–111.
  • Brennan, Geoffrey, Lina Eriksson, Robert E. Goodin, and Nicholas Southwood, 2013, Explaining Norms , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199654680.001.0001
  • Brewer, Marilynn B., 1979, “In-group Bias in the Minimal Intergroup Situation: A Cognitive-Motivational Analysis”, Psychological Bulletin , 86(2): 307–324. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.86.2.307
  • –––, 1991, “The Social Self: On Being the Same and Different at the Same Time”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin , 17(5): 475–482. doi:10.1177/0146167291175001
  • Brewer, Marilynn B. and Sherry K. Schneider, 1990, “Social Identity and Social Dilemmas: A Double-Edged Sword”, in Dominic Abrams and Michael A. Hogg (eds.), Social Identity Theory: Constructive and Critical Advances , Wheatsheaf, NY: Harvester.
  • Camerer, Colin F., 2003, Behavioral Game Theory. Experiments in Strategic Interaction , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Cancian, Francesca M, 1975, What are Norms? A Study of Beliefs and Action in a Maya Community , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cappelen, Alexander W., Astri Drange Hole, Erik Ø Sørensen and Bertil Tungodden, 2007, “The Pluralism of Fairness Ideals: An Experimental Approach”, American Economic Review , 97(3): 818–827. doi:10.1257/aer.97.3.818
  • Charness, Gary and Matthew Rabin, 2002, “Understanding Social Preferences with Simple Tests”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 117(3): 817–869. doi:10.1162/003355302760193904
  • Chavez, Alex K. and Cristina Bicchieri, 2013, “Third-Party Sanctioning and Compensation Behavior: Findings from the Ultimatum Game”, Journal of Economic Psychology , 39: 268–277. doi:10.1016/j.joep.2013.09.004
  • Cialdini, Robert B. and Noah J. Goldstein, 2004, “Social Influence: Compliance and Conformity”, Annual Review of Psychology , 55: 591–621. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.142015
  • Cialdini, Robert B., Carl A. Kallgren, and Raymond R. Reno, 1991, “A Focus Theory of Normative Conduct”, in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology , volume 24, Mark P. Zanna (ed.), New York: Academic Press, pp. 201–234. doi:10.1016/S0065-2601(08)60330-5
  • Coleman, James S., 1990, Foundations of Social Theory , Cambridge, MA: Belknap.
  • Coleman, Jules L., 1989, “Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules”, Chicago-Kent Law Review , 65(1): 177–191. [ Jules Coleman 1989 available online ]
  • Dawes, Robyn M., 1972, Fundamentals of Attitude Measurement , New York: Wiley.
  • –––, 1980, “Social Dilemmas”, Annual Review of Psychology , 31: 169–193. doi:10.1146/annurev.ps.31.020180.001125
  • –––, 1991, “Social Dilemmas, Economic Self-Interest, and Evolutionary Theory”, in Donald R. Brown and J.E. Keith Smith (eds.), Recent Research in Psychology: Frontiers of Mathematical Psychology: Essays in Honor of Clyde Coombs , New York: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-3088-5_2
  • Deutscher, Irwin, 1973, “What”, in his What We Say/What We Do: Sentiments & Acts , Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman.
  • Dhami, Sanjit S., 2016, The Foundations of Behavioral Economic Analysis , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Diamond, A.S., 1935, Primitive Law , London: Watts.
  • Dufwenberg, Martin and Georg Kirchsteiger, 2004, “A Theory of Sequential Reciprocity”, Games and Economic Behavior , 47(2): 268–298. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2003.06.003
  • Durkheim, Émile, 1895 [1982], Les Règles de la méthode sociologique , Paris. Translated as The Rules of Sociological Method , W. D. Hall (trans.), Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.
  • –––, 1950 [1957], Leçons de Sociologie: Physique des Moeurs et du Droit , Istanbul: Cituri Biraderlet Basimevi. Translated as Professional Ethics and Civic Morals , Cornelia Brookfield (trans.), Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.
  • Ellickson, Robert C., 1991, Order Without Law: How Neighbors Settle Disputes , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ellingsen, Tore, Magnus Johannesson, Johanna Mollerstrom, and Sara Munkhammar, 2012, “Social Framing Effects: Preferences or Beliefs?”, Games and Economic Behavior , 76(1): 117–130. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2012.05.007
  • Elster, Jon, 1989a, The Cement of Society: A Study of Social Order , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511624995
  • –––, 1989b, “Social Norms and Economic Theory” Journal of Economic Perspectives , 3(4): 99–117. doi:10.1257/jep.3.4.99
  • Falk, Armin and Urs Fischbacher, 2006, “A Theory of Reciprocity”, Games and Economic Behavior , 54(2): 293–315. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2005.03.001
  • Fehr, Ernst and Klaus M. Schmidt, 1999, “A Theory of Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 114(3): 817–868. doi:10.1162/003355399556151
  • –––, 2006, “The Economics of Fairness, Reciprocity and Altruism—Experimental Evidence and New Theories”, in Serge-Christophe Kolm and Jean Mercier Ythier (eds.), Handbook of The Economics of Giving, Altruism and Reciprocity (Volume 1), Amsterdam: North-Holland/Elsevier, pp. 615–691. doi:10.1016/S1574-0714(06)01008-6
  • Fishbein, Martin E., 1967, “A Consideration of Beliefs and Their Role in Attitude Measurement”, in Readings in Attitude Theory and Measurement , Martin E. Fishbein (ed.), New York: Wiley.
  • Freeman, Linton C. and Türröz Ataöv, 1960, “Invalidity of Indirect and Direct Measures of Attitude Toward Cheating”, Journal of Personality , 28(4): 443–447. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6494.1960.tb01631.x
  • Gächter, Simon, Daniele Nosenzo, and Martin Sefton, 2013, “Peer Effects in Pro-Social Behavior: Social Norms or Social Preferences?”, Journal of The European Economic Association , 11(3): 548–573. doi:10.1111/jeea.12015
  • Gaertner, Samuel L. and John F. Dovidio, 1986, “The Aversive Form of Racism”, in John F. Dovidio and Samuel L. Gaertner (eds.), Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism: Theory and Research , Orlando, FL: Academic Press, pp. 61–89.
  • Geanakoplos, John, David Pearce, and Ennio Stacchetti, 1989, “Psychological Games and Sequential Rationality”, Games and Economic Behavior , 1(1): 60–79. doi:10.1016/0899-8256(89)90005-5
  • Geertz, Clifford, 1973, “Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture”, in The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays , New York: Basic Books, pp. 3–30.
  • Gintis, Herbert, 2000, Game Theory Evolving , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Granovetter, Mark, 1985, “Economic Action and Social Structure: the Problem of Embeddedness”, American Journal of Sociology , 91(3): 481–510. doi:10.1086/228311
  • Guala, Francesco, 2016, Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Hamilton W.D., 1964, “The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour I and II”, Journal of Theoretical Biology , 7: 1–16 and 17–52. doi:10.1016/0022-5193(64)90038-4 and 10.1016/0022-5193(64)90039-6
  • Handfield, T., & Thrasher, J., 2019, “Two of a kind: Are norms of honor a species of morality?” Biol Philos , 34, 39. doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9693-z
  • Hardin, Russell, 1982, Collective Action , New York: Resources for the Future.
  • Harding, John, Harold Proshansky, Bernard Kutner, and Isidor Chein, 1954 [1969], “Prejudice and Ethnic Relations”, in Gardner Lindzey (ed.), Handbook of Social Psychology , volume 2, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, pp. 1021–1061. Reprinted in Gardner Lindzey and Elliot Aronson (eds.), Handbook of Social Psychology , second edition, volume 5, Reading, MA: Addison Wesley, 1969, pp. 1–76.
  • Hausman, Daniel M., 2008, “Fairness and Social Norms” Philosophy of Science , 75(5): 850–860. doi:10.1086/594529
  • Hechter, Michael and Karl-Dieter Opp, 2001, Social Norms , New York: Russel Sage Foundation.
  • Henrich, Joseph and Robert Boyd, 2001, “Why People Punish Defectors: Weak Conformist Transmission Can Stabilize Costly Enforcement of Norms in Cooperative Dilemmas”, Journal of Theoretical Biology , 208(1): 79–89. doi:10.1006/jtbi.2000.2202
  • Henrich, Joseph, Robert Boyd, Samuel Bowles, Colin Camerer, Ernst Fehr, Herbert Gintis, and Richard McElreath, 2001, “In Search of Homo Economicus: Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies”, American Economic Review , 91(2): 73–78. doi:10.1257/aer.91.2.73
  • Hirshmann, Albert O., 1982, Shifting Involvements: Private Interest and Public Action , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Hoebel, Adamson E., 1954, The Law of Primitive Man , Cambridge, MA: Atheneum.
  • Hogg, Michael A. and John C. Turner, 1987, “Social Identity and Conformity: A Theory of Referent Informational Influence”, in William Doise and Serge Moscovici (eds.), Current Issues in European Social Psychology , Volume 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 139–182.
  • Homans, George Caspar, 1950, The Human Group , New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company.
  • –––, 1961, Social Behavior , New York: Harcourt Brace and World.
  • Insko, Chester A. and John Schopler, 1967, “Triadic Consistency: A Statement of Affective-Cognitive-Conative Consistency”, Psychological Review , 74(5): 361–376. doi:10.1037/h0020278
  • Kagel, John H. and Alvin E. Roth, 2016, Handbook of Experimental Economics , Volume 2, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Klassen, Albert D., Colin J. Williams, and Eugene E. Levitt, 1989, Sex and Morality in the U.S.: An Empirical Enquiry Under the Auspices of the Kinsey Institute , Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.
  • Kramer, Roderick M. and Marilynn B. Brewer, 1984, “Effects of Group Identity on Resource Use in a Simulated Commons Dilemma”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 46(5): 1044–1057. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.46.5.1044
  • Krupka, Erin L. and Roberto A. Weber, 2013, “Identifying Social Norms Using Coordination Games: Why Does Dictator Game Sharing Vary?”, Journal of The European Economic Association , 11(3): 495–524. doi:10.1111/jeea.12006
  • LaPiere, Richard T., 1934, “Attitudes vs. Actions”, Social Forces , 13(2): 230–237. doi:10.2307/2570339
  • Ledyard, John, 1995, “Public Goods Experiments”, in John H. Kagel and Alvin E. Roth (eds.), The Handbook of Experimental Economics , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Lewis, David, 1969, Convention: A Philosophical Study , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. doi:10.1002/9780470693711
  • –––, 1975, “Languages and Language”, in Language, Mind, and Knowledge , ( Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science , 6), Keith Gunderson (ed.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–35. [ Lewis 1975 available online ]
  • López-Pérez, Raúl, 2008, “Aversion to Norm-Breaking: A Model”, Games and Economic Behavior , 64(1): 237–267. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2007.10.009
  • Mackay, Charles, 1841, Extraordinary Popular Delusions and the Madness of Crowds , N. Stone (ed.), Hertfordshire: Wordsworth, 1995.
  • Mackie, G., 1996, “Ending Footbinding and Infibulation: A Convention Account”, American Sociological Review , 61(6): 999–1017. doi:10.2307/2096305
  • Matza, David, 1964, Delinquency and Drift , New York: Wiley.
  • Maynard Smith, J. and G. R. Price, 1973, “The Logic of Animal Conflict”, Nature , 246(5427): 15–18. doi:10.1038/246015a0
  • Miller, Dale T. and Rebecca K. Ratner, 1996, “The Power of the Myth of Self-Interest”, in Leo Montada and Melvin J. Lerner (eds.), Current Societal Concerns About Justice , New York: Plenum Press. doi:10.1007/978-1-4757-9927-9_3
  • Muldoon, Ryan, 2017, “Perspectives, Norms and Agency”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 34(1): 260–276. doi:10.1017/S0265052517000127
  • –––, 2018a, “Understanding Norms and Changing Them”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 35(1): 128–148. doi:10.1017/S0265052518000092
  • –––, 2018b, “Norms, Nudges, and Autonomy”, In: Boonin, D. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Public Policy . Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-93907-0_18
  • –––, 2020, “Social Norms and Social Order”, in: Chartier and Van Schoelandt (eds) The Routledge Handbook of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought . Routledge.
  • Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Bicchieri, C., Hartmann, S., & Sprenger, J., 2014, “On the emergence of descriptive norms”, Politics, Philosophy & Economics , 13(1): 3–22. doi:10.1177/1470594X12447791
  • Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C. & Hartmann, S., 2014, “Why are there descriptive norms? Because we looked for them”, Synthese 191, 4409–4429. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0534-y
  • Nachbar, J.H., 1990, “‘Evolutionary’ Selection Dynamics in Games: Convergence and Limit Properties”, International Journal of Game Theory , 19(1): 59–89. doi:10.1007/BF01753708
  • North, Douglass C., 1990, “A Transaction Cost Theory of Politics” Journal of Theoretical Politics , 2(4): 355–367. doi:10.1177/0951692890002004001
  • O’Gorman, Hubert J., 1975, “Pluralistic Ignorance and White Estimates of White Support for Racial Segregation”, Public Opinion Quarterly , 39(3): 313–330. doi:10.1086/268231
  • Olson, Mancur, 1965 [1971], The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups , revised edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ostrom, Elinor, 2000, “Collective Action and The Evolution of Social Norms”, Journal of Economic Perspectives , 14(3): 137–158. doi:10.1257/jep.14.3.137
  • Pagel, Elaine, 2003, Beyond Belief: The Secret Gospel of Thomas , New York: Vintage Books.
  • Parsons, Talcott, 1951, The Social System , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 1937 [1968], The Structure of Social Action. A Study in Social Theory with Special Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers , New York, London: Free Press.
  • Parsons, Talcott and Edward A. Shils, 1951, Towards a General Theory of Action , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Posner, Eric A., 2000, Law and Social Norms , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Prentice, Deborah A. and Dale T. Miller, 1993, “Pluralistic Ignorance and Alcohol Use on Campus: Some Consequences of Misperceiving the Social Norm”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 64(2): 243–56. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.64.2.243
  • Rabin, Matthew, 1993, “Incorporating Fairness into Game Theory and Economics”, American Economic Review , 83(5): 1281–1302.
  • Reuben, Ernesto and Arno Riedl, 2013, “Enforcement of Contribution Norms in Public Good Games with Heterogeneous Populations”, Games and Economic Behavior , 77(1): 122–137. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2012.10.001
  • Robinson, Claude E., 1932, Straw Votes: A Study of Political Prediction , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Rommetveit, Ragnar, 1955, Social Norms and Roles: Explorations in the Psychology of Enduring Social Pressures with Empirical Contributions from Inquiries into Religious Attitudes and Sex Roles of Adolescents from Some Districts in Western Norway , Oslo: Akedemisk Forlag.
  • Schelling, Thomas C., 1960, The Strategy of Conflict , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1978, Micromotives and Macrobehavior , New York: Norton.
  • Schram, Arthur and Gary Charness, 2015, “Inducing Social Norms in Laboratory Allocation Choices”, Management Science , 61(7): 1531–1546. doi:10.1287/mnsc.2014.2073
  • Scott, John Finley, 1971, Internalization of Norms: A Sociological Theory of Moral Commitment , Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
  • Sherif, Muzafer, 1936, The Psychology of Social Norms , New York: Harper.
  • Skyrms, Brian, 1996, Evolution of the Social Contract , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511806308
  • –––, 2004, The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139165228
  • Stigler, George J. and Gary S. Becker, 1977, “De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum”, American Economic Review , 67(2): 76–90.
  • Sugden, Robert, 1986 [2004], The Economics of Rights, Co-operation and Welfare , second edition, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004.
  • –––, 2000, “The Motivating Power of Expectations”, in Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn (eds.), Practical Rationality, Rules, and Structure , Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9616-9_7
  • Tajfel, Henri, 1973, “The Roots of Prejudice: Cognitive Aspects”, in Psychology and Race , Peter Watson (ed.), Chicago: Aldine.
  • –––, 1981, Human Groups and Social Categories: Studies in Social Psychology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Taylor, Peter D. and Leo B. Jonker, 1978, “Evolutionary Stable Strategies and Game Dynamics”, Mathematical Biosciences , 40(1–2): 145–156. doi:10.1016/0025-5564(78)90077-9
  • Thibaut, John W. and Harold H. Kelley, 1959, The Social Psychology of Groups , New York: Wiley.
  • Thrasher, John, 2018, “Evaluating bad norms” Social Philosophy and Policy, 35(1): 196–216. doi:10.1017/S0265052518000055
  • Thrasher, J., & Handfield, T., 2018, “Honor and Violence”, Hum Nat 29, 371–389. doi:10.1007/s12110-018-9324-4
  • Trivers, Robert L., 1971, “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism”, Quarterly Review of Biology , 46(1): 35–57. doi:10.1086/406755
  • –––, 1985, Social Evolution , Menlo Park, CA: Benjamin/Cummings.
  • Turnbull, C. M., 1972, The Mountain People , New York: Touchstone.
  • Turner, John C., Michael A. Hogg, Penelope J. Oakes, Stephen D. Reicher, and Margaret S. Wetherell, 1987, Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Ullmann-Margalit, Edna, 1977, The Emergence of Norms , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Vanderschraaf, Peter, 1995, “Convention as Correlated Equilibrium”, Erkenntnis , 42(1): 65–87. doi:10.1007/BF01666812
  • Warner, Lyle G. and Melvin L. DeFleur, 1969, “Attitude as An Interactional Concept: Social Constraint and Social Distance as Intervening Variables Between Attitudes and Action”, American Sociological Review , 34(2): 153–169. doi:10.2307/2092174
  • Wicker, Allan W., 1969, “Attitude versus Actions: The Relationship of Verbal and Overt Behavioral Responses to Attitude Objects”, A Journal of Social Issues , 25(4): 41–78. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4560.1969.tb00619.x
  • Wrong, Dennis H., 1961, “The Oversocialized Conception of Man in Modern Sociology”, American Sociological Review , 26(2): 183–193. doi:10.2307/2089854
  • Wuthnow, Robert, 1991, Acts of Compassion: Caring for Others and Helping Ourselves , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Xiao, Erte and Cristina Bicchieri, 2010, “When Equality Trumps Reciprocity”, Journal of Economic Psychology , 31(3): 456–470. doi:10.1016/j.joep.2010.02.001
  • Young, H. Peyton, 1993, “The Evolution of Conventions”, Econometrica , 61(1): 57–84. doi:10.2307/2951778
  • –––, 1998a, “Social Norms and Economic Welfare”, European Economic Review , 42(3–5): 821–830. doi:10.1016/S0014-2921(97)00138-4
  • –––, 1998b, Individual Strategy and Social Structure: An Evolutionary Theory of Institutions , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Arló-Costa, Horacio and Arthur Paul Pedersen, “ Social Norms, Rational Choice and Belief Change ”, manuscript, Carnegie Mellon Research Showcase.
  • Axelrod, Robert, 1992, “ How to Promote Cooperation ”, Current Contents—Social and Behavioral Sciences , 44: 10 (November 2, 1992); this is a scan of the version that appeared in Current Contents—Arts and Humanities , 23: 16 (November 9, 1992).
  • Selected Papers on Social Norms at EconPapers .
  • Social Norm , entry in Wikipedia .

altruism | belief | common knowledge | convention | evolution | game theory | game theory: evolutionary | morality: and evolutionary biology | normative cognition, psychology of | social institutions

Acknowledgments

A portion of section 6 of this entry has been adapted from “Game-Theoretic Accounts of Social Norms”, by Cristina Bicchieri and Alessandro Sontuoso, in The Handbook of Experimental Game Theory , Mónica Capra, Rachel Croson, Tanya Rosenblatt, and Mary Rigdon (eds.), Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2020.

Copyright © 2023 by Cristina Bicchieri < cb36 @ sas . upenn . edu > Ryan Muldoon < ryan . muldoon @ gmail . com > Alessandro Sontuoso < sontuoso @ sas . upenn . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Social Roles and Social Norms In Psychology

Saul Mcleod, PhD

Editor-in-Chief for Simply Psychology

BSc (Hons) Psychology, MRes, PhD, University of Manchester

Saul Mcleod, PhD., is a qualified psychology teacher with over 18 years of experience in further and higher education. He has been published in peer-reviewed journals, including the Journal of Clinical Psychology.

Learn about our Editorial Process

Olivia Guy-Evans, MSc

Associate Editor for Simply Psychology

BSc (Hons) Psychology, MSc Psychology of Education

Olivia Guy-Evans is a writer and associate editor for Simply Psychology. She has previously worked in healthcare and educational sectors.

On This Page:

There are many ways that people can influence our behavior, but perhaps one of the most important is that the presence of others seems to set up expectations

We do not expect people to behave randomly but in certain ways in particular situations.  Each social situation entails a particular set of expectations about the “proper” way to behave. Such expectations can vary from group to group.

Social roles emphasize the duties and behaviors attached to a specific position, and social norms dictate broader behavioral guidelines within a community or group.

Social Roles

One way these expectations become apparent is when we look at the roles people play in society.

Social roles refer to the behavior patterns expected of individuals in different situations and settings based on their specific position within a social unit. These roles come with rights, responsibilities, expectations, and social norms.

Examples include roles based on family (e.g., parent, sibling), occupation (e.g., teacher, doctor), or societal functions (e.g., leader, citizen).

Social roles help structure interactions within groups, providing a framework for understanding what is expected of individuals in various contexts. They are crucial in shaping individual behavior, identity, and social dynamics.

Social roles can contribute to societal stability by creating predictable behaviors and interactions. In this sense, they serve a functional role that validates their existence and persistence.

Social roles are the part people play as members of a social group. With each social role you adopt, your behavior changes to fit the expectations both you and others have of that role.

In the words of William Shakespeare:

All the worlds a stage,

And all the men and women merely players:

They have their exits, and their entrances;

And one man in his time plays many parts.

These lines capture the essence of social roles.  Think of how many roles you play daily, e.g., son, daughter, sister, brother, student, worker, friend, etc.  Each social role carries expected behaviors called norms.

While social roles provide a framework for behavior, they can also be limiting. They can perpetuate stereotypes, hinder personal expression, and promote inequalities. For instance, rigid gender roles can limit opportunities and potentials for individuals.

Social Norms

Social norms are the unwritten rules of beliefs, attitudes, and behaviors that are considered acceptable in a particular social group or culture.

Norms provide us with an expected idea of how to behave and function to provide order and predictability in society. For example, we expect students to arrive at a lesson on time and complete their work.

Norms provide order in society. It is difficult to see how human society could operate without social norms. Humans need norms to guide and direct their behavior, provide order and predictability in social relationships, and make sense of and understand each other’s actions. These are some of the reasons why most people, most of the time, conform to social norms.

The idea of norms provides the key to understanding general social influence and conformity. Social norms are the accepted standards of behavior of social groups.

These groups range from friendship and workgroups to nation-states. Behavior that fulfills these norms is called conformity , and most of the time, roles and norms are powerful ways of understanding and predicting what people will do.

Norms are defining appropriate behavior for every social group. For example, students, neighbors, and patients in a hospital are all aware of the norms governing behavior. As individuals move from one group to another, their behavior changes accordingly.

These norms can vary widely between cultures, regions, and individual societies, and what’s considered normal or acceptable in one context may not be so in another.

  • Greetings : Shaking hands when meeting someone in many Western cultures, while bowing is customary in countries like Japan.
  • Dining : Using forks and knives for eating in Western societies, whereas chopsticks are used in many East Asian countries.
  • Dress Code : Wearing formal attire in corporate settings, or covering one’s head in places of worship in certain religions.
  • Queueing : Waiting in line for one’s turn, such as at a supermarket checkout or bus stop.
  • Hygiene : Covering one’s mouth when coughing or sneezing.
  • Punctuality : Being on time for appointments or meetings is expected in many cultures.
  • Personal Space : Maintaining a certain distance when speaking to someone, with variations based on cultural norms.
  • Public Behavior : Keeping voice volume down in public places like libraries or cinemas.
  • Reciprocity : Sending a thank-you note after receiving a gift.
  • Digital Etiquette : Not looking over someone’s shoulder while they’re on their phone or avoiding loud phone conversations in public transport.

There is considerable pressure to conform to social roles. Social roles provide an example of social influence in general and conformity in particular.  Most of us, most of the time, conform to the guidelines provided by the roles we perform.

We conform to the expectations of others. We respond to their approval when we play our roles well and to their disapproval when we play our roles badly.

But how far will conformity go?  Zimbardo’s Stanford Prison Experiment illustrates the power of social roles in relation to conformity.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

Home — Essay Samples — Sociology — Social Norms — Norm Violation in Sociology

test_template

Norm Violation in Sociology

  • Categories: Deviance Social Norms

About this sample

close

Words: 1203 |

Published: Feb 12, 2024

Words: 1203 | Pages: 3 | 7 min read

Table of contents

Social norms essay: research methodology, breaking a social norm essay: research results, discussion: the consequences of social norm violation, norm violation faq.

  • What is norm violation in sociology? Norm violation in sociology refers to the intentional or unintentional breaking of social rules and norms that govern society.
  • How do social norms shape society? Social norms play a significant role in shaping society by determining acceptable behavior. They provide guidelines for how individuals should act and interact with others in their community.
  • Can social norms change over time? Yes, social norms are not fixed and can change over time. What was once considered typical or acceptable may now be deemed unacceptable or outdated.
  • What was the focus of the norm violation experiment described in the essay? The norm violation experiment aimed to observe and analyze how individuals would respond to the violation of the social norm of using gender-segregated public restrooms. The experiment sought to determine whether people would attempt to correct the behavior or ignore it, highlighting their readiness to address norm violations.
  • What were the results of the norm violation experiment? The most common reaction observed was subtle confusion without any subsequent comments. Men recognized that the woman had entered the wrong restroom but chose to either leave hurriedly or avoid entering after seeing her inside. This indicated a preference to either escape or ignore norm violations rather than confront them. Only a few individuals attempted to point out the mistake, while others simply asked her to leave. There were no signs of disrespect or physical contact, with only one instance of rude behavior.
  • What were the consequences of the norm violation for the experimenter? The experimenter initially felt uncertainty and shame regarding her behavior, but as the experiment progressed, she became more accustomed to the situation. This suggests that hedonic adaptation may occur in similar circumstances, leading to a normalization of the behavior.
  • What does the norm violation experiment suggest about society? The norm violation experiment suggests that people prioritize their personal space and time over addressing others' social behavior directly. This may reflect an increasing trend towards individualism and selfishness in society. However, it is important to recognize the importance of cooperation and adherence to social norms for the functioning and survival of society.

Image of Dr. Oliver Johnson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr. Heisenberg

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Sociology

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

1 pages / 488 words

3 pages / 1591 words

3 pages / 1555 words

2 pages / 764 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Social Norms

In the intricate tapestry of society, the concept of being an outsider often raises intriguing questions about identity, belonging, and perception. The question, "are outsiders simply those who are misjudged or misunderstood," [...]

Social norms are the unwritten rules that govern behavior in a society. They dictate how individuals should act, dress, and speak in various situations. These norms are essential for maintaining order and cohesion within a [...]

Norms and social norms are powerful forces that shape our behavior and guide our social interactions. They provide a sense of order, cohesion, and predictability in society. Norms act as social guidelines, ensuring that [...]

Implicit bias, an intrinsic component of human cognition, holds a significant role in shaping our attitudes, beliefs, and actions without conscious awareness. This essay delves deeply into the definition of implicit bias, [...]

Baines, S. (2011). Cannibalism in the Early Modern Atlantic World. Perspectives on European History, 41(1), 10-17.Boëtsch, G., Oettlé, A. C., & Leclerc, C. (2019). Cannibalism in prehistoric human populations: A review. Journal [...]

During the Elizabethan Era in England, spanning from 1558 to 1603, sports and recreational activities played a significant role in the daily lives of the people. These activities were more than just pastimes; they reflected the [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

social norms good essay

Gustavo Razzetti

When Breaking the Rules Is the Smart Thing to Do

How and when to do it..

Posted December 6, 2018 | Reviewed by Davia Sills

Most people are afraid to break the rules. Others believe it is the only way to make things happen—they think rules are meant to be broken.

Some people approach life like everything is forbidden unless it is permitted. Others think that everything is allowed until it is explicitly prohibited.

What about you?

The problem with a rigid approach to rules is that it divides people—either you are a conformist or a rebel.

Not all rules are equal. Some were created to control people, others in a different time. Certain rules are black and white; others are open to interpretation.

Frankie foto / Unsplash

Sometimes, it’s okay to break the rules.

I’m not talking about doing it randomly, but with a purpose. Choose to break the rules that limit you, not just because you don’t like them. Break the rules, but consider the consequences on the rest, not only on you.

Start a Fire on Purpose

Breaking the rules just for the sake of it makes no sense. Continually challenging everything is not courage but a lack of focus. Just because we can transgress something doesn’t mean we have to do it.

Break the rules that limit more than they enable you.

Sometimes following the established rules is boring . That’s why people break them—to free themselves, not to send a message.

That’s what happened to William Webb Ellis back in 1823. He was tired of playing football (soccer for Americans); the player took the ball in his arms and ran with it, thus starting a new sport: rugby—named after his school.

Those who start the fire get the credit.

" Fire-starters " is the nickname for those who spearhead change—they don’t just start the fire; they choose when and where to ignite it. They start the fire with a purpose.

Why We Break Rules (or Not)

Our own rules can limit us.

When American women relocate to wealthier cities, they adopt new fashion preferences to please the locals. For example, the heel height of women’s shoes becomes higher. If a woman moves from a lower-status location to New York City, there is an 86 percent chance that she will ditch the flats for heels.

The pressure to conform is self-imposed . When we try to disagree with social norms, our brain turns on an alarm. As science shows , we have internalized the judgments and preferences of other people.

Following rules is one thing. Sticking to the norms to be accepted by others is a different matter.

“Only those who will risk going too far can possibly find out how far one can go.” —T. S. Eliot

Breaking rules is like cheating. Behavioral scientists found a correlation between dishonesty and creativity . People with the most creative jobs or mindsets are more likely to break the rules.

The more creative one is, the easier it is to tell the story in a way that justifies breaking the rules.

There’s an emotional upside, too—people who break the rules feel smarter than the rest. Maybe because they are not conforming. They are also liberated—getting rid of rules allows their brains to think freely and let their creatives juices flow without limitations.

Sometimes, you have to break the rules to start a fire.

A simple method for breaking the rules

“By all means, break the rules, and break them beautifully, deliberately, and well.” —Robert Bringhurst

Pablo Picasso wasn’t just a talented artist; he was one of the most prolific that ever existed. Most people associate the Spanish painter with cubism—an art movement he created. However, Picasso mastered traditional drawing and painting before he explored modern styles.

Master it before you break it—that’s what you can learn from the genius.

Understanding when and how to break the rules requires a method. Corporate rules tend to limit their people rather than enable them to do more and better. This is the approach I use when coaching teams become more innovative.

Outcome > Rule

Before breaking a rule, evaluate if the outcome is worth it. Simply put, will the outcome justify the consequences of breaking that rule?

Choose to start a fire when the outcome is worth it.

Values > Outcome

Each person has his/her values—the same as with organizations. I’m not telling you what’s right or wrong. Before deciding to break the rules, reflect if the decision will go against your values or not.

social norms good essay

Choose to stick to your values over any ideal outcome.

Collective Good > Personal Benefit

Breaking rules has consequences. I’m not talking about people getting upset or not liking your behaviors. Sometimes, the aftermath of your behaviors can benefit you but hurt your team or organization.

Choose the collective over your personal benefit.

Gustavo Razzetti

Gustavo Razzetti is a change leadership consultant and speaker who helps build a culture of change. He writes at the intersection of self-awareness, creativity, and resilience.

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Psychiatrist
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find Teletherapy
  • United States
  • Brooklyn, NY
  • Chicago, IL
  • Houston, TX
  • Los Angeles, CA
  • New York, NY
  • Portland, OR
  • San Diego, CA
  • San Francisco, CA
  • Seattle, WA
  • Washington, DC
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Therapy Center NEW
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

March 2024 magazine cover

Understanding what emotional intelligence looks like and the steps needed to improve it could light a path to a more emotionally adept world.

  • Coronavirus Disease 2019
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience

Thank you for visiting nature.com. You are using a browser version with limited support for CSS. To obtain the best experience, we recommend you use a more up to date browser (or turn off compatibility mode in Internet Explorer). In the meantime, to ensure continued support, we are displaying the site without styles and JavaScript.

  • View all journals
  • My Account Login
  • Explore content
  • About the journal
  • Publish with us
  • Sign up for alerts
  • Open access
  • Published: 16 February 2024

Changes in social norms during the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic across 43 countries

  • Giulia Andrighetto 1 , 2 , 3   na1 ,
  • Aron Szekely   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5651-4711 1 , 4   na1 ,
  • Andrea Guido 1 , 2 , 5 ,
  • Michele Gelfand 6 ,
  • Jered Abernathy 7 ,
  • Gizem Arikan   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-2083-7321 8 ,
  • Zeynep Aycan 9 , 10 ,
  • Shweta Bankar 11 ,
  • Davide Barrera   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-0441-5073 4 , 12 ,
  • Dana Basnight-Brown   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7200-6976 13 ,
  • Anabel Belaus   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-9657-8496 14 , 15 ,
  • Elizaveta Berezina   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-1972-8133 16 ,
  • Sheyla Blumen   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-9960-7413 17 ,
  • Paweł Boski   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-0984-5686 18 ,
  • Huyen Thi Thu Bui 19 ,
  • Juan Camilo Cárdenas   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-0005-7595 20 , 21 ,
  • Đorđe Čekrlija   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-8177-8663 22 , 23 ,
  • Mícheál de Barra   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-4455-6214 24 ,
  • Piyanjali de Zoysa   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7382-6503 25 ,
  • Angela Dorrough   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-5645-949X 26 ,
  • Jan B. Engelmann   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-6493-8792 27 ,
  • Hyun Euh   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-0972-1640 28 ,
  • Susann Fiedler   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-9337-2142 29 ,
  • Olivia Foster-Gimbel   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-4583-3060 30 ,
  • Gonçalo Freitas   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5888-3000 31 ,
  • Marta Fülöp 32 , 33 ,
  • Ragna B. Gardarsdottir   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-3368-4616 34 ,
  • Colin Mathew Hugues D. Gill   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-3225-246X 16 , 35 ,
  • Andreas Glöckner   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7766-4791 26 ,
  • Sylvie Graf   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7810-5457 36 ,
  • Ani Grigoryan   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5453-2879 37 ,
  • Katarzyna Growiec   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-4448-2561 18 ,
  • Hirofumi Hashimoto   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-3648-9912 38 ,
  • Tim Hopthrow   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-2331-7150 39 ,
  • Martina Hřebíčková   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-8700-1326 36 ,
  • Hirotaka Imada   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-3604-4155 40 ,
  • Yoshio Kamijo   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-2184-9594 41 ,
  • Hansika Kapoor   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-0805-7752 42 ,
  • Yoshihisa Kashima 43 ,
  • Narine Khachatryan   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-3590-7131 37 ,
  • Natalia Kharchenko 44 ,
  • Diana León   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-4596-3858 45 ,
  • Lisa M. Leslie 30 ,
  • Yang Li   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-8239-3279 46 ,
  • Kadi Liik   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-5166-9893 47 ,
  • Marco Tullio Liuzza   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-6708-1253 48 ,
  • Angela T. Maitner   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-3896-5783 49 ,
  • Pavan Mamidi 11 ,
  • Michele McArdle 8 ,
  • Imed Medhioub   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-4676-7330 50 ,
  • Maria Luisa Mendes Teixeira   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-0606-1723 51 ,
  • Sari Mentser   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-1520-8253 52 ,
  • Francisco Morales   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-0785-8838 53 ,
  • Jayanth Narayanan   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-2720-1593 54 ,
  • Kohei Nitta 55 ,
  • Ravit Nussinson   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7331-548X 56 , 57 ,
  • Nneoma G. Onyedire   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-4941-2300 58 ,
  • Ike E. Onyishi 58 ,
  • Evgeny Osin   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-3330-5647 59 ,
  • Seniha Özden 9 ,
  • Penny Panagiotopoulou 60 ,
  • Oleksandr Pereverziev 61 ,
  • Lorena R. Perez-Floriano   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-6898-7794 62 ,
  • Anna-Maija Pirttilä-Backman   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7437-9645 63 ,
  • Marianna Pogosyan 64 ,
  • Jana Raver 65 ,
  • Cecilia Reyna   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-6097-4961 14 ,
  • Ricardo Borges Rodrigues 66 ,
  • Sara Romanò 12 ,
  • Pedro P. Romero   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-2616-4498 67 , 68 ,
  • Inari Sakki   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-8717-5804 63 ,
  • Angel Sánchez   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-1874-2881 69 , 70 ,
  • Sara Sherbaji   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7815-8962 49 , 71 ,
  • Brent Simpson   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-9468-157X 7 ,
  • Lorenzo Spadoni   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-1208-2897 72 ,
  • Eftychia Stamkou 73 ,
  • Giovanni A. Travaglino   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-4091-0634 40 ,
  • Paul A. M. Van Lange   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-7774-6984 74 ,
  • Fiona Fira Winata 75 ,
  • Rizqy Amelia Zein   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-7840-0299 75 ,
  • Qing-peng Zhang 76 &
  • Kimmo Eriksson   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-7164-0924 2 , 77 , 78  

Nature Communications volume  15 , Article number:  1436 ( 2024 ) Cite this article

3615 Accesses

33 Altmetric

Metrics details

  • Human behaviour

The emergence of COVID-19 dramatically changed social behavior across societies and contexts. Here we study whether social norms also changed. Specifically, we study this question for cultural tightness (the degree to which societies generally have strong norms), specific social norms (e.g. stealing, hand washing), and norms about enforcement, using survey data from 30,431 respondents in 43 countries recorded before and in the early stages following the emergence of COVID-19. Using variation in disease intensity, we shed light on the mechanisms predicting changes in social norm measures. We find evidence that, after the emergence of the COVID-19 pandemic, hand washing norms increased while tightness and punishing frequency slightly decreased but observe no evidence for a robust change in most other norms. Thus, at least in the short term, our findings suggest that cultures are largely stable to pandemic threats except in those norms, hand washing in this case, that are perceived to be directly relevant to dealing with the collective threat.

Similar content being viewed by others

social norms good essay

Worldwide divergence of values

Joshua Conrad Jackson & Danila Medvedev

social norms good essay

Persistent interaction patterns across social media platforms and over time

Michele Avalle, Niccolò Di Marco, … Walter Quattrociocchi

social norms good essay

Interviews in the social sciences

Eleanor Knott, Aliya Hamid Rao, … Chana Teeger

Introduction

Societies vary extensively in the kinds and number of social norms—the unwritten social rules that guide behavior 1 , 2 —that they adopt and the extent to which people within those societies follow them. From religious ceremonies and dress codes to environmental conservation and infection-containment, we embrace an astonishing diversity of social norms. An influential theory proposes that societies with many strong social norms, and in which individuals who deviate from the script face severe social punishment, can be classified as tight, while those that are permissive, have few and weak social norms, and norm-breakers are subject to little punishment are known as loose 3 , 4 . Such differences in cultural tightness are also reflected in prevailing socio-political institutions and practices. Tighter countries, or regions, are likelier to have restrictive socio-political institutions (e.g., government, media, education, legal, and religious), stricter constraints across everyday situations (e.g., public park, library, restaurant, workplace, classroom), more incremental innovation, lower debt, and stronger metanorms (norms about punishment) among others 3 , 5 , 6 , 7 , 8 , 9 , 10 , 11 . Loose cultures are instead more open to new ideas, more predisposed to change and substantial innovation, but may have difficulties in facing collective risks. Indeed, recent work finds that looser societies had less success in limiting COVID-19 cases and deaths in the first stages of the pandemic 12 .

Given the broad practical and scientific importance of tightness-looseness, it is essential to understand what factors are associated with these differences across countries and cultures. Tightness-Looseness theory 3 contends that societies that have experienced chronic ecological and social threats—frequent disease, warfare, and environmental catastrophes—throughout history develop tighter cultures to maintain order and survive chaos and crises. In contrast, societies with less exposure to such ecological threats can afford to develop looser cultures that allow innovation and creativity at the cost of order. This core hypothesis, that social norm strength is related to the threats that nations have (or have not) historically encountered, is well supported by correlational evidence from cross-sectional surveys 3 , 6 , 7 , ethnographic datasets 8 , a long-term online experiment 13 , and a long-term survey about social distancing norms 14 . Moreover, computational models have shown that dramatic increases in threat cause tightening 15 . On the other hand, cultural evolution has been argued to be a slow process 16 , 17 , suggesting the alternative that norm strength is stable after a collective threat. The COVID-19 pandemic provides an opportunity to examine whether tightening naturally occurs or if culture remains stable in the early stages of a collective threat. This knowledge can help us not only predict the future responses of countries to similar situations and potentially identify effective interventions to deal with these crises but also to better anticipate social changes that can impact our societies for generations to come.

Here we address this question by studying a dataset on cultural tightness, social norms, and metanorms—norms about the punishment of norm-breakers 18 —and exploit variation in disease severity due to the COVID-19 pandemic to test whether tightening evolves after a collective threat. Specifically, we combine data from a survey collected between April–December 2019 (Wave 1) 5 prior to the pandemic with a repeat of the same survey, in the same countries and sampled from the same populations, that we conducted in March–July 2020 (Wave 2) during the first months of the COVID-19 pandemic. The combined data come from 30,431 respondents (samples from both students and non-students) and cover 55 cities in 43 countries (see Table  S1 for summary).

The follow-up data (Wave 2) were collected during the initial stages of the pandemic so they capture the early changes (or their stability) in norms that occurred. While this means that we cannot infer the long-run consequences of the pandemic on norms, it also presents important advantages. First, our data provide an insight into norm change under extreme circumstances—while social, political, and economic systems were in upheaval—which provides strong stimuli for change to occur potentially shaping norms. Put differently, if norm change occurs, then there is a good chance we should be able to observe this in the early stages. Second, early data give an insight into the non-equilibrium dynamics of how cultures move from one stable state to another. Third, we are able to test the boundaries of tightness-looseness theory in terms of timeline: our data indicate a lower bound on the time that may be needed for large-scale norm change to occur in response to pandemic threat. Fourth, endogeneity issues are reduced. Specifically, it reduces the possibility for other large-scale shocks to affect the data and the possibility of time varying factors (e.g. hospital infrastructure development) to confound our results.

To study whether a change in disease threat is associated with a change in norms, we study five outcomes. (i) Tightness-looseness: elicited using the standard six questions (e.g., “There are many social norms that people are supposed to abide by in this country”) with ratings standardized to control for response sets 3 , 5 . (ii) Situation-specific social norms’ strength: measured with disapproval of norm-breaking in four settings (e.g., listening to music on headphones at a funeral 19 ) and stealing shared resources 20 . (iii) Metanorm strength: for each of the prior scenarios respondents also rated the appropriateness of different responses to the norm-breaker by another individual (verbal confrontation, ostracism, gossip, physical punishment, and non-action) 5 , 18 . (iv) Frequency of punishing norm-breakers. (v) Hand washing norms: respondents indicated the situations (e.g., after shaking someone’s hand) in which people should wash their hands. Our core expectation is that these outcomes are higher after the emergence of COVID-19 than before.

These outcomes vary in their relevance to the COVID-19 pandemic. Hand hygiene is strongly related, stealing is partly related (i.e. stealing shared resources during a pandemic is particularly harmful), while others, such as listening to music on headphones at a funeral, are unrelated to the pandemic. Intuitively, norms most related to preventing disease spread should change the most. Yet tightness-looseness theory does not make such detailed predictions. Instead, it proposes the overarching hypothesis that norms and metanorms strengthen. Such a broad change may happen for two interlinked reasons: in the presence of threats, people rely more on social norms as heuristics to safely determine what to do and this increase in conformity leads to a general tightening 21 ; it is beneficial to have tight norms across the board since tightening even irrelevant norms can increase a general norm-following tendency that implies increased norm-following for the more relevant ones.

To gain a deeper insight into the mechanisms that may be associated with change, we exploit the heterogeneity across countries in their exposure to COVID-19 and we collected data on three pathways through which we conjecture that COVID-19 pandemics may shape norms. Two of these are the respondent’s beliefs about the prevalence of COVID-19 and their fear of COVID-19, as we conjecture that disease threat shapes the strength of norms through individuals’ perceptions. The final pathway concerns government policy. By implementing strict (or lenient) anti-disease policies, governments can signal to their citizens the severity of the threat. Moreover, they impose policies that change their citizens’ behavioral patterns (e.g., not shaking hands, socially isolating) and these may have consequences on social expectations and norms. While all countries in the sample have been exposed to the pandemic, the continuous variation in our collected measures helps shed light on the association between cultural change and intensity of COVID-19 pandemic. The study, including the hypotheses and analyses, was pre-registered with the Open Science Framework (see Methods).

Overall, we find that in the short term, the global threat posed by the COVID-19 pandemic was associated with a significant strengthening of social norms related to hand washing, a behavior highly relevant to limit disease spread. Contrary to our initial predictions, other established social norms governing our daily lives exhibit resilience and remain largely unchanged. In addition, cultural tightness slightly decreased accompanied by small decrease in punishment frequency. These findings suggest that the immediate impact of a global threat is selective in changing those norms that are directly relevant to cope with the threat and emphasizes the adaptive nature of societies in the face of a collective crisis.

Our analytic strategy proceeds in two stages. We first compare Wave 1 to Wave 2 averages using multilevel models with individual responses grouped on city and country. We then seek to identify the mechanisms associated with changes for only those outcomes that show significant associations which are robust across both models and sub-items. To do this we use the change across waves (Wave 2 - Wave 1) as the dependent variable as predicted by perceived prevalence, fear, and government stringency and use country-level observations and OLS regression models with heteroskedastic robust standard errors. Prevalence is measured using “What percent of people living in your province do you think have been infected with COVID-19?” and fear is the combination of three items (Cronbach’s α  = 0.84, see Methods for country-level variation). To capture variation in governmental policies, we use the Stringency Index from the Oxford COVID-19 Government Response Tracker 22 .This second stage of our analysis is similar in spirit to a difference-in-differences design but differs to the classical setup in that we have no entirely untreated control group—all countries in our sample were to some extent affected by the emergence of the COVID-19 pandemic—and instead of a treated and untreated group, we have many groups with different COVID-19 pandemic exposure levels. All analyses account for age, gender, and student status to control for any sample composition differences between the waves (see Methods). We also check whether deaths and cases, which account for the different levels of COVID-19 across countries, affect our results and find that they do not (see  Supplementary Materials ).

After our analyses were conducted, we added equivalence tests using the two one-sided tests procedure 23 , 24 , 25 to identify whether significant changes that we find are practically meaningful and if non-significant findings provide evidence for the absence of a meaningful change. In this procedure, we specify a series of smallest effect size of interest (SESOI) and then compare Wave 1 to Wave 2 changes and the mechanism associations to these SESOIs. Our SESOIs were set ex-post and not pre-registered and, given the lack of existing literature, or even data, concerning the changes in our outcome variables, there is large uncertainty about how the SESOI should be set (see Methods for discussion). Consequently, we use a benchmark-based approach and set the SESOI to Cohen’s d  = 0.1 (a small effect size 26 ) for our main individual-level analyses and β = ± 0.10 (a small effect size 26 ) for the mechanisms analyses (see Methods for details).

Tightness-Looseness

Tightness decreases (x̅ 1  = 1.90, x̅ 2  = 1.81; Fig.  1A ; Table  S1 ) although the effect size is small (Cohen’s d  = 0.11; b  = −0.028, 95% CI = [−0.047; −0.009], p  = 0.003; Table  S2 ), and the change is heterogeneous across countries (varying slope model: b  = −0.037, 95% CI = [−0.073; −0.001], p  = 0.042; random effect variance τ 11  = 0.01; Table  S2 ; Figure  S2 ). In most countries, the change is not significant (81.4%; 35/43), it is negative in 16.3% (7/43) and even positive in 2.3% (1/43) (Fig.  S2 ). Countries that have higher fear levels towards COVID-19 reduced their tightness the most ( b  = −0.081, 95% CI = [−0.157; −0.005], p  = 0.037; Table  S3 ) though this association is small. Perceived prevalence and government stringency are not significantly associated with change in tightness-looseness ( b  = −0.003, 95% CI = [−0.010; 0.003], p  = 0.306 and b  = 0.0003, 95% CI = [−0.002; 0.001], p  = 0.721, respectively; Table  S3 ).

figure 1

( A ) tightness-looseness, ( B ) situation-specific norms, ( C ) metanorms, ( D ) punishing frequency and ( E ) hand washing norms. Tightness and punishing frequency slightly decrease  while hand washing norms increase after the emergence of the COVID−19 pandemic. Other social and metanorms display non-robust changes. Change in appropriateness items is computed by scaling the average change in each country to the maximum possible change. Hence, the index can take values from −1 to +1. Red and black dots depict sampled cities; red dots represent cities sampled in both waves while black dots refer to cities only sampled in Wave 2. Indonesia is not included in hand washing norm data because of a mistake in the survey translation (see Methods).

Situation-specific norms

Situation-specific norm strength decrease slightly from Wave 1 to Wave 2 (x̅ 1  = 1.15, x̅ 2  = 1.12; Fig.  1B ; Cohen’s d  = 0.04; b  = −0.017, 95% CI = [−0.028; −0.006], p  = 0.003; Table  S4 ) but this is not robust as it becomes non-significant when allowing for heterogeneous effects across countries (varying slope model: b  = −0.011, 95% CI = [−0.054; 0.033], p  = 0.628, τ 11  = 0.02; Table  S4 ; Fig.  S3 ). Analyses conducted on the five specific norm-breaking scenarios separately also show no consistent pattern (three are negative and two are positive) and the size of the changes is minimal (Table  S5 ). These results demonstrate that COVID-19 has no consistent effect on situation-specific norms, and, even where it does, the effect is minor.

We report similar findings for metanorms (Fig.  1C ). There is no significant change across the waves (x̅ 1  = 2.15, x̅ 2  = 2.17; Cohen’s d  = 0.03; b  = 0.006, 95% CI = [−0.001; 0.013], p  = 0.120; Table  S6 ; Fig.  S4 ) and there is little consistency across the different kinds of punishments: approval of ostracism slightly increases ( b  = 0.028, 95% CI = [0.015; 0.040], p  < 0.001; Table  S7 ) while gossip approval slightly decreases ( b  = −0.024, 95% CI = [−0.035; −0.013], p  < 0.001; Table  S7 ). Estimates from our models show no significant change in verbal confrontation, physical confrontation, and non-action (reverse coded) items.

Punishing frequency

In contrast, we find a statistically significant decrease in frequency of punishment (x̅ 1  = 3.00, x̅ 2  = 2.96; Fig. 1D ; Cohen’s d  = −0.07; b  = −0.034, 95% CI = [−0.047; −0.022], p  < 0.001;  Table  S8 ). This effect remains negative and significant with a varying slopes model ( b  = −0.031, 95% CI = [−0.059; −0.003], p  = 0.028, τ 11  = 0.01; Table  S8 ) and it is generally consistent across sub-items with the frequency of gossip ( b  = −0.091, 95% CI = [−0.112; −0.070], p  < 0.001; Table  S9 ) and confronting ( b  = −0.021, 95% CI = [−0.041; −0.002], p  = 0.035; Table  S9 ) both decreasing. Perhaps due to distancing and self-isolating measures, avoiding shows no significant change ( b  = 0.011, 95% CI = [−0.012; 0.034], p  = 0.335; Table  S9 ). Frequency of gossiping tended to decrease more in countries with a higher level of fear of COVID-19 ( b  = −0.139, 95% CI = [−0.261; −0.016], p  = 0.028; Table S10 ). The other change in punishing frequency categories, including the overall index, are not associated with the mechanism variables (Table  S10 ).

Hand washing norms

Hand washing norms increase on average (x̅ 1  = 4.07, x̅ 2  = 4.50; Fig. 1E ; Cohen’s d  = 0.32; b  = 0.420, 95% CI = [0.390; 0.450], p  < 0.001; Table  S11 ) and in almost every country (41 out of 42 countries, Fig.  1E ; all countries when considering only COVID relevant items, Fig.  S1 ). Results remain unchanged when accounting for country-level heterogeneity (varying slope model: b  = 0.433, 95% CI = [0.361; 0.506], p  < 0.001; τ 11  = 0.04; Table  S11 Fig.  S3 ). The increase is most strongly associated in the categories perceived to be relevant to reducing COVID-19 spread (Table  S12 ). Fear of COVID−19 accounts for most of the increase across all items ( b  = 0.040, 95% CI = [0.004; 0.076], p  = 0.032; Table  S13 ) and this effect becomes stronger when predicting only the change of COVID-relevant items ( b  = 0.092, 95% CI = [0.035; 0.148], p  = 0.002; Table  S13 ). Perceived prevalence does not predict hand washing norm change both when considering all items ( b  = 0.002, 95% CI = [−0.0003; 0.0049], p  = 0.085; Table  S13 ) and relevant items ( b  = 0.004, 95% CI = [−0.001; 0.008], p  = 0.086; Table  S13 ) but does so after shaking hands ( b  = 0.004, 95% CI = [0.001; 0.008], p  = 0.015; Table  S13 ). Governmental stringency does not predict change in hand washing norms ( b  = 0.0002, 95% CI = [−0.001; 0.001], p = 0.723; Table  S13 ).

Equivalence tests

For tightness-looseness, situation-specific norms, metanorms, and punishing frequency, we find that the between wave variation observed are statistically equivalent (all p  < 0.001) implying that the differences are statistically smaller than the SESOI we set. For hand washing norms, we find that the change is statistically greater than the SESOI, exceeding the upper equivalence bound (see Methods for details). For the mechanisms analyses, fear of COVID-19 is significantly associated with the outcomes of tightness-looseness and hand washing norms while all the other relevant mechanism coefficients are not significantly different to zero. Yet they all overlap with either the upper or lower equivalence bounds meaning that there is insufficient evidence to conclude a negligible effect (see Methods for details).

Our findings show that even a crisis as profound, global, and multifaceted as COVID-19 does not dramatically change the social norms of cultures in the short-term, except those believed to directly reduce disease spread, hand washing norms in this case. Nevertheless, and contrary to our expectations, we find a small decrease in tightness and punishing frequency and no significant robust changes in most social norms and metanorms in the early stages of the pandemic. Importantly, the non-significant findings are due to the absence of substantial changes and not because of a lack of power. What explains these results? One possibility is that the key prediction of tightness-looseness theory needs to be revised. Due to existing large-scale studies across multiple fields, which support the association between threat and tightness-looseness 3 , 6 , 7 , 8 , 9 , 10 , 11 , 12 and more broadly social norm strength 13 , 27 , 28 , we do not think this is the likeliest explanation. Instead, we think that there are more probable interpretations.

A distinct possibility is that cultural evolution is slow and extensive time is necessary between a collective threat and a subsequent change in cultures 16 , 17 . Indeed, if cultures do change slowly, we may expect specific cultural evolutionary mismatches—i.e., when traits that evolved in one environment become disadvantageous in a different environment 29 , 30 . Specifically, tight societies that have historically experienced threat may have traits that are better matched to dealing with a collective threat such as COVID-19, whereas looser societies would experience more of a cultural mismatch, as evidenced in 12 . Another interpretation is that different threats may tighten different norms, namely those most relevant to overcoming the specific immediate threats: pandemics may make hygiene norms stronger while earthquakes may, instead, increase norms of helping. This would be consistent with an experimental study which found that a risk of collective loss increased the strength of norms concerning cooperation 13 . Over time, this would create a mosaic of norms that together correspond to the emergent notion of tightness. If correct, cultures that face a variety of threats will be those that end up the tightest. Another possibility is that pathogen threats, which are abstract and invisible, have particular characteristics and produce different tightening dynamics than threats which are concrete and visible (e.g., earthquakes, terrorism, or warfare) 31 , 32 . The former are harder to assess, potentially causing uncertainty and panic that may have led to egoistic behavior during early stages of the pandemic. Indeed, as extensively reported by the mass media, there was hoarding of resources in the early stages of the pandemic 33 , 34 and recent work finds evidence for the erosion of social trust 35 .

These conclusions should also be considered in light of the limitations to our study. First, we use convenience samples (albeit both students and non-students). While this is unlikely to have substantial implications on our between-wave estimates, since the samples are broadly similar between the waves, it should be kept in mind when generalizing our findings to the broader populations. Specifically, it is possible that social norm change, or a lack thereof, occurred differently outside of cities, varied with socio-economic factors, or that younger people, who are overrepresented in our samples, experience fewer health-risks and our findings may not generalize to more senior people or those facing health issues. Second, our design allows us to avoid key endogeneity issues that are present in prior work, but cannot cleanly identify causal effects. More specifically, our first-stage analyses, comparing Wave 1 to Wave 2 averages, allows us to exclude reverse causality and country-constant confounders but it cannot exclude time-trends (e.g. changes in norm strength occurring over time irrespective of the pandemic). Our second-stage analyses, using perceived prevalence, fear, and government stringency to predict changes in the outcomes, reduces the possibility that such time-trends (or other confounding factors) are responsible for the observed changes as these would need to be correlated with our predictors and changes in social norms. In addition, we find little evidence for pre-existing time trends in tightness-looseness (see Methods and Fig.  S7 ). Still, we do not have the power in the mechanisms analyses to detect small effects and cannot entirely identify causality.

Our sample includes data from a first study wave collected before the breakout of the pandemic (April–December 2019, Wave 1 5 ) and data from a second wave (March–July 2020, Wave 2) that we collected during the initial stages of the COVID−19 emergence. For comparability of samples across waves and among countries, we set out to collect data from approximately 200 college students at least in a major city in each country, which was achieved in all countries (Table  S1 ). To assess the robustness of the country-level measures obtained from these samples, we complemented the main sampling strategy by collecting additional data from non-student samples.

When administering Wave 2, we aimed to collect data also from a subset of participants who took part in Wave 1 study. These participants were marked as “experienced” participants and were re-contacted (e.g. through laboratory recruitment systems). For six locations (Bosnia-Herzegovina, Canada, Colombia, Czech Republic, Italy, United States), we were able to recruit participants who had participated in Wave 1 but without matching their responses across waves. For two locations (Israel and Poland), we were able to uniquely identify participants and match their responses. Privacy and anonymity were nevertheless preserved in these samples. This allowed us to check whether experience of participation affects our findings. When specifically checking among participants matched across waves we find non-significant results that go in the same direction (see end of Methods).

In our analyses, we considered a response valid if a participant correctly passed an attention check placed at the end of the survey (i.e., participants had to click a specific item response). We discarded observations because of missing responses (4074 in Wave 1, 4660 in Wave 2) or failed attention checks (197 in Wave 1, 202 in Wave 2). We additionally excluded participants who declared an age under 18 (157 in Wave 1, 222 in Wave 2). The final dataset includes responses from 43 countries, 55 locations (six of which were sampled only in Wave 1, while only one sampled exclusively in Wave 2), and 30,431 valid respondents (see Table  S1 ).

We used the survey administered in 5 to preserve comparability, with the sole addition of a small number of questions (at the end of the survey precluding any effects on the prior questions) regarding COVID-19 fear and prevalence, desired Tightness-Looseness measures, generalized trust, and risk aversion. The survey was translated into 30 different languages, following the standard practice of independent translation and back-translation. The study was conducted anonymously online using Qualtrics. The English version of the survey is publicly available as part of our pre-registration ( https://osf.io/9ve4t ). Our study is a survey therefore no randomization occurred and some of the investigators were not blinded to the study’s hypotheses.

All participants gave their informed consent and we complied with all relevant ethical regulations. Approval of the study protocol was obtained from ethics committees and institutional review boards where required including for the University of Melbourne (Australia), Queen’s University at Kingston (Canada), Universidad de los Andes (Colombia), Institute of Psychology, Czech Academy of Sciences (Czech Republic), Universidad San Francisco de Quito (Ecuador), United Research Ethics Committee of Psychology (Hungary), Monk Prayogshala (India), Trinity College Dublin (Ireland), Open University of Israel (Israel), LUISS University (Italy), United States International University - Africa (Kenya), Sunway University (Malaysia), University of Amsterdam (Netherlands), SWPS University (Poland), Universidade de Lisboa (Portugal), National University of Singapore (Singapore), University of Colombo (Sri Lanka), Koc University (Turkey), American University of Sharjah (United Arab Emirates), Brunel University London (United Kingdom), University of Kent (United Kingdom), University of South Carolina (United States of America), and New York University (United States of America). Ethical approval was not sought in countries where the approval received for the study conducted in Wave 1 5 was considered sufficient or where local legislation did not require ethical approval in the first place.

Study preregistration

We pre-registered our study in two phases. Our initial pre-registration was submitted before data gathering ( https://osf.io/zvdkt/ ) (March 23rd 2020) and contained a design and provisional data analysis plan. Due to the short timeframe before data collection began, the analysis plan was only provisional. Our second pre-registration, which was submitted after the data were collected but before the data were examined or analyzed (October 22nd 2020), contains a detailed analysis plan that we completely followed ( https://osf.io/9ve4t ).

The hypotheses that we pre-registered and test are the following:

H1: Tightness-Looseness levels in Wave 2 will be higher on average than in Wave 1.

H2a: Perceived threat will be positively associated with change in tightness.

H2b: Perceived prevalence will be positively associated with change in tightness.

H2c: A stricter governmental response will be positively associated with change in tightness.

H3a: Punishments, on average, are perceived as more appropriate.

H3b: People are likelier to engage in punishing norm violations.

In addition to the aforementioned hypotheses, we investigate the differences in situation specific norms and a set of items measuring hand hygiene norms between waves 1 and 2 to provide a fuller understanding in social norm changes. Furthermore, to study the mechanisms for hand hygiene norms and punishment change, we complement our analyses by exploring the moderating role of perceived threat, COVID-19 prevalence, and governmental stringency on the change in hand hygiene norms and frequency of punishment, both of which show consistent changes from Wave 1 to Wave 2.

Survey measures

We measured the following variables through survey questions. These were elicited in both Wave 1 and Wave 2 unless stated otherwise.

Tightness-looseness scores

We compute tightness-looseness scores (TL) following individual-level standardization as in past work 3 , 5 . Standardization is needed to adjust for cross-cultural variation in response sets given that some cultures are more likely to provide extreme responses or acquiesce to survey items than others 3 , 36 . Following guidelines from cross-cultural psychology 36 , 37 , and from data published in the first wave 5 , we calculate appropriateness scores by averaging each individual’s responses to a large set of heterogeneous items (i.e. 50 appropriateness items that all used the same response scale, from extremely inappropriate to extremely appropriate). This score is then subtracted from participants’ responses in the tightness-looseness questionnaire (6 items from ref. 3 ). The final individual TL scores are computed by averaging the adjusted 6 items. After transformation, TL scores display an overall average x̅ = 1.85, standard deviation s = 0.81, min = −2.26, max = 5.25. Differently from 5 , we did not impute missing TL data. This resulted in tiny differences in TL scores between studies (difference between mean TL scores = 0.01) that do not affect the validity of our results. The correlation between our TL scores and those appearing in 5 is essentially perfect (Spearman test, r  = 0.997, p  < 0.001). Standardizing tightness-looseness scores does not affect our results (checked for all tightness-looseness analyses reported in the manuscript). Furthermore, the correlation between standardized and non-standardized measures of TL is high and significant ( r  = 0.84 for Wave 1 measures, r  = 0.85 for Wave 2 measures, p  < 0.001 in both cases).

Given our empirical interest in assessing the change in tightness-looseness associated with the emergence of the pandemic, we also checked whether TL scores changed or not between 2000–2003 (Wave 0), using data from 3 , and 2019 (Wave 1) 5 , and 2020 (Wave 2). We find that tightness-looseness scores have remained unchanged in almost all countries since 2000–2003 (Wave 0 to Wave 1: r  = 0.89; Wave 0 to Wave 2: r  = 0.88, all p < 0.001) and that there is strong stability in the ordering of countries (Kendall rank test, t  = 0.752, p  < 0.001, Fig.  S7 panels A, B) implying that TL is a stable measure. More formally, to check whether trends in TL scores were similar across our countries pre-pandemic, with respect to their post-pandemic COVID-19 intensity, we use the following model:

Where TL indicates tightness-looseness from country c , at time t; Wave are dummy variables indicating the study wave (Wave 1 or Wave 2; Wave 0 is the baseline), and Covid Severity is fear of COVID-19, perceived cases, actual COVID-19 cases, or COVID-19 deaths (we check each sequentially). If there are no systematic differences in trend pre-pandemic then δ 1  = 0. This would indicate that countries that were later affected by the pandemic with heterogenous intensities had TL change that followed the same pattern between Wave 0 and Wave 1. We find no evidence for systematic differences in trends of TL scores between 2000–2003 and 2019 according to later COVID-19 severity (Table  S14 ).

Participants’ appropriateness ratings are measured with their responses to five scenarios that cover potential norm-violating behavior in several domains concerning cooperation and out-of-place everyday behavior (see Analysis Plan of the pre-registration Analysis Plan). Ratings of the appropriateness of each item were elicited through a six-point scale, ranging from extremely inappropriate (coded 0) to extremely appropriate (coded 5). Average rating across countries is x̅ = 1.13, standard deviation s  = 0.60, min = 0, max = 5.

Metanorm scenarios

Metanorms were collected for each situation (five in total) based on survey items reported in our pre-registered analyses plan. Items covered five different punishment behaviors for each situation (hence, a total of 25 items, see Analysis Plan of pre-registration Analysis Plan), which are: verbal and physical confrontation, gossip, non-action (reverse coded) and ostracism, and we collected participants’ ratings of the appropriateness of each. Appropriateness was elicited through a six-point scale, ranging from extremely inappropriate (coded 0) to extremely appropriate (coded 5). Each punishment behavior is used as a separate dependent variable. Average appropriateness across countries is x̅ = 2.22, standard deviation s = 1.25, min = 0, max = 5.

We consider three survey items eliciting the frequency at which respondents engaging in confronting, gossiping, and ostracizing someone who behaves inappropriately. Frequency of punishment was elicited using a five-point scale ranging from never (coded 1) to always (coded 5). We analyzed these all together (with mixed effects at the scenario level) and also conducted separate analyses for each item separately. Average frequency of punishment across countries is x̅ = 2.98, standard deviation s = 0.59, min = 1, max = 5.

Hand washing norms

Our survey asked participants in which of six situations they think people should wash hands. These situations are: before eating a meal, after eating a meal, after defecating, after urinating, when they come home, and after shaking someone’s hand. Hand washing norms are analyzed using as both the number of situations considered as appropriate (number of ticks) as well as whether a participant considered a given situation as appropriate (participant ticked or not a given situation). Because of a translation mistake in our survey, one country (Indonesia) has been excluded from all the analyses of these items. Average number of appropriate situations across countries was x̅ = 4.28, standard deviation  s  = 1.30, min = 0, max = 6.

Fear of COVID-19

Our measure of COVID-19 fear comes from the Wave 2 survey. In particular, respondents answered three items: “How concerned are you by the spread of the new Coronavirus (COVID-19)?” “How much fear do you have by the spread of the Coronavirus?” “How dangerous do you think the Coronavirus is?”. Participants responded on a six-point scale. We then compute the average over items. Average COVID-19 fear is x̅ = 4.42, standard deviation s = 0.41, min = 3.42, max = 5.20. Following our pre-registration, we checked internal consistency of the items listed above reporting (Cronbach’s α = 0.84). We additionally computed Cronbach’s alphas for each country separately. Estimated values range from 0.58 (Kenya) to 0.90 (Poland) (see below for full list). The cross-country average is 0.80 ( s  = 0.07) which is close to the value obtained when merging all countries in our sample. Since estimated Cronbach alphas fall within the range of satisfactory internal consistency, throughout our main analyses, we averaged these items to create a single variable at the individual level. The only country with alpha <0.60 is Kenya; all our analyses reported in the manuscript are robust and do not substantially change when excluding Kenya from the dataset.

The full list of countries’ alphas is: ARE: 0.81, ARG: 0.76, ARM: 0.82, AUS: 0.78, BIH: 0.83, BRA: 0.79, CAN: 0.82, CHL: 0.80, CHN: 0.77, COL: 0.80, CZE: 0.85, DEU: 0.86, ECU: 0.75, ESP: 0.79, EST: 0.87, FIN: 0.84, GBR: 0.86, GRC: 0.85, HUN: 0.87, IDN: 0.83, IND: 0.71, IRL: 0.84, ISL: 0.77, ISR: 0.90, ITA: 0.86, JPN: 0.85, KEN: 0.58, KOR: 0.87, LKA: 0.63, MYS: 0.66, NGA: 0.65, NLD: 0.78, POL: 0.91, PRT: 0.88, RUS: 0.77, SAU: 0.84, SGP: 0.82, SWE: 0.80, TUR: 0.84, UKR: 0.89, USA: 0.82, VNM: 0.83. PER: items missing due to error in data collection.

Perceived COVID-19 prevalence

Our measure of disease prevalence was elicited with the Wave 2 survey question “What percent of people living in your province do you think have been infected with COVID-19? Please do not look up actual statistics to answer this question—just enter your best guess” (0–100). Average perceived COVID-19 prevalence across countries is x̅ = 21.87, standard deviation s = 7.05, min = 8.53, max = 42.65.

External measures

We measured the following variables through external data sources that we matched with our survey data.

Stringency Index

Our measure of the intensity of government response to COVID-19 is the Stringency Index from the Oxford COVID-19 Government Response Tracker 22 . The measure contains indicators reporting the severity of containment and closures (e.g. school and workplace closures and restrictions on gathering size; see items C1-C8 in ref. 23 ) and public information campaigns (item H1 in ref. 23 ). The Stringency Index can vary between 0 and 100. We match participants’ responses to our survey with Stringency Index data calculated on the same day. Average stringency across countries is x̅ = 78.12, standard deviation  s = 13.54, min = 32.77, max = 99.48.

Deaths and cases

We use COVID-19 deaths and cases per million from Our World in Data 38 (downloaded November 2020). Data were matched with participants’ responses to our survey based on day of response (thus case and deaths data run from March–July 2020). Average of deaths across countries and periods is x̅ = 47.88 per million,  standard deviation  s = 103.70, min = 0.05, max = 481.99. Average of cases across countries and periods is x̅ = 834.95 per million, standard deviation   s  = 1067.72, min = 1.98, max = 4389.68.

Computed measures

The following measures were computed based on changes between Wave 1 and Wave 2. In addition to the pre-registered test ΔTightness-Looseness, we did this only for those variables that showed robust changes between the waves (see Analyses).

ΔTightness-looseness, Δpunishing, and Δhand washing

When computing change in TL, we averaged individual scores for each country and compute the difference between Wave 2 and Wave 1 values (Wave 2–Wave 1). A similar procedure is followed for computing change in other items. For hand washing and punishing items (frequency of punishment) we computed changes across waves both for each individual item and for the average of all items.

We started by analyzing the between-wave changes in Tightness-Looseness, situation-specific norms, metanorms, punishing, and hand washing norms. Then, for those changes that are shown to be robust (across sub-items and model specifications, including with random slopes and with controls for COVID-19 cases and deaths), we examine the mechanisms predicting a change in our variables of interest (ΔTightness-Looseness, Δpunishing, and Δhand washing). The models used for both stages are outlined below. In addition to these models, we replicated all of our analyses with the addition of random slopes to allow for country-level variation of the effect associated with COVID-19 pandemic. For these, we additionally report τ 11 , the variance of the main parameter of interest ( Wave 2) to shed light on the heterogeneity of the effect due to COVID-19 pandemic among countries. Moreover, we also conducted these analyses controlling for deaths and cases (adjusted to each country population size) to account for the different levels of COVID-19 pandemic across the countries and this does not affect our results. For all coefficient estimates we report the results from two-sided t -tests. All tests meet the relevant assumptions. We do not adjust for multiple comparisons.

Tightness-looseness, situation-specific norms, and punishing

We use multilevel models with random intercepts at the individual ( n  ≈ 29,000), city ( n  = 55), and country ( n  = 43) level. Put formally, to test Hypothesis 1, we estimate the following multilevel model with varying intercepts at the country ( c ), city ( k ) and individual ( i ) level:

where Z is the vector of control variables to account for possible between-wave sample variation (age, gender, and student/non-student status), Wave 2 is a dummy variable taking value 1 when an observation was collected in Wave 2 and 0 otherwise. Our analyses for situation-specific norms, punishing, and hand washing norms follow the same model structure with the dependent variable changed to those variables.

We use multilevel models with random intercepts at the country ( c ), city ( k ), scenario ( s ), and individual ( i ) levels and implement the following model specification:

where A is the appropriateness score given by individual i to the punishment scenario s , in country c , city k . N is the average appropriateness at the location level that participants have given to the norm violation of scenario s (see also Methods in ref. 3 ) and Z is a vector of demographic controls (age, gender, and student/non-student status).

We used two approaches to test hand washing norms. First, to model the number of ticked categories we use the same model structure as Eq.  2 but with the dependent variable replaced with the number of ticks given by participant i , in county c , and city k . Second, to test the probability of ticking each single situation we use a multilevel logit regression with random intercepts at the country and city level:

Where H is the odds of participant i , in country c , and city k , ticking that it is appropriate to wash hands for a given setting. Z is a vector of demographic controls (age, gender, and student/non-student status).

ΔTightness-looseness, Δpunishing frequency, and Δhand washing

These analyses are conducted using heteroskedasticity-robust OLS regressions with observations at the country level. Observations are country-level as the dependent variable is Wave 1 to Wave 2 change in a given country. We do not use city-level because in a small number of countries different cities were sampled between Wave 1 and Wave 2. Put formally we estimate the following model for ΔTightness-Looseness:

where Fear is fear of COVID-19, PC is perceived cases of COVID-19, and SI is the Stringency Index from the Oxford COVID-19 Government Response Tracker.

We performed similar analyses for the change in hand washing and punishment. In particular, for the former, we conducted analyses for the change in the number of ticks for (i) all items, (ii) specifically for items that were not directly related to the COVID-19 pandemic (before meal, after meal, after defecating, and after urinating), (iii) specifically for items that are directly related to the pandemic (after shaking hands and after coming home), and (iv) each item separately that is directly related to the pandemic (Table  S12 ).

For the items measuring punishing frequency, we estimate the change in responses for each single item individually (Table  S9 ), and change in the mean of all of our 3 items (grand mean change) (Table  S10 ).

Tightness-looseness change for tracked participants

We were able to perfectly match responses to our survey across waves for two locations in our sample: Israel and Poland. Below, we report the results from a robustness check aimed to test tightness score decrease.

For our Israel sub-sample of tracked participants ( N  = 57), tightness scores decrease on average of 0.16 (Cohen’s d  = 0.17, Wilcoxon paired samples r  = 0.172), yet the change is not significant (Wilcoxon paired samples test, V  = 30, p  = 0.195). For our Poland sub-sample ( N  = 10), tightness scores decrease by about 0.12 (Cohen’s d  = 0.15), but the change is not significant (Wilcoxon paired samples test, V  = 30, p  = 0.85). We interpret results from our sub-samples as highly noisy but consistent with our general results from the full dataset showing a small decrease in tightness scores.

For 6 locations (Bosnia-Herzegovina, Canada, Colombia, Czech Republic, Italy, United States), we were able to distinguish responses coming from participants who previously participated in the first wave, but were not able to match the id of each responses. By running multilevel linear regression models, we report evidence of no significant change in tightness-looseness scores for these sub-populations ( b  = 0.046, p  = 0.222).

Power analysis

The main aim of this study was to examine whether the pandemic was associated with a systematic change in tightness-looseness (TL) scores compared to pre-pandemic scores. To make sure that our sample is large enough to detect small changes in TL, we compute the power achieved based on the mixed effects model in Eq. 2 . We adopt the common convention that a small effect be equivalent to a Cohen’s d of at least 0.10. From our sample, it means that the average TL score changes by at least 10% of its standard deviation, that is a change in TL of 0.08 (TL  s  = 0.80). By using the R package “simr”, we estimate the 95% CI of achieved power from the model in Eq. 2 to be 95% CI = [96.38; 100] (predictor “Wave2”, α = 0.05, 100 simulations).

We then perform sensitivity analysis to provide evidence of sufficient achieved power for models testing the change in TL scores. Given a sample of 28,374 individuals, a significance level of α = 0.05, and a desired power 0.80, we estimate the minimum detectable change in raw TL scores of 0.025 (equivalent to Cohen’s d  = 0.03).

We also perform sensitivity analysis for the proposed mechanisms variables (Eq.  5 ). Given a sample of 41 countries, a significance level of α = 0.05, and a desired power 0.80, we estimate the minimum detectable effect size f². Results show that the minimum effects that could be detected are of medium to large size f² = 0.2 (two sided) for the proposed mediating variables.

We performed equivalence tests for all the Wave 1 to Wave 2 change analyses following the two one-sided test (TOST) procedure 23 , 24 , 25 . To set the smallest effect size of interest (SESOI) it is recommended to use substantive motivations (e.g. prior findings in the literature) 23 , 24 . Yet, for our analyses, we were unable to identify clear substantive bases for setting the SESOI. For instance, comparable meta-norm measures do not exist, to our knowledge, while for tightness-looseness, there is only one other source for comparable large-scale cross-country data 3 but this is solely available in a transformed form making a comparison in mean change to our waves meaningless (see Supplementary Note  1 ). Given this absence of comparable prior empirical evidence for setting the SESOIs, we consider a Cohen’s d  = 0.10 as the SESOI for changes in our measures over time. While for all mechanism analyses, we considered standardized betas as effect size measure, and consider a threshold of β  = ±0.10 (a small effect size 26 ) as the SESOI benchmark for all mechanisms tested.

We conducted the TOST procedure (set at the 5% significance level) using the coefficients and standard errors derived from the model estimates displayed in the main text and supplementary materials . For example, when analyzing the SESOI for TL, we estimate the equivalent change Δ in the raw scale corresponding to d  = 0.10. The coefficient estimate and standard error are drawn from Model 1 (Table  S2 ) and the TOST procedure is applied. The SESOIs of all other norm measures are calculated by applying the same reasoning and the TOSTs are conducted in the same way. For each equivalence test, we report the smallest magnitude t- value from among the two one-sided tests performed.

Tightness-looseness

We find a significant difference between our estimate of TL change and the SESOI (Δ = ±0.08, t (28369) = 5.53, p  < 0.001) such that the relevant coefficient ( b  = −0.028, 90% CI = [−0.047; −0.009]) is contained within the upper and lower equivalence bounds. This indicates that although there is a significant decrease in TL from Wave 1 to Wave 2 the change is statistically equivalent.

We find a significant difference between our estimate of situation-specific norms change and the within-country SESOI (Δ = ±0.06, t (142531) = 7.802, p  < 0.001) such that the relevant coefficient ( b  = −0.017, 90% CI = [−0.028; −0.006]) is contained within the upper and lower equivalence bounds. This indicates that while we find a significant decrease in situation-specific norms from Wave 1 to Wave 2, the change is statistically equivalent.

We find a significant difference between our estimate of metanorms change and the SESOI (Δ = ±0.05, t (484665) = −12.925, p  < 0.001) such that the relevant coefficient ( b  = 0.006, 90% CI = [−0.001; 0.012]) is contained within the upper and lower equivalence bounds. This implies that the change in metanorms is not significant from Wave 1 to Wave 2 and statistically equivalent.

We find a significant difference between our estimate of punishing frequency change and the SESOI ( Δ = ±0.1, t (85490) = 9.603, p  < 0.001) such that the relevant coefficient ( b  = −0.034, 90% CI = [−0.047; −0.022]) is contained within the upper and lower equivalence bounds. This means that, although we find a statistically significant decrease in punishing frequency, the change is statistically equivalent.

We find a significant difference between our estimate of hand washing norms change and the SESOI (Δ = ±0.13, t (28134) = −49.84, p  < 0.001) such that the relevant coefficient ( b  = 0.420, 90% CI = [0.390; 0.450]) is above the upper equivalence bound. This implies that the change in hand washing norms is significant from Wave 1 to Wave 2 and not statistically equivalent.

Mechanism analyses

When running the equivalence tests for the factors included in the mechanism analysis of the change in TL scores , we find that all standardized coefficients of our factors (Fear of COVID-19, β = −0.283, 90% CI [−0.503; −0.063]; Perceived Prevalence, β = −0.201, 90% CI [−0.526; 0.124]; Gov. Stringency, β = −0.036, 90% CI [−0.205; 0.133]) overlap with either the upper or lower equivalence bounds. This means that there is insufficient evidence to conclude a negligible effect.

The same analyses run for the change in hand washing norms give similar results in terms of equivalence. The coefficient associated with Fear of COVID-19 ( β = 0.352, 90% CI = [0.087; 0.618]), Perceived Prevalence ( β = 0.343, 90% CI [0.017; 0.669]) as well as Gov. Stringency ( β = −0.058, 90% CI [−0.333; 0.216]) overlap with either the upper or lower bound of the equivalence interval indicating that there is insufficient evidence to conclude a negligible effect.

Likewise, results from the equivalence tests for the change in punishing frequency show that the coefficient associated with Fear of COVID−19 ( β = −0.080, 90% CI = [−0.2314; 0.071]), Perceived Prevalence ( β = 0.008, 90% CI [−0.241; 0.257]) as well as Gov. Stringency ( β = −0.096, 90% CI [−0.255; 0.062]) overlap with either the upper or lower bound of the equivalence interval indicating that there is insufficient evidence to conclude a negligible effect.

Reporting summary

Further information on research design is available in the  Nature Portfolio Reporting Summary linked to this article.

Data availability

The data generated in this study have been deposited in the Open Science Framework ( https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/STKFR ). Non-experimental data included in our datasets (i.e., intensity of government response to COVID-19 is the Stringency Index, COVID-19 deaths and cases per million) are taken from the Oxford COVID−19 Government Response Tracker 22 and Our World in Data 38 (downloaded November 2020). Wave 0 data are from 3 and  Wave 1 data are from 5 .

Code availability

The survey and analysis code are available at the Open Science Framework ( https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/STKFR ).

Bicchieri, C. The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms (Cambridge University Press, 2006).

Elster, J. The Cement of Society: A Survey of Social Order (Cambridge University Press, 1989).

Gelfand, M. J. et al. Differences between tight and loose cultures: a 33-nation study. Science 332 , 1100–1104 (2011).

Article   CAS   PubMed   ADS   Google Scholar  

Pelto, P. J. The differences between “tight” and “loose” societies. Trans.-action 5 , 37–40 (1968).

Google Scholar  

Eriksson, K. et al. Perceptions of the appropriate response to norm violation in 57 societies. Nat. Commun. 12 , 1481 (2021).

Article   CAS   PubMed   PubMed Central   ADS   Google Scholar  

Chua, R. Y. J., Huang, K. G. & Jin, M. Mapping cultural tightness and its links to innovation, urbanization, and happiness across 31 provinces in China. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116 , 6720–6725 (2019).

Harrington, J. R. & Gelfand, M. J. Tightness–looseness across the 50 united states. Proc. Natl Acad Sci. USA 111 , 7990–7995 (2014).

Jackson, J. C., Gelfand, M. & Ember, C. R. A global analysis of cultural tightness in non-industrial societies. Proc. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci. 287 , 20201036 (2020).

Article   Google Scholar  

Chua, R. Y. J., Roth, Y. & Lemoine, J.-F. The impact of culture on creativity: how cultural tightness and cultural distance affect global innovation crowdsourcing work. Adm. Sci. Q. 60 , 189–227 (2015).

Jackson, J. C., Gelfand, M., De, S. & Fox, A. The loosening of American culture over 200 years is associated with a creativity–order trade-off. Nat. Hum. Behav. 3 , 244–250 (2019).

Article   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Jackson, J. C. et al. Ecological and cultural factors underlying the global distribution of prejudice. PLoS ONE 14 , e0221953 (2019).

Article   CAS   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Gelfand, M. J. et al. The relationship between cultural tightness–looseness and COVID-19 cases and deaths: a global analysis. Lancet Planet. Health 5 , e135–e144 (2021).

Article   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Szekely, A. et al. Evidence from a long-term experiment that collective risks change social norms and promote cooperation. Nat. Commun. 12 , 5452 (2021).

Vriens, E., Andrighetto, G. & Tummolini, L. Risk, sanctions and norm change: the formation and decay of social distancing norms. Philos Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B. Biol. Sci. 379 , 20230035 (2024).

Roos, P., Gelfand, M., Nau, D. & Lun, J. Societal threat and cultural variation in the strength of social norms: an evolutionary basis. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 129 , 14–23 (2015).

Nunn, N. On the Causes and consequences of cross-cultural differences: an economic perspective. in Handbook of Advances in Culture and Psychology : 9 (eds. Gelfand, M. J., Chiu, C.-Y. & Hong, Y.-Y.) 125–188 (Oxford University Press, 2022).

Algan, Y. & Cahuc, P. Inherited trust and growth. Am. Econ. Rev. 100 , 2060–2092 (2010).

Axelrod, R. An evolutionary approach to norms. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 80 , 1095–1111 (1986).

Price, R. H. & Bouffard, D. L. Behavioral appropriateness and situational constraint as dimensions of social behavior. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 30 , 579–586 (1974).

Eriksson, K., Andersson, P. A. & Strimling, P. Moderators of the disapproval of peer punishment. Group Process. Intergroup Relat. 19 , 152–168 (2016).

Griskevicius, V., Goldstein, N. J., Mortensen, C. R., Cialdini, R. B. & Kenrick, D. T. Going along versus going alone: when fundamental motives facilitate strategic (non)conformity. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 91 , 281–294 (2006).

Hale, T. et al. A global panel database of pandemic policies (Oxford COVID−19 Government Response Tracker). Nat. Human Behav. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-021-01079-8 (2021).

Lakens, D. Equivalence tests: a practical primer for t tests, correlations, and meta-analyses. Soc. Psychol. Personal. Sci. 8 , 355–362 (2017).

Lakens, D., Scheel, A. M. & Isager, P. M. Equivalence testing for psychological research: a tutorial. Adv. Methods Pract. Psychol. Sci. 1 , 259–269 (2018).

Schuirmann, D. J. A comparison of the two one-sided tests procedure and the power approach for assessing the equivalence of average bioavailability. J. Pharmacokinet. Biopharm. 15 , 657–680 (1987).

Article   CAS   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Cohen, J. Statistical Power Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences . (Routledge, 1988). https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203771587 .

Sosis, R., Kress, H. C. & Boster, J. S. Scars for war: evaluating alternative signaling explanations for cross-cultural variance in ritual costs. Evol. Hum. Behav. 28 , 234–247 (2007).

Roes, F. L. & Raymond, M. Belief in moralizing gods. Evol. Hum. Behav. 24 , 126–135 (2003).

Gelfand, M. J. Cultural evolutionary mismatches in response to collective threat. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 30 , 401–409 (2021).

Gelfand, M. J., Gavrilets, S. & Nunn, N. Norm dynamics: Interdisciplinary perspectives on social norm emergence, persistence, and change. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 75 , (2024).

Barclay, P. & Benard, S. The effects of social vs. asocial threats on group cooperation and manipulation of perceived threats. Evol. Hum. Sci. 2 , e54 (2020).

Gavrilets, S. Collective action and the collaborative brain. J. R. Soc. Interface 12 , 20141067 (2015).

Baddeley, M. Hoarding in the age of COVID-19. J. Behav. Econ. Policy 4 , 69–75 (2020).

Syahrivar, J., Genoveva, G., Chairy, C. & Manurung, S. P. COVID-19-induced hoarding intention among the educated segment in Indonesia. SAGE Open 11 , 21582440211016904 (2021).

Lo Iacono, S., Przepiorka, W., Buskens, V., Corten, R. & van de Rijt, A. COVID-19 vulnerability and perceived norm violations predict loss of social trust: a pre-post study. Soc. Sci. Med. 291 , 114513 (2021).

Gelfand, M. J., Raver, J. L. & Ehrhart, K. H. Methodological issues in cross-cultural organizational research. in Handbook of Research Methods in Industrial and Organizational Psychology 216–246 (Blackwell Publishing, 2002).

van de Vijver, F. J. R. & Leung, K. Methods and data analysis for cross-cultural research . (Sage Publications, Inc, 1997).

Ritchie, H. et al. Coronavirus Pandemic (COVID-19). Our World in Data . https://ourworldindata.org/coronavirus (2020).

Download references

Acknowledgements

Knut and Wallenberg Grant “How do human norms form and change?” 2016.0167. (G.An.). The Swedish Research Council grant “Norms & Risk: Do social norms help dealing with collective threats” 2021-06271 (G.An.). Ministero dell’Istruzione dell’Università e della Ricerca, PRIN 2017, prot. 20178TRM3F (D.B.). Universidad de Los Andes, Fondo Vicerrectoría de Investigaciones (J.-C.C.). Ministry of Innovation and Technology of Hungary, National Research, Development and Innovation Fund NKFIH-OTKA K135963 (M.F.). Grant 23-061770 S of the Czech Science Foundation (M.H. and S.G.). RVO: 68081740 of the Institute of Psychology, Czech Academy of Sciences (M.H. and S.G.). RA Science Committee, research project N.20TTSH-070 (A.Gr. and N.Khac.). Open University of Israel, 511687 (R.N.). HSE University Basic Research Program (E.O.). Project BASIC (PID2022-141802NB-I00) funded by MCIN/AEI/10.13039/501100011033 and by “ERDF A way of making Europe” (A.Sá.). US Army Research Office Grant W911NF-19-1-910281 (B.S.). Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research, 019.183SG.001 (E.S.). Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research, VI.Veni.201 G.013 (E.S.). European Commission, Horizon 2020-ID 870827 (E.S.). UKRI Grant “Secret Power” No. EP/X02170X/1 awarded under the European Commission’s “European Research Council - STG” Scheme (G.A.T.).

Author information

These authors contributed equally: Giulia Andrighetto, Aron Szekely.

Authors and Affiliations

Institute of Cognitive Sciences and Technologies, National Research Council of Italy, Rome, Italy

Giulia Andrighetto, Aron Szekely & Andrea Guido

Institute for Futures Studies, Stockholm, Sweden

Giulia Andrighetto, Andrea Guido & Kimmo Eriksson

Institute for Analytical Sociology, Linköping University, Linköping, Sweden

Giulia Andrighetto

Collegio Carlo Alberto, Turin, Italy

Aron Szekely & Davide Barrera

CEREN EA 7477, Burgundy School of Business, Université Bourgogne Franche-Comté, Dijon, France

Andrea Guido

Graduate School of Business and Department of Psychology, Stanford University, Stanford, USA

Michele Gelfand

Department of Sociology, University of South Carolina, Columbia, USA

Jered Abernathy & Brent Simpson

Department of Political Science, Trinity College Dublin, Dublin, Ireland

Gizem Arikan & Michele McArdle

Department of Psychology, Koç University, Istanbul, Turkey

Zeynep Aycan & Seniha Özden

Faculty of Management, Koç University, Istanbul, Turkey

Zeynep Aycan

Ashoka University, Sonipat, India

Shweta Bankar & Pavan Mamidi

Department of Culture, Politics, and Society, University of Turin, Turin, Italy

Davide Barrera & Sara Romanò

United States International University – Africa, Nairobi, Kenya

Dana Basnight-Brown

Instituto de Investigaciones Psicológicas (IIPsi), Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas (CONICET); CABA, Córdoba, Argentina

Anabel Belaus & Cecilia Reyna

Facultad de Psicología, Universidad Nacional de Córdoba (UNC), Córdoba, Argentina

Anabel Belaus

Sunway University, Bandar Sunway, Malaysia

Elizaveta Berezina & Colin Mathew Hugues D. Gill

Departamento de Psicología, Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú, Lima, Perú

Sheyla Blumen

SWPS University, Warsaw, Poland

Paweł Boski & Katarzyna Growiec

Hanoi National University of Education, Hanoi, Vietnam

Huyen Thi Thu Bui

Universidad de los Andes, Bogota, Colombia

Juan Camilo Cárdenas

University of Massachusetts Amherst, Amherst, USA

Faculty of Philosophy, University of Banja Luka, Banja Luka, Bosnia and Herzegovina

Đorđe Čekrlija

Institute of Psychology, University of Greifswald, Greifswald, Germany

Centre for Culture and Evolution, Brunel University London, Uxbridge, UK

Mícheál de Barra

Faculty of Medicine, University of Colombo, Colombo, Sri Lanka

Piyanjali de Zoysa

Department of Psychology, University of Cologne, Cologne, Germany

Angela Dorrough & Andreas Glöckner

Center for Research in Experimental Economics and Political Decision Making (CREED), Amsterdam School of Economics, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Jan B. Engelmann

Gies College of Business, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Champaign, USA

Vienna University of Economics and Business, Vienna, Austria

Susann Fiedler

Stern School of Business, New York University, New York, USA

Olivia Foster-Gimbel & Lisa M. Leslie

Instituto de Ciências Sociais, Universidade de Lisboa, Lisboa, Portugal

Gonçalo Freitas

HUN-REN Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience and Psychology, Research Centre of Natural Sciences, Budapest, Hungary

Marta Fülöp

Institute of Psychology, Karoli Gáspár University of the Reformed Churches, Budapest, Hungary

Faculty of Psychology, University of Iceland, Reykjavik, Iceland

Ragna B. Gardarsdottir

Universal College Bangladesh, Dhaka, Bangladesh

Colin Mathew Hugues D. Gill

Institute of Psychology, Czech Academy of Sciences, Brno, Czech Republic

Sylvie Graf & Martina Hřebíčková

Department of Personality Psychology, Yerevan State University, Yerevan, Armenia

Ani Grigoryan & Narine Khachatryan

Osaka Metropolitan University, Osaka, Japan

Hirofumi Hashimoto

School of Psychology, University of Kent, Canterbury, UK

Tim Hopthrow

Royal Holloway, University of London, Egham, UK

Hirotaka Imada & Giovanni A. Travaglino

Waseda University, Tokyo, Japan

Yoshio Kamijo

Department of Psychology, Monk Prayogshala, Mumbai, India

Hansika Kapoor

Melbourne School of Psychological Sciences, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia

Yoshihisa Kashima

Kyiv International Institute of Sociology, Kyiv, Ukraine

Natalia Kharchenko

DeJusticia, Bogotá, Colombia

Nagoya University, Nagoya, Japan

School of Natural Sciences and Health, Tallinn University, Tallinn, Estonia

Department of Medical and Surgical Sciences, “Magna Græcia” University of Catanzaro, Catanzaro, Italy

Marco Tullio Liuzza

Department of Psychology, American University of Sharjah, Sharjah, United Arab Emirates

Angela T. Maitner & Sara Sherbaji

Department of Finance and Investment, Imam Mohammad Ibn Saud Islamic University, Riyadh, Saudi Arabia

Imed Medhioub

Presbyterian Mackenzie University, São Paulo, Brazil

Maria Luisa Mendes Teixeira

The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem, Israel

Sari Mentser

Universidad de los Andes, Santiago, Chile

Francisco Morales

Northeastern University, Boston, USA

Jayanth Narayanan

Ritsumeikan University, Shiga, Japan

Kohei Nitta

Department of Education and Psychology, The Open University of Israel, Ra’anana, Israel

Ravit Nussinson

Institute of Information Processing and Decision Making (IIPDM), University of Haifa, Haifa, Israel

Department of Psychology, University of Nigeria, Nsukka, Nigeria

Nneoma G. Onyedire & Ike E. Onyishi

HSE University, Moscow, Russia

Evgeny Osin

Department of Education and Social Work, University of Patras, Patras, Greece

Penny Panagiotopoulou

POLLSTER, Kiev, Ukraine

Oleksandr Pereverziev

Universidad Diego Portales, Santiago, Chile

Lorena R. Perez-Floriano

Faculty of Social Sciences, Social Psychology, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland

Anna-Maija Pirttilä-Backman & Inari Sakki

Leadership and Management, Amsterdam Business School (ABS), University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Marianna Pogosyan

Queen’s University at Kingston, Ontario, Canada

Centro de Investigação e Intervenção Social, Instituto Universitário de Lisboa (ISCTE-IUL), Lisbon, Portugal

Ricardo Borges Rodrigues

School of Economics, Universidad San Francisco de Quito, Quito, Ecuador

Pedro P. Romero

Experimental and Computational Economics Lab (ECEL), Universidad San Francisco de Quito, Quito, Ecuador

Grupo Interdisciplinar de Sistemas Complejos (GISC), Departamento de Matemáticas, Universidad Carlos III de Madrid, Leganés, Spain

Angel Sánchez

Instituto de Biocomputación y Física de Sistemas Complejos (BIFI), Universidad de Zaragoza, Zaragoza, Spain

Department of Anthropology, University College London, London, UK

Sara Sherbaji

Department of Economics and Law, University of Cassino and Southern Lazio, Cassino (FR), Italy

Lorenzo Spadoni

Department of Psychology, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Eftychia Stamkou

Department of Experimental and Applied Psychology, Vrije Universiteit, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Paul A. M. Van Lange

Faculty of Psychology, Universitas Airlangga, Surabaya, Indonesia

Fiona Fira Winata & Rizqy Amelia Zein

Guangzhou University, Guangzhou, P. R. China

Qing-peng Zhang

Center for Cultural Evolution, Stockholm University, Stockholm, Sweden

Kimmo Eriksson

Malardalens University, Vasteras, Sweden

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Contributions

G.An., A.Sz. and A.Gu. designed the study and wrote the manuscript. A.Gu. analyzed the data. K.E., M.G., A.Gl. and M.T.L. provided critical input on the study and/or the manuscript. All other authors arranged translations where required, gave feedback on wording of items, collected data, and reviewed the manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giulia Andrighetto .

Ethics declarations

Competing interests.

The authors declare no competing interests.

Peer review

Peer review information.

Nature Communications thanks Pat Barclay, Andrew Delton, Peder Isager, Anne Scheel and the other, anonymous, reviewer(s) for their contribution to the peer review of this work. A peer review file is available.

Additional information

Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary information

Supplementary information, reporting summary, peer review file, rights and permissions.

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ .

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Andrighetto, G., Szekely, A., Guido, A. et al. Changes in social norms during the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic across 43 countries. Nat Commun 15 , 1436 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-024-44999-5

Download citation

Received : 14 September 2021

Accepted : 12 January 2024

Published : 16 February 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-024-44999-5

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

By submitting a comment you agree to abide by our Terms and Community Guidelines . If you find something abusive or that does not comply with our terms or guidelines please flag it as inappropriate.

Quick links

  • Explore articles by subject
  • Guide to authors
  • Editorial policies

Sign up for the Nature Briefing newsletter — what matters in science, free to your inbox daily.

social norms good essay

IMAGES

  1. 102 Examples of Social Norms (List)

    social norms good essay

  2. ≫ Why People Conform to Social Norms and an Analyses of Group Free

    social norms good essay

  3. Breaking Social Norms Essay

    social norms good essay

  4. Breaking Social Norms Essay

    social norms good essay

  5. What Is The Social Norms? Free Essay Example

    social norms good essay

  6. Essay

    social norms good essay

VIDEO

  1. Social Norms -- Meaning, Characteristics and Functional Importance. || supervisor

  2. “Do You Resent Social Norms?” #SOC119 #Resent #SocialNorms #Norms #Resentment

  3. 3.4 Социальные нормы

  4. Importance of having good norms #talkshow #ttm #podcast #teacher #education #norms #good

  5. Обществознание. Урок 11. Социальные нормы. Отклоняющееся поведение. Социальный контроль

  6. Essay on Good Manners in english

COMMENTS

  1. Social Norms and Their Violations

    Social norms shape the behaviors and actions of individuals to a considerable extent. They represent an unwritten policy concerning the expected human behavior. Social norms are fundamental in promoting order and control in society. These rules reflect the behavioral patterns of members of a certain group. The application of these norms can be ...

  2. Social Norms In Society: [Essay Example], 654 words

    Social Norms in Society. Social norms are an integral part of society, shaping the way individuals behave and interact with one another. These norms are the unwritten rules that govern our actions, beliefs, and values, and they vary across different cultures, communities, and time periods. In this essay, we will explore the concept of social ...

  3. Norms And Social Norm: [Essay Example], 854 words GradesFixer

    Norms can be defined as shared expectations and rules that govern the behavior of individuals within a particular society or group. They are the social guidelines that inform individuals about what is considered appropriate or inappropriate in a given context. Norms can be categorized into various types, such as folkways, mores, and taboos ...

  4. Social Norms Essay

    Examples of some social norms that students learn are: "do not yell in the library," "do not speak unless spoken to," "do not talk to strangers," and "close the door when you use the restroom.". As you grow older, these rules become unspoken because everyone knows how to act like a proper individual in society.

  5. Example Of Social Norms: [Essay Example], 488 words

    Social norms are the unwritten rules that govern behavior within a society. They are deeply ingrained in a culture and are passed down from generation to... read full [Essay Sample] for free ... Norm Violation in Sociology Essay. Social norms play a significant role in shaping society and determining acceptable behavior. However, these norms ...

  6. 102 Examples of Social Norms (List)

    Examples of Social Norms. Greeting people when you see them. Saying "thank you" for favors. Holding the door open for others. Standing up when someone else enters the room. Offering to help someone carrying something heavy. Speaking quietly in public places. Waiting in line politely. Respecting other people's personal space.

  7. Social Norms

    Social norms, the informal rules that govern behavior in groups and societies, have been extensively studied in the social sciences. Anthropologists have described how social norms function in different cultures (Geertz 1973), sociologists have focused on their social functions and how they motivate people to act (Durkheim 1895 [1982], 1950 [1957]; Parsons 1937; Parsons & Shils 1951; James ...

  8. PDF Social norms and social influence

    Social norms are the foundation of culture, of language, of social interaction, cuisine, love, marriage, play, prejudice, economic exchange and traffic control. The elements of this list are fundamental to human life; the list is endless. The human organism is built for social norms. The foundations of social norms in imitation and social learn ...

  9. PDF Essays on Social Norms

    Essays on Social Norms By Minjae Kim B.A. Political Science University of Chicago, 2012 S.M. Management Research Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 2017 ... good person to be around. Although he might not want the title, he will always be a -^(M-! '3 for me

  10. Examples of Social Norms & Societal Standards in Sociology

    The following are some common social norms that people in the US and UK follow daily (Hechter & Opp, 2001): Shaking hands when greeting someone. Saying "please" and "thank you". Apologizing when one makes a mistake. Standing up when someone enters the room.

  11. The Good Society: Core Social Values, Social Norms, and Public ...

    The Good Society: Core Social Values, Social Norms, and Public Policy Robert Perrucci1 and Carolyn C. Perrucci2 This essay is an attempt to transcend the contentious political environment by offering a conceptual framework for discussing the outlines of a "good society" and its constituent elements. We offer an argu-

  12. Why do people follow social norms?

    Abstract. Norms prescribe how to make decisions in social situations and play a crucial role in sustaining cooperative relationships and coordinating collective action. However, following norms often requires restricting behavior, demanding to curtail selfishness, or suppressing personal goals. This raises the question why people adhere to norms.

  13. Social Roles and Social Norms In Psychology

    Each social role carries expected behaviors called norms. While social roles provide a framework for behavior, they can also be limiting. They can perpetuate stereotypes, hinder personal expression, and promote inequalities. For instance, rigid gender roles can limit opportunities and potentials for individuals.

  14. Social Norm Essays: Examples, Topics, & Outlines

    Social Norm Experiment: Scenario 6 -- Facing the rong ay in an Elevator Solomon Asch's Conformity Experiments during the 1950s demonstrated how much individual opinion and even perception of reality can be influenced by others (Gerrig & Zimbardo 2009, 577-579). In the original series of experiments, Asch tested subjects by presenting with a perceptual question that should have been very easy ...

  15. Social Norms Essay

    On the other hand, some scholars argue that social norms are created primarily to stimulate roles, thus reinforcing the stability of a social class. Although the reason behind the emergence and reality of norms are unclear, ... Good Essays. Read More. Decent Essays. Breaking a Social Norm Essay. 863 Words; 4 Pages;

  16. Essay On Social Norms

    1828 Words 8 Pages. Social Norms One of the main ways in which society functions is based on social norms, which help regulate the actions that people will carry out on a daily basis. Social norms can be learned as part of someone 's culture or can be influenced by authority such as a government. Examples of the different types of norms could ...

  17. Norm Violation in Sociology: [Essay Example], 1203 words

    Social Norms Essay: Research Methodology. To ensure accurate results, I selected various locations and times to conduct the experiment. It was essential to choose public restrooms with high attendance rates to collect sufficient data for analysis. The experiment itself was straightforward. I entered the men's restroom and observed the reaction ...

  18. When Breaking the Rules Is the Smart Thing to Do

    As science shows, we have internalized the judgments and preferences of other people. Following rules is one thing. Sticking to the norms to be accepted by others is a different matter. "Only ...

  19. The Importance Of Social Norms In Society

    The Importance Of Social Norms In Society. Good Essays. 1040 Words. 5 Pages. Open Document. Within society everyone has a certain set of standards that most everybody follows. These are called norms. Merriam-Webster defines a norm as a principle of right action binding upon the members of a group and serving to guide, control, or regulate ...

  20. Social norms and social practices

    Abstract. Theories of social norms frequently define social norms in terms of individuals' beliefs and preferences, and so afford individual beliefs and preferences conceptual priority over social norms. I argue that this treatment of social norms is unsustainable. Taking Bicchieri's theory as an exemplar of this approach, I argue, first ...

  21. Social Norms

    1218 Words. 5 Pages. Open Document. Introduction. Social norms are powerful to the point that they influence the actions of all who are members of society. Social norms are so ingrained in most people that to not follow such untold rules of behavior, likely creates serious tension for oneself. Social norms appear to be unique to sentient life ...

  22. Changes in social norms during the early stages of the COVID-19

    The emergence of COVID-19 dramatically changed social behavior across societies and contexts. Here we study whether social norms also changed. Specifically, we study this question for cultural ...