Logo Oapen

  • For Librarians
  • For Publishers
  • For Researchers
  •   OAPEN Home

Public International Law

A Multi-Perspective Approach

Thumbnail

Contributor(s)

cc

Publisher website

Publication date and place, classification, public remark.

  • Imported or submitted locally

Export search results

The export option will allow you to export the current search results of the entered query to a file. Differen formats are available for download. To export the items, click on the button corresponding with the preferred download format.

A logged-in user can export up to 15000 items. If you're not logged in, you can export no more than 500 items.

To select a subset of the search results, click "Selective Export" button and make a selection of the items you want to export. The amount of items that can be exported at once is similarly restricted as the full export.

After making a selection, click one of the export format buttons. The amount of items that will be exported is indicated in the bubble next to export format.

  • Search Menu
  • Advance articles
  • EJIL: Talk!
  • The Podcast!
  • EJIL: Live!
  • Author Guidelines
  • Submission Site
  • Open Access
  • Why Publish?
  • About European Journal of International Law
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Journals Career Network
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Dispatch Dates
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Issue Cover

Article Contents

1 cues from world public opinion, 2 international public law in a comparative perspective, 3 international public authority: the object of international public law.

  • < Previous

From Public International to International Public Law: Translating World Public Opinion into International Public Authority

Director, Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International Law, Heidelberg, Germany. Email: [email protected] .

Junior Professor, Goethe University Frankfurt, Germany; Senior Research Affiliate, Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International Law, Heidelberg, Germany. Email: [email protected] .

Associate Professor, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Email: [email protected] . We are indebted to Miriam Aziz and Elena Allendörfer for their editorial assistance.

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Armin von Bogdandy, Matthias Goldmann, Ingo Venzke, From Public International to International Public Law: Translating World Public Opinion into International Public Authority, European Journal of International Law , Volume 28, Issue 1, 1 February 2017, Pages 115–145, https://doi.org/10.1093/ejil/chx002

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This article argues that increasing demands in world public opinion for legitimate and effective international institutions require a paradigm shift in public international law. There is a part of public international law that should be better understood as international public law because it enables and disciplines the pursuit of public interests by international institutions. We consider such activities as exercises of international public authority. The article elaborates our approach by way of a thorough discussion of other approaches to governance phenomena in international legal scholarship. It then carves out the notion of international public authority. This notion includes various types of soft and informal governance instruments with innovative compliance mechanisms as well as the activities of informal and hybrid institutions or network-like structures.

A significant part of world public opinion regards international institutions with considerable ambivalence; many of these institutions have become powerful, and quite a few of their activities raise serious doubts. Nonetheless, they should be vested with more powers in order to better further common interests. 1 World public opinion voices legitimacy concerns alongside regulatory demands – a tension that poses serious challenges for these institutions. We share this ambivalent view of international institutions and see that much academic writing supports it. 2 In response to the legitimacy concerns and regulatory demands, we propose a theory of international public law.

The purpose of our theory is to identify, reconstruct and develop that segment of public international law that governs the exercise of international public authority. 3 Switching ‘public’ and ‘international’ is not a slip of the pen but expresses the overall thrust of our theory: to advance a public law paradigm in international law. Thereby, we aim at taking account of world public opinion in the language of international law. International public law stands for the reconstruction and development of the legal regimes governing the activities of international institutions in light of their publicness. In this way, legal scholarship may contribute to improving the legitimacy and the effectiveness of their activities.

Today, in the wake of globalization, international institutions, including classical international organizations such as the United Nations (UN) or the International Centre for the Settlement of Investment Disputes (ICSID), informal institutions such as the G7 and network-like structures such as certain regulatory bodies in the financial sector devise policies with huge domestic impact, 4 be it through regulation, deregulation, adjudication, administration or the dissemination of information. The UN sanctions against Iraq contributed to the death of thousands. 5 The UN Security Council lists persons suspected of terrorist activities, triggering a complete freeze of their assets with serious consequences for their lives. 6 The World Bank and the International Monetary Fund have caused profound changes of domestic economic and social policies. 7 The Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) regularly ranks states according to the academic performance of their schoolchildren, transforming education policy in many countries. 8 Investment tribunals decide on whether domestic environmental regulation amounts to an indirect expropriation for which a host state is liable to a foreign investor. 9 While international institutions are very present in some policy fields, they have little impact in others where international action is also called for – for example, in the field of climate change. The development of international institutions is obviously uneven, especially from the perspective of the global south as it is often in line with interests of the global north. 10

To grasp the legitimacy concerns as well as the regulatory requests surrounding international institutions, we reconstruct their power as an exercise of international public authority. In a nutshell, the exercise of international public authority is the adoption of an act that affects the freedom of others in pursuance of a common interest. 11 This understanding helps single out activities that require grounds of legitimacy that go beyond the consent of member states to the institution’s foundational act. Singling out those activities is a precondition for increasing their legitimacy. It also opens avenues for more effective regulation. 12

Even though views within world public opinion may diverge on many important issues, it seems to be common ground that public authority should advance common interests and that it should do so in a way that merits obedience. Since these twin requirements, and their uneasy relationship, are the key characteristics for contemporary public law in most domestic legal orders, public law theories, doctrines and practical expertise may help in the development of international public law. Of course, there are important differences between domestic and international public law, not least because the latter is not supported by one overarching state, nation or people. However, this does not impede learning across levels of governance. The establishment of the International Society of Public Law testifies to this possibility. 13

The second part of this article elaborates the idea behind the public law approach by engaging with other conceptualizations of globalization and their repercussions on world public opinion in legal scholarship. The third part develops our theory of international public authority, which defines the object of international public law, and the fourth part of the article assesses our proposal in the light of current developments in global politics.

We present our theory of international public law in a Socratic way, engaging with the texts that guided our reflections. The first set of texts juxtaposes our approach to understandings informed by private law thinking. The second step engages with positions analysing law from an external – that is, sociological – viewpoint. The third step presents three approaches that fit neatly into the public law paradigm. Each of these approaches depicts certain aspects of that thinking. Our approach aims at combining their strengths and addressing some of their weaknesses.

A International Public Law versus the Private Law Paradigm

1 the traditional private law paradigm: bilateralism, coordination, consent.

In the past, the ‘public’ in public international law was explained by the fact that its main subjects are states – that is, public institutions – not because it governs the exercise of public authority. 14 In fact, the very lack of public authority – that is, anarchy – was often seen as the defining feature of the international order. 15 Accordingly, many consider public international law to be a horizontal order of co-existence based on consent. 16 Thus, it mostly operates on the basis of a private law paradigm.

Surely, this paradigm has always attracted much critique. 17 More recently, there are increasing signs that it is inadequate for many, if not most, parts of public international law. In the attempt to cater to common interests, international law has developed a sophisticated institutional structure that is hard to reconcile with ideas of horizontal relations based on (state) consent alone. 18 Our shift towards international public law rests on the conviction that the private law paradigm, due to its focus on self-interest and horizontal structures, is insufficient, in particular, when it comes to the operation of this institutional structure. International public law, by contrast, lays bare its authority, reads international law in relation to common interests and confronts problems of legitimacy.

Thinking in terms of international public law does not categorically replace the private law paradigm. Some fields and practices of international law may still be understood in analogy to contracts. 19 What is more, the private law paradigm does provide tools to react to a changed reality. 20 First of all, private law instruments can further the common good. Contracts and property are essential to a functioning, welfare-enhancing economy; private law instruments like emissions rights might contribute to fighting climate change. 21 Emmanuelle Jouannet has argued that even modern ‘liberal’ international law – that is, the contemporary international law of co-ordination that follows the private law paradigm – is not only based on sovereign equality but also on democracy and human rights. 22 Eyal Benvenisti has used present-day private law theories in order to advance far-reaching proposals for the understanding and development of international law. 23 He presents states as trustees of humanity and reconstructs their sovereign control over a territory along progressive theories of private property. 24 However, this approach concerns relationships between states and foreign citizens under their jurisdiction. It does not deal with international institutions. Indeed, in his recent book, The Law of Global Governance , Benvenisti himself opts for global administrative law, thereby leaving the private law paradigm behind when he turns to international institutions. 25

2 The New Contractualism of Rational Choice

The private law paradigm will certainly live on, especially among (neo-)realist international lawyers who are sceptical of the prowess of international law, of international institutions and of legally curbing state power. From their viewpoint, a public law approach looks utterly misguided. Jack Goldsmith and Eric Posner caused a stir with such a view a decade ago. 26 According to them, authority beyond states is plainly impossible, as a matter of fact and for normative reasons. For democratic states, the domestic constituency is the only relevant factor. And governments are bound to do what is best for them. States are therefore unlikely to truly pursue common projects with other states, let alone cosmopolitan ones. 27 Any international obligation, even if it results from a freely concluded treaty, is suspicious since it constrains the domestic democratic process. 28 The criticisms of this approach are manifold. For example, it categorically denies that international commitments – in the form of a treaty or otherwise – could well be an expression of domestic democratic interests. It further disregards that international cooperation enables individual states to do together what they could not do alone. Finally, it only views international constraints as problematic and does not take into account the constraints that individual states would impose upon one another in the absence of international cooperation.

Other approaches share the attempt to link everything happening in the field of international law to a certain vision of human and state behaviour where self-interest constitutes the principal source of motivation. 29 Some of this research recognizes that it might be rational for self-interested states to confer tasks to international institutions with some degree of autonomy. 30 Yet even more differentiated rational choice approaches face serious critiques. They ultimately continue to take the maximization of state interests to be the main, if not single, reason for action. This yardstick is both unduly reductive and highly indeterminate. 31

3 Droit privé total: The Renewed Lex Mercatoria

Approaches to international law based on systems theory do not consider society as an aggregate of individual actions and interests. 32 But there is still little hope for an international public law. Systems theory assumes that society consists of different social systems (law, economics, politics and so on) that are sealed off in relation to one another. They also globalize at different speeds. The political system typically lags behind. 33 For this reason, systems theory considers the idea of an overarching public order, which is central to public law thinking, as being hopeless. Instead, it places its bets on spontaneous interactions within the various social systems of world society. 34

The renewed lex mercatoria serves as a principal case in point. 35 Such a global legal regime is understood as developing in line with the rationality of its corresponding social system. The relationship between legal regimes reflects the profound contradictions and collisions that prevail in world society, thus giving rise to a global legal pluralism of different legal regimes. 36 Even the emergence of human rights as a – somehow – constitutional standard in international law remains limited to the political realm, thus to one functionally differentiated system of society and is far from being truly universal. 37 Collisions among different legal regimes may at best be tamed through mechanisms of horizontal coordination, by ‘reciprocal observation, anticipatory adaptation, cooperation, trust, self-commitment, reliability, negotiations, and a context of permanent reference to one another’. 38 The private law paradigm ought to explain this form of horizontal coordination.

System theoretical approaches are related to calls for private international law or a new transnational (or global) law as the appropriate legal response to global governance. 39 They argue that the increasing importance of private, informal and transnational phenomena, as well as all of the various hybrids they produce, renders public law approaches ill-suited, if not hopeless, to take care of common interests. 40 Indeed, strictly hierarchical and unitary conceptions of public law are no longer convincing. But there are good reasons to doubt that rules established between private actors can live on their own, whether factually or normatively speaking. The claim for the desirability of a ‘public’ dimension expresses the awareness and conviction that social interactions are, and should be, regulated by rules that emerge from discourses about common interests. Neither the ambitious political vision for peace and justice, nor the articulation and promotion of more specific common interests can be achieved by regimes based solely on spontaneous private ordering. In recognition of this, world public opinion places its hopes on the effective regulation by legitimate international institutions.

B International Public Law versus Sociological Approaches

1 global governance and transnational legal process.

The international public law approach shares three insights with global governance studies. 41 First is the recognition of the significance of institutions and processes beyond the state. The most visible mark of their significance might be the degree of autonomy that international institutions enjoy vis-à-vis state governments. 42 Second, research on global governance notes the importance of informality of many institutions, procedures and instruments. It stresses the need to go beyond established legal concepts that cannot grasp such informality. 43 Third, as is obvious from the use of the term ‘global’ rather than ‘international’, global governance emphasizes the multi-level character of processes and interactions. We share these three insights and agree that these mechanisms should not be neglected but, rather, be made the object of legal reconstructions. We also share the idea that a convincing concept of law must be broader and more differentiated than the classic triad of treaty, custom and general principles. And although we focus more narrowly on international phenomena, we have other levels of governance on the radar, especially because both the effectiveness and the legitimacy of international institutional activity, and of international public law, heavily depend on domestic public law.

However, global governance studies display serious normative and cognitive shortcomings endemic in many liberal international relation theories, many of which come into view through the prism of public law. Normatively speaking, global governance is mainly understood as a technocratic process concerned with ‘problem solving’. 44 It is focused on pursuing defined goals effectively but is rather silent about how to define goals or about how to strike inevitable normative balances when pursuing any single goal. What is more, a concern for the workings of power relations is largely absent. 45 On the cognitive side, global governance studies lack a conceptual framework for distinguishing and identifying those instruments that raise questions of legitimacy and those that do not.

The same may be said of transnational legal process. 46 The latter is characterized by an emphasis on law as a continuous process of consecutive decisions instead of a stable system of rules. 47 It provides important insights as to why decisions are obeyed, whether for reasons of self-interest, identity or as a result of repeated interaction. 48 Much like global legal pluralism, 49 it accommodates the input of a host of new actors and develops a broader view on different sites for the generation of legal normativity beyond the classic realm of governmental interaction. Its main normative argument boils down to suggesting that the variety of many different processes sustains the normativity of the outcome. Precisely why this should be the case remains unclear.

The public law approach responds to these limits of governance studies and transnational legal process with its focus on the exercise and justification of public authority. It thereby avails itself of the dual function of modern public law. Accordingly, public authority may only be exercised if it is based on an authorizing act (constitutive or enabling function), and its exercise controlled and limited by substantive and procedural standards (limiting function). 50 For this reason, public law helps to translate concerns about the legitimacy of governance activities into meaningful arguments of legality. Work under the concept of global governance or transnational legal process is typically insufficient for this purpose because it does not provide a basis for the identification of those acts that are critical. Nor does it show how those acts may be framed in terms of law.

2 Critical Approaches

The normative implications that many studies of global governance and theories of transnational legal process draw – the more actors and the more forms of law, the merrier – meets with a strong critique from perspectives that highlight diffuse governance processes and informality as a fig-leaf for the exercise of power. 51 Whereas advocates of global governance studies, transnational legal process and global legal pluralism might view plurality and informality as mechanisms to break into the centres of state power, Martti Koskenniemi and others see it, above all, as the subjugation of that same power to vested economic interests. Against the move to informality, they uphold the legal form and formal language of the law as a possible shield against private power and a possible vehicle for progressive politics. 52 They draw attention to how dominant interpretations in international law reflect power imbalances and entrench biases. 53 But the language of law, they suggest, offers at least a marginal degree of resistance to such exercises of power in the name of economic efficiency or morality. 54 Even if one does not share Koskenniemi’s fundamental scepticism about legitimizing the exercise of power through law, the critical approach forcefully underlines the epistemological and political challenges that legal scholarship has to meet.

Another important point stressed by critical scholarship is the political nature of the public-private divide. As Hans Kelsen has already shown with great clarity, the view that some fields are necessarily to be left to private ordering whereas only some others can be subject to public ordering is deeply ideological. 55 American critical legal studies and feminist scholarship, in particular, has deepened and elaborated this insight. 56 We agree that the public-private distinction has shielded and perpetuated relationships of dominance in the past and present by the pretence that they belonged to the private realm. But responses to this wrong can and should proceed without giving up the distinction in its entirety. First, the private sphere is certainly not immune against governmental interference. Second, in contemporary legal practice, the public-private distinction has lost its static character. The public sphere extends over whatever issue the competent institutions decide it to extend. The private sphere provides no safe haven for oppressive relationships. Third, as we argue in the next section, the public-private distinction continues to exercise an important function for the identification and formulation of common interests. 57

3 International Public Law and the Need for Legal Doctrine

Insights of political science and political theory remain external to the extent that these explanations and assessments usually cannot be processed in the operation of the legal system. According to an understanding shared by many legal traditions, public law scholarship also has an ‘internal’ or ‘doctrinal’ dimension, possibly its most important one, which is to evolve and manage the operative vocabulary of the law that constitutes and constrains public authority. Of course, this role of public law scholarship is different from one legal tradition to another, but it is certainly far more pronounced in most traditions than in the USA. 58 We understand doctrine and more external approaches to the law to be complementary, not adversarial.

The development of an operative legal vocabulary for international public authority is a pressing task. Most importantly, the frequent absence of elaborated legal standards leads to the unfortunate situation that international institutions exercise public authority that many might perceive to be illegitimate but cannot claim to be illegal for lack of such standards. The discourse on legality is out of sync with the discourse on legitimacy. 59 Too often, international law is silent about what world public opinion considers as dubious exercises of international public authority. Only internal approaches that provide criteria for the legality or illegality of specific acts can offer suggestions to rectify this dissonance. This gap between legality and legitimacy is deeply troubling. The experience of the state since early modernity, not only of liberal democracies, teaches how important it is that legitimacy concerns can be put forward, in principle, as issues of legality. 60 This is a core role of public law. It renders the translation of legitimacy concerns into legal arguments and eventually into the normative fabric of social interaction possible. Indeed, world public opinion testifies to the problematic dissonance between legality and legitimacy.

Moreover, legal vocabulary is usually much more detailed and specific than that of other disciplines. Much of public law doctrine consists in elaborating the significance in concrete cases of the ‘big ideas’, such as human rights, checks and balances, rule of law, democracy and so on. It disentangles complex patterns into individual acts and actors and provides a frame that constitutes and constrains them. This has the important practical effect that not every single act of public authority needs to be investigated for want of legitimacy. Instead, acts that are legal are presumed to be legitimate – a presumption that can, and has often been, rebutted. 61

A doctrinal approach not only serves normative but also cognitive purposes. The lack of a developed legal framework contributes to the amorphous image of international institutions, international policies and international normativity. Legal concepts and theories, developed to understand the law and to manage normative expectations, also play an important role for coming to terms with the social world. As shown for the domestic level of governance, public institutions, their policies and the normative operations within a society need and live within legal terminology (see, for example, the doctrines of contract, separation of powers, due process and so on). However, there is an absence of commensurate legal concepts regarding international institutions, policies and instruments. Not least, a lack of understanding and trust in the legitimacy of international law’s dynamic core prevails, generally speaking, which is part of the ambivalence of world public opinion. Since traditional concepts such as sovereignty, sources of law or consent have lost so much of their explanatory purchase, international institutions, policies and instruments remain opaque. If their legal regime is uncertain, it is more likely that they do not fully achieve their regulatory objectives. Doctrinal elaborations therefore support the effectiveness of legal instruments.

4 Public Law Approaches: Institutional, Constitutional and Administrative Law

Responding to the need for an internal, public law approach, a rich field of research has emerged to legally frame global governance. This field mainly consists of institutional, constitutional and administrative law approaches. By and large, they pursue the twofold intention of furthering the potential of international public authority while hedging its risks. None of these approaches laments the decline of the Westphalian order. Rather, they aim at rendering global governance more efficient as well as more legitimate. Institutional, constitutional and administrative approaches all develop aspects of international public law. While important differences exist between these approaches, the common ground is considerable, and we think that elaborating this common ground propels a better exchange of ideas. In particular, we suggest that they can all work well with, and gain from, the notion of international public authority.

(a) International institutional law

International institutional law focuses on international organizations as subjects of international law, describing both their externally relevant activities and their internal law with a view to carving out common principles embedded in the legal design and practices of all international institutions. 62 For international public law, international institutional law provides a breakthrough as it features a concept that contains the first nucleus of international public authority. As is well known, according to international institutional law, an international organization requires the possibility of forming ‘a will of its own’ in the pursuit of its objectives. 63 This is to be understood against the former understanding, which viewed international organizations as permanent intergovernmental venues, hence, as part of the domestic administration of the member states. 64

The capacity of autonomous decision making of international institutions enables them to formulate common interests for their member states. In this respect, international institutional law was mainly developed according to a functionalist understanding of international institutions. As Jan Klabbers has recently shown, the functionalist orientation of international institutional law stems from the insight that nations are heavily interdependent and therefore inevitably need to cooperate in permanent, non-sporadic ways. Paul Reinsch, who Klabbers identifies as the first scholar of international institutional law, embedded this approach into a progress narrative. He believed that de-politicized, technical organizations would have a calming effect on overbearing national interests, which would eventually contribute to world peace. 65 Two world wars later, David Mitrany advocated institutions that would provide welfare services to their members, among them many newly independent states. 66 Wolfgang Friedmann’s seminal work on the law of cooperation epitomizes the underlying paradigm shift in the focus of international law from concerns regarding state sovereignty to the welfare of the citizens and the self-preservation of mankind. 67 While states would remain the principal subjects of international law, a supranational society created by global and regional international organizations with legal personality would rise to the level of an actor in its own right. 68 Recognizing the vertical structure of international institutional law and its focus on common interests, Philip Allott designated it as ‘international public law’. 69

Today, international institutional law holds great potential as a framing device for international public authority since international organizations are of enormous significance for public affairs in times of global governance. It is no wonder that this stream of research has greatly evolved as of late. 70 New instruments, competencies and procedures of international organizations have come into its focus. 71 In order to live up to the challenges of global governance, international institutional law could easily be extended so as to encompass not only the activities of international organizations in a strict sense but also the actions of less formalized institutions, such as the Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe, or non-binding instruments. 72

The limits of the international institutional law approach lie elsewhere. Although this school of thought views the welfare of individuals as its overarching concern, it does not regard them as subjects of international law 73 and is unconcerned about their freedom. 74 Accordingly, the putatively technical character of their tasks – their advantage, according to Mitrany – shields them from requirements of additional legitimacy beyond state consent. The emergence of claims in world public opinion for such legitimacy shows that this view faces an increasing number of problems. Remarkably, Klabbers’ textbook presents international institutional law as being caught up in the tension between autonomous international institutions and member states. He leaves no space for the role of individuals. 75 And, yet, he also builds on a strand of the public law approach that takes the individual most seriously – namely, constitutionalism. 76

(b) Constitutionalism

The broadest strand of legal scholarship that deals with global governance phenomena from a public law perspective is constitutionalism. 77 Like international institutional law, it is driven by the intuition that a strictly horizontal conception of the international order needs to be supplemented by considerations for its more vertical structures. 78 In the language of constitutionalism, and in contrast to international institutional law, these structures amount to a common order encompassing the entire international community. Thus, with the exception of functionalist approaches, 79 most constitutional approaches ultimately base this order on the freedom of individuals and their capacity for self-determination. 80

Constitutionalism comprises a variety of strands. Whereas some authors use the constitutionalist approach to redefine the international legal order as a whole, 81 others, closer to our concern, use it in order to legally frame activities of international institutions in light of first principles. 82 Especially with regard to the latter, we see a noteworthy insight. Scholars in this camp advocate that activities of international institutions should be investigated in the light of the experience of domestic public (or constitutional) law in liberal democracies with its focus on freedom. 83 Accordingly, constitutionalism suggests that many of the standards of domestic constitutional law may be instructive for the legal regimes of international public authority. 84 Obviously, overly simplistic analogies must be avoided when construing the public law framework of world society. However, this strand of constitutionalism rightly stresses the importance for international public law of core principles such as human rights, the rule of law and democratic inclusion. 85

While we share constitutionalism’s core intuition about freedom and the concern for core principles, we depart from its more value-laden variants and, more generally, harbour some reservations about the use of the concept of constitution for the international level. Constitutionalism, like constitutionalization, somehow suggests a progression towards a global polity or even federal union that appears problematic. 86 It might suggest a degree of hierarchy, closure and a quest for ultimate reasons that is unattainable (only think of the dazzling question of a pouvoir constituant in world society).

Constitutional pluralism, however, does address this difficulty to some extent. Again, there is a wide variety of versions of constitutional pluralism. Some authors, like Neil MacCormick, understand constitutional pluralism as different constitutional levels within one hierarchical organization, similar to federal states. 87 This variety of pluralism brings into focus questions about the relationship between these communities. 88 While constitutional pluralism might help to adequately reconstruct the legal order of the European Union, it seems hardly convincing for the global level. Radical pluralist approaches, by contrast, deny the existence of any overarching universal legal rules or the idea of overcoming different fragmented global legal regimes. 89 Intermediate approaches take the citizens as the ultimate subjects of legitimacy and recognize that individuals are social beings who do not live in isolation but, rather, have many social relationships and affiliations. They may therefore belong to different communities at different levels at the same time. 90 This opens the possibility of tapping into domestic democratic processes in order to legitimize international public authority. 91

Although we share with constitutional pluralism the pluralistic view of citizens and other communities as subjects of legitimacy, we are concerned about the limited capacity of such approaches to deal with questions of political inclusion. Constitutionalism focuses above all on the impact of governance arrangements on human rights. However, not every act that raises legitimacy concerns constitutes a human rights problem. That would be too narrow a focus. Constitutional approaches often lack a differentiated vocabulary to grasp hugely different phenomena of global governance.

(c) Global administrative law

A third approach to deal with the phenomena of global governance in a specifically legal way seeks inspiration from administrative law thinking rather than from constitutionalism. Here again, different varieties exist. Probably the most far-reaching one is the project of global administrative law, which suggests that much of global governance can be understood as administration and demands that it be regulated by administrative law principles such as transparency, participation, reasoned decision making and mechanisms of review. 92 While some scholars aim at the deductive development of such principles, 93 others proceed inductively and use the normative reservoir of domestic or European administrative law. 94

The common denominator of this strand of research – the emphasis on domestic administrative law – bears a great potential for innovation. Our approach corresponds inasmuch as we stress the usefulness of intra-disciplinary exchange in legal studies: the study of the law of international public institutions should be informed by the study of domestic public institutions. 95 The full development of international law as international public law appears hardly feasible without building on national administrative legal insights and doctrines elaborated in the past century.

Our approach differs from the global administrative law approach as we regard it as being too ‘global’. It risks effacing or blurring the distinctions that are essential to the construction, evaluation and application of norms concerning public authority. Our very term international public law stresses that the validity, legality, legal effects and legitimacy of acts under international law depend on criteria that are specific to the international legal order. Whenever a legal issue comes up with respect to any act, the first step to tackle it legally is therefore to determine the legal order to which it belongs. Moreover, we wonder what would be the overarching legal basis of a global administrative law. Would it be general principles or would it have a status of its own, above positive law? The notion of global administrative law evokes a fusion of domestic administrative and international law that gives too little consideration to the fact that the validity and legal effects of international and domestic law follow very different rules. 96

In addition, global administrative law hinges on the imprecise concept of administration. It casts its net very widely and extends its scope to the whole range of activities and actors on various levels. While it taps into a public law repertoire, it applies its standards not only to entities that qualify as international organizations but also to those that straddle the public/private divide just as well as hybrid institutions or even private transnational bodies. 97 What is then understood as administration is also extremely wide and, notably, includes the activity of international courts and tribunals. 98

Global administrative law draws together very different institutions and acts that raise demands for legitimacy that are markedly different. Administrative principles may be the part of the cure for some, but not for all. In contrast to global administrative law, as well as to international institutional law and constitutionalism, we place the concept of international public authority on centre stage. It allows us to focus on the specific requirements of typical instruments. Indeed, global administrative law is already using the concept of authority, and our elaboration will continue on this path. 99

A Five Key Elements of International Public Law

The comparative sketch of international public law yields five key elements of our theory of international public law. First, international public law is inspired by, and dependent on, domestic public law, but it is not fused with it. This approach caters for both the autonomy and the interdependence of the international and domestic legal orders; it does not merge them into one global (or transnational) law.

Second, although we understand world society as complex and pluralistic, we do not believe that these features render the formulation of common interests impossible. Rather, international public law provides the institutional framework for such public policies, even in the absence of a world state or other forms of deep political integration, such as the European Union.

A third distinctive feature is the centrality of the concept of international public authority. The public law approach focuses on the acts that claim to pursue common interests and therefore require a public law framework that ensures their legitimacy, regardless of their legal nature. International public law is the law applicable to the exercise of international public authority. International public law, therefore, excludes the strictly horizontal phenomena of public international law that do not claim to pursue common interests. It includes, however, phenomena that are beyond the source-based understanding of international law, such as the G7.

The concept of authority leads to a fourth core feature. It is defined by its impact on freedom. Freedom is the main rationale underlying the public law approach, both in its political dimension, which entitles people to collectively exercise public power, and in its individual dimension, which is reflected in human rights. International public law focuses on the impact of concrete acts upon freedom. Moreover, freedom provides guidance for the reconstruction of the public law framework. It needs to ensure that public authority respects freedom in its political or individual dimension.

Closely linked is a fifth feature. Our theory of international public law ought to enable doctrinal reconstructions translating complex social relationships into a language of legality. While we stress the need for theoretical reflection, we consider the eventual orientation of practice to be the leading, though certainly not exclusive, goal of legal scholarship. This sets the framework for the methodology that we adopt. We think that a focus on interpretation and doctrinal reconstruction is of particular help for advancing the practical uses of legal scholarship. Whereas few lawyers master techniques of social research or political theory, they globally share the techniques of interpreting and applying the law. For this reason, our theory for identifying international public authority will be framed in such a way that it can be interpreted and applied like other legal concepts. 100

Legal scholarship stands with respect to the conceptualization of international institutions approximately where it stood with respect to domestic institutions a century ago at the dawn of the modern administrative state. 101 There is little more than the intuition that something new has come into existence, combined with a troubling impression of opaqueness and confusion. Although Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s statement that the Owl of Minerva only takes flight at dusk when the shades of night are gathering is a poetic exaggeration, the scholarly framing of new phenomena lags behind their actual development. The successful theorization of emergent realities is a slow process. Sound scholarship needs to be rooted in the concreteness of multifarious reality. At the same time, it must reach for parsimonious abstractions. In this double sense, it should be reconstructive. Patient observation and creative innovation should meet in spiralling, dialectical reasoning. Otherwise, to use a Kantian metaphor, the empirics (or legal practice) remains blind and theory (or doctrinal concepts) remains void.

At the beginning, a new scholarly approach faces the difficulty that there are only old concepts for new phenomena, which appear inadequate. One way to proceed is to craft new terms. Governance and accountability are fine examples. They have helped to identify the phenomena and the normative challenges. Yet they can hardly be fleshed out without being linked to the grand old concepts. And these concepts are like prima ballerinas: as soon as they appear on the scene, they take the limelight and outshine the new terms. Scholars have been seeking to adapt those grand concepts, such as sovereignty, legitimacy, constitutionalism, pluralism and, with an even clearer normative ambition, the rule of law, human rights and democracy. In this exercise, the very nature of the concepts comes to the fore: they receive meaning from their interaction. Accordingly, the entire conceptual web needs adaptation, a process to which the concept of authority came late. 102

The following two sections elaborate the concept of international public authority. The function of this concept is to identify acts of international institutions that should be legally reconstructed according to the public law paradigm because they advance common interests in a way that impacts upon the freedom of others. This allows for a novel, much broader legal reconstruction of complex social relationships.

B International Public Authority

1 international character.

Whether an act amounts to an exercise of international public authority, in contrast to domestic or supranational authority, depends on the provision it invokes as a legal basis, be it implicitly or explicitly. If this provision belongs to public international law, then such an exercise of authority is international. What then belongs to the realm of public international law? The established sources of treaties, custom and general principles provide guidance in most cases. Some acts, however, are based on soft legal instruments – for example, the Basel Accords by the Basel Committee on Banking Supervision. Soft law created by states or international institutions should be included in the canon of possible legal bases because, in the context of global governance, it often plays a functionally equivalent role to hard law. 103 The choice between soft law and hard law as a legal basis should not allow governments and international institutions to escape normative requirements, and, indeed, the respective legal regimes are often similar. 104

The insistence on the distinction between domestic and international law is criticized for being too limited. 105 We do not deny the global, multilevel or transnational structure of many policies. However, we see the more narrow focus as justified by two main considerations. First, reconstructive legal scholarship needs to respond to the basic structures of the law. As we argued in respect to global administrative law, legal analysis and legal argument should distinguish between domestic and international law and, therefore, also between domestic and international authority. 106 This distinction is crucial to enabling a thorough analysis of the twin concerns of legitimacy and effectiveness in the pursuit of common interests. The validity, legality, legitimacy and legal effects of an act depend largely on the legal order to which it belongs. Likewise, whenever the question arises whether the protection of common interests requires additional forms of authority, then the challenge of making such authority legitimate and effective varies with the legal order in which it is rooted. Nobody will claim that the exercise of international authority is legitimized in a way that corresponds to the mechanisms that legitimize domestic authority. Neither a world parliament nor a world government exists. Domestic courts treat exercises of international public authority differently from domestic authority, thereby granting international institutions wider discretion. 107 Likewise, international institutions cannot regulate a certain issue in the same way as domestic institutions. Rather, they normally rely on the executive capacity of the domestic level.

The second argument for our focus rests on a principled consideration of political freedom. International law and international authority have a unique potential for political inclusion. If politics and policies are to serve several polities, there is no other legal order that is capable of achieving a similar degree of inclusion. Notwithstanding the many conceptual and practical challenges of democratizing international institutions, there are no viable alternatives in sight. Hegemony, informal governmental networks or outsourcing to private institutions fare much worse in this respect. Thus, our choice for international law as the legal order that has the potential to be the most inclusive polity echoes Winston Churchill’s bon mot on democracy: ‘It’s the worst, except for all the others.’

2 Publicness

It is far more difficult to pin down what makes international authority public. Given the various meanings as well as trenchant critiques of the public–private distinction, 108 this difficulty is not surprising. Indeed, one might well succumb to doubt, especially in light of the messy complexities that mire global governance. 109 A distinction of this kind arguably does more harm than good, for example, by leaving the exercise of power in the private realm out of sight. 110 We agree that it is impossible to understand the cosmos of global governance without considering private and hybrid actors. Yet the importance of such actors does not render the public–private distinction useless but, rather, confirms its significance.

This dichotomy enables us to distinguish – to give but one example – entities as different as the UN and Blackwater (which is today known as Academi). It is undeniable that international institutions such as the UN or the World Bank operate under a different legal regime compared to transnational corporations. The public–private divide, with all of its problems, provides an important stock of knowledge to elaborate this difference. Granted, there are attempts at building overarching legal regimes, in particular, by using human rights. 111 But even if some aspects of human rights apply directly to private institutions, 112 a plethora of differences remain. 113

The distinction between public and private law responds to a fundamental differentiation in modern societies. Most will agree that, whatever the eventual definitions, private action – in particular, private economic activity – and public action belong to different social spheres and must respond to different operational logics and justificatory requirements. 114 Public and private law provide the legal frameworks for activities that follow different rationales. Most importantly, private law allows actors to act solely in pursuit of their self-interest, whereas public law requires a higher standard, often coined as the pursuit of a common interest. Though of continental European origin, the distinction has spread through the world of common law. It is important to note that the United Kingdom shares this understanding of public law. 115 The experience of the USA is different, but no other legal order has a comparable tradition in regard to constitutional adjudication. And, even with respect to it, the 20th century witnessed the consolidation of administrative law. 116 Of course, there have been attempts to overcome the public–private divide, the most notable example being state socialism, but its consequences were highly dysfunctional.

It is difficult to apply the distinction to global governance; however, that alone gives no reason to abandon it. The apparent hybridity of some institutions, often advanced as an argument against the distinction, 117 rather reinforces it – any observation of hybridity requires an understanding of the individual components that render something hybrid. For instance, a hybrid car is a car that uses a combustion engine and an electric motor, and a mule is a cross between a horse and a donkey. There are, as always, difficult cases of qualification, but this does not undermine the utility of conceptual differentiations.

(a) Publicness and common interest

Concepts enable us to understand and deal with reality. Our overall aim is to provide a legal concept in line with calls in world public opinion for effective and legitimate international action that advances common, or public, interests. According to world public opinion, the public character of an act thus derives from its relation to common interests. It depends on the social sphere from which it originates. If the activity is part of the sphere where self-interest is a sufficient justification, the act is private; if it belongs to the sphere where common interests are predominant, it is public. We therefore define the publicness of international authority and international public law in accordance with the basic differentiation in modern societies. Of course, the differentiation is less clear in world society than in most domestic societies, but it should be apparent that the UN, the Basel Committee and the World Bank are categorically different from, say, Academi, Goldman Sachs or Exxon.

Contrasting this approach with other understandings of publicness further exposes its main thrust. In public international law, there is a widespread understanding that international law is public because it governs the relations between public institutions, with its opposite being private international law (or conflict of laws). 118 But as global governance studies have shown, there are more actors involved than states. Another understanding uses the public–private distinction to define the competences of (domestic) administrative courts 119 or a specific regime of (domestic) administrative responsibility. 120 This is also not an option for the international realm since such institutions or regimes hardly exist there. 121 Closer to our interest is the definition whereby ‘public’ refers to a relationship of subordination not justified by direct consent. 122 However, the convoluted structure of most instances of global governance makes it nearly impossible to define ‘publicness’ in terms of hierarchy or asymmetric relationships. Moreover, hierarchy and asymmetric relationships imply an element of ‘authority’, and we do not wish to equal publicness and authority.

According to yet another conception, an institution is public if it operates under a privileged legal regime. In the past, one function of public (or administrative) law was to protect administrative institutions against judicial review by the common courts. This definition is persuasive in light of the concerns articulated in world public opinion, given the broad immunity of international institutions in domestic courts and the scarcity of international review. Immunities raise doubts about the legitimacy of their acts. Indeed, some institutions advance policies that would not withstand the control of domestic courts, as the saga of the Kadi cases demonstrates. 123 However, this immunity derives from the international character of those institutions. Therefore, it would make little sense to also use this feature for defining publicness.

By contrast, in our context, it makes a lot of sense for publicness to turn on the pursuit of a common interest or common good. 124 This understanding comes with a considerable pedigree. 125 It already existed in antiquity, as reflected in the distinction in Roman law between ius publicum and ius privatum , although one should certainly not overlook the differences between Roman society and today’s society. 126 For our purpose, the pursuit of a common interest hinges on the legal mandate, whatever its legal qualification, including soft law. We thus define an exercise of authority as public if the actor claims that the legal basis of the act mandates it to advance a common interest.

(b) The claim to advance a common interest

The definition lends itself to legal operationalization because it refers to the legal basis of an act and is therefore open to legal interpretation. The first interpretative step is to determine the norm that the actor invokes explicitly or implicitly as a legal basis, followed by an interpretation of that norm to determine if it requires the pursuit of a common interest. Other conditions of legality that the act must meet are not relevant for the purposes of its classification as public.

We focus only on the claim to have a mandate to pursue a common interest because the publicness criterion that we propose only defines the legal regime that determines the conditions for the legality of the act. In addition, for an act to qualify as public, it suffices that there is a reasonable presumption of acting under the claimed mandate. Whether the mandate actually exists and covers the activity is a different question – one of legality – which is to be settled subsequently in accordance with the respective substantive and procedural requirements. It does not affect its qualification as being public. As in the case of domestic legal orders, illegal exercises of public authority exist. 127 This is where our definition differs from Benedict Kingsbury and Megan Donaldson, who require that an act meets certain substantive or procedural principles in order to be considered public. 128

This complex definition serves another important function: to distinguish the common interest from the activities of public interest groups. Whereas such groups claim to further the common interest, they lack a specific mandate. Indeed, many public interest groups, such as Greenpeace or Transparency International, play an important role and contribute to the common interest. They may be mandated by their members, but they claim to advance interests of individuals that extend beyond their membership. International organizations, by contrast, are entitled to advance policies in the common interest. International as well as domestic law makes a clear difference in this respect. Of course, some might consider international organizations to be just as self-interested as private corporations and as demonstrating less public spirit than some non-governmental organizations. However, from a legal standpoint, the difference in the mandate to pursue the common interest is all too obvious.

Our understanding of what makes an act public begs the question regarding how to define a common or public interest in a pluralistic world society. As Kelsen, critical legal studies and feminism have shown, to define something as public is a highly political issue that has important repercussions. 129 Several possibilities come to mind. One might resort to a list of issues believed to be too important to be left to the private realm. However, such a criterion is too vague and too contested. Jeremy Waldron, similar to Kingsbury and Donaldson, suggests certain elements of the public rule of law. Among them are the idea of a rule by legal rules, the limitation of discretionary powers and the availability of legal review. 130 However, this approach certainly does not grasp what world public opinion sees as the core international common interests, namely poverty reduction, human rights advancement, environmental protection and economic stability.

In the end, it is only the public itself – that is, a community and its institutions – that can define common interests. An actor may thus claim to articulate a common interest if it is mandated to act on behalf of a community (including the international community). At first sight, this replaces one problematic definition with another one: what is a community? Two thousand years of political theory have dealt with this question. 131 Given the deep cleavages in the discussion, it is advisable to rely on the law instead of tying the definition of publicness to a specific theory. This also allows for a plurality of approaches. At the same time, there is wide consensus that a community requires at least an institutional framework for the articulation of a common interest. 132 That is a question of the interpretation of its mandate.

Our approach does not lead to academic science fiction: the term ‘international community’, though vague, is well established in international law and politics, as is the term ‘community interest’. 133 Of course, many theoretical and empirical questions persist. For example, one might debate whether the international community is a community of states or of individuals or whether the UN General Assembly is mandated to articulate its interests. 134 Be that as it may, there are certainly other communities, be they regional or functional, which may formulate common interests through their respective institutions. To sum up, publicness is established by reference to the legal mandate – hard or soft – that the act invokes explicitly or implicitly. If the mandate equips an international institution with the power to define and pursue a common interest, any authority that the institution might exercise in this frame should be qualified as public. But what is authority?

3 Authority

To provide an understanding of the authority for international institutions is just as intricate. Traditionally speaking, public authority is equated with state power, sovereignty and the legitimate means of coercion. On this account, international institutions would not exercise authority. However, many citizens experience international institutions as having a powerful impact on their lives. Our concept of international public authority is a scholarly response that elaborates such perceptions. It credits the fact that impact can have many faces other than physical coercion and overwhelming force, so that a broader definition of authority is needed.

Inspired by world public opinion and the core idea of the public law approach, we take freedom to be the decisive criterion for broadening the concept of authority. Authority is defined as the acts based on international law that impact other actors’ freedom. Such impact may materialize by changing a legal position or by legally obliging a person to act in a certain way or to suffer a sanction, but it may also be factual. The impact may affect humans not only individually but also – as is usually the case with international public authority – collectively – that is, when an act addresses entities such as states. 135

To posit freedom as the guiding idea is, of course, a choice, but it is a reconstructive one that is supported by both theoretical reflection and legal developments. In many legal orders, public law is guided by this idea. Freedom, as we understand it, refers to the freedom of individuals – that is to say, both their private and their public freedom. The public freedom of individuals consists, on the most abstract level, in meaningful inclusion in the political process that determines the common interest. Private freedom embraces the full development of the individual. 136 This concept of freedom is far broader than that of liberty, which merely stands against interference with rights such as property rights. 137 It squares neatly with the triad of obligations to respect, protect and fulfil in contemporary human rights law. 138 Acts that impact on this freedom are so important that they require specific justification. The legal aspect of that justification is our topic.

Our understanding of international public authority as international law-based acts impacting other actors’ freedom is broad, but it is distinct from yet broader concepts such as power, hegemony, dominance or leverage. Exercises of international public authority imply the claim to be mandated by international law to impact somebody else’s freedom. As is the case with publicness, this does not mean that an illegal act would disqualify as an exercise of authority. There can be illegal exercises of authority, and the act might become the object of a legal dispute. In many legal orders, it is crucial that an exercise of public authority ( puissance public , öffentliche Gewalt ) can be challenged as illegal and quashed by appropriate institutions without losing its qualification as an exercise of public authority. Similarly, it is worth reminding our readers that this understanding of authority is to be distinguished from legitimacy: authority implies a rebuttable claim to legitimacy. 139 In this respect, our concept is in line with Joseph Raz’s influential understanding of authority. 140

C The Many Faces of International Public Authority

What does it take to affect freedom? The authority of domestic public institutions rests, according to received wisdom, on their competence to use physical coercion to make a person or entity act as they command. Sometimes, acts of international institutions are backed up by credible means of coercion, such as some UN Security Council resolutions. 141 However, this is not typically the case. We identify and explain three ‘softer’ and more common mechanisms through which international institutions might affect freedom. 142

1 Clever Compliance Mechanisms

One type of mechanism that often provides policies with ‘teeth’, so to speak, are financial sanctions or benefits. This form of power is well recognized at the international level. From the world of international adjudication, we note that a trade measure found to be in violation of international trade law may give rise to sensitive countermeasures. 143 A recent award of damages by ICSID amounted to approximately US $2.3 billion. 144 It may be enforced in domestic courts. Such obligations hurt and impact freedom. Domestic legislatures might abstain from legislative projects for fear of expensive claims for damages. Financial benefits may have a comparable impact. Many countries have reformed important parts of their domestic law according to the policies of the Bank for International Reconstruction and Development and the International Monetary Fund (IMF) in order to qualify for the financial support they needed. International institutions use benefits as a means to force their policies upon states. 145

A further mechanism that ensures compliance is the threat to exclude a state from international cooperation if it does not heed the policies of international institutions. It rests on an important feature that undergirds international institutions’ authority: reputation. The failure to honour a decision by an international institution entails reputational costs that might be relevant even for heavyweight actors like the United States 146 or Russia. 147 Of course, all too often states – especially mighty ones – defy international decisions. But, in the present interdependent world, states depend far more on international cooperation than before. 148 In order to avoid a reputational loss, actors are motivated to comply and thereby support the authority of the act in question.

According to this logic, it is also possible to argue that non-binding or even non-legal acts can amount to exercises of international public authority in that they impact freedom. 149 Whoever violates non-binding or non-legal instruments does not need to fear damages or reprisals. But they might face other, more indirect sanctions. The black list of uncooperative states in matters of money laundering set up by the Financial Action Task Force showed that the prospect of being on such a list even induces rising powers like China to respect the corresponding international standards. 150

2 Semantic Authority

The authority of international acts can also rest on their capacity to shape the terms of international discourse. An important example is the effect of international acts on the distribution of argumentative burdens. 151 The function of precedents is illustrative. International judicial decisions are not considered binding beyond the parties to the dispute. 152 And, yet, the dynamics of legal discourse and the normative expectation that like cases should be decided alike trigger argumentative burdens for those who wish to make a legal argument. A party that seeks redress in the context of world trade law against rules on wildlife protection will find itself compelled to base its reasoning on the Appellate Body report in EC – Seals , whether it agrees with the report or not. 153 Any legal counsel to a dispute will do her best to use all earlier reports that suit her position. Rather than saying that precedents are non-binding for non-disputing parties, counsel will argue with precedents to possibly spin them in their favour. In effect, they fight over the meaning of earlier decisions just as they fight over WTO agreements.

Judges and arbitrators are expected to respond to the arguments advanced by the parties. They even have a genuine interest in using precedents as they support their decisions and suggest coherence. Thus, the WTO Appellate Body held that WTO panels should follow earlier decisions because they create legitimate expectations. 154 This testifies to the semantic authority of courts and similar international institutions – that is to say, the capacity to establish reference points for legal discourse. 155 Anyone making legal arguments needs to submit to such discursive constraints. They become part of the rules of the game.

In order to understand such authority, it is important to widen the view towards the social context and discursive construction of authority and not to limit it to the bilateral relationship suggested by the ‘command-and-obey’ logic underpinning traditional understandings of authority. Authority, in this sense, emerges when a broader social belief holds that B should do x because A said so. 156 Actors might even internalize the terms of the discourse. This brings us to issues of how power is exercised through cognitive frames. 157

3 Governance by Information

Acts of international institutions may further impact the freedom of others by influencing their knowledge and perceptions. 158 Governance by information has become a particularly important instrument on the global level. Michel Foucault has analysed its function in the modern state. 159 His research on gouvernementalité emphasizes that binding law is only one form of governing people. Once the modern state started aiming at governing the economy and people’s social life, it developed a multiplicity of further instruments in order to discipline people, to guide them and frame their mindsets. 160 Accordingly, instruments such as information and conceptual frames are highly significant for understanding authority.

On the international level, governance by information impacts a given policy field by creating pressure on, or shaping the cognitive framework of, policy makers through the collection, processing and dissemination of information. 161 Many empirical studies have shown how such governance operates. 162 Cognitive frames influence which facts we observe and consider important and how we react to them. 163 International institutions seek recourse to governance by information in order to advance international policies. Examples abound. The OECD provides comparative data about the performance of school policies. Its Program for International Student Assessment (PISA) publishes detailed reports every three years as well as a ranking list. 164 It also publishes the OECD Economic Outlooks, which provide important advice for macro-economic policy making, 165 while investment decisions are guided by the ‘Doing Business’ reports of the World Bank. 166 The UN Development Programme developed the Human Development Index indicating the level of development, assessing the overall outcome of domestic politics. 167 Indicators provide a powerful mechanism for policy making because they make data accessible and enjoy huge trust and press for policies suggested by the data. 168 At the very least, those who disagree are put under a severe burden of justification.

Of course, it is difficult to determine which information acts are influential enough that they constitute exercises of authority and should therefore be framed according to the public law paradigm. However, our theoretical framework, combined with information from the field, provides good guidance. Take the example of the PISA program of the OECD. Its impact on policy making rests both on long-term developments such as changing attitudes about education and on the immediate use of the survey data, for example, for the allocation of funding. A rough indicator of impact is the press coverage after the release of a new PISA report. 169 A more reliable indicator might be government reform projects that can be identified as direct or indirect consequences of PISA, especially if they differ from past educational policies. For PISA, a wealth of arguments justifies considering the publication of rankings as an exercise of public authority and, therefore, to reconstruct the legal framework according to the public law paradigm, not least because it concerns a sensitive policy field.

Which acts ultimately amount to exercises of international public authority hinges on the degree to which they impact freedom. Where to draw the line is a question of judgement or political choice. Our theoretical framework cannot substitute such judgment or choice, but it can inform it. Legal scholarship may then offer a set of standardized instruments that facilitate the identification of acts of international public authority and render a legal regime applicable to them, thereby ensuring a basic level of legitimacy. 170 This has been elaborated for the OECD PISA programme elsewhere. 171

Some might consider that the project of translating world public opinion into more legitimate standard instruments of stronger multilateral institutions is too reminiscent of the hopes triggered by the fall of the Berlin wall. Since then, concepts such as state power, bilateralism, geopolitics or realism have crept back to the forefront of global politics. 172 Given the impotence of international institutions in the light of pressing crises such as the conflict in Eastern Ukraine, Syria or the refugee crisis on the Mediterranean Sea, a theory of international public authority might be regarded as insufficient and myopic. However, the public law approach neither suggests, nor implies, a progression to a harmonious world wisely regulated by illuminated international institutions. Far from it. As set out at the beginning, our basic stance reflects the ambivalence of world public opinion. More importantly, many international institutions, while impotent in some respects, continue to impact people’s lives in many ways. The IMF, for instance, is far busier now than in the decade preceding the global financial crisis. And the negotiations for a Transatlantic Trade and Investment Partnership, whatever its ultimate fate, show that political projects for powerful international institutions are not a relict of the past. Many individuals have an acute awareness of international public authority. They mistrust the policies of international institutions while calling on them to improve their lot. The public law approach considers this as both a rational and a realist reaction and tries to give it a legal frame.

Zürn and Ecker-Ehrhardt, ‘Politisierung als Konzept der Internationalen Beziehungen’, in M. Zürn and M. Ecker-Ehrhardt (eds), Die Politisierung der Weltpolitik (2013) 7; Furia, ‘Global Citizenship, Anyone? Cosmopolitanism, Privilege and Public Opinion’, 19 Global Society (2005) 331. Much evidence is to be found in the detailed studies published at www.WorldPublicOpinion.org ; for the USA, see Council on Foreign Relations, US Opinion on International Institutions, available at www.cfr.org/international-organizations-and-alliances/us-opinion-international-institutions/p20131 (last visited 22 December 2016).

E.g., E. Benvenisti, The Law of Global Governance (2014); J. Brunnée and S. Toope, Legitimacy and Legality in International Law. An Interactional Account (2010); Cassese, ‘Administrative Law without the State? The Challenge of Global Regulation’, 37 New York University Journal of International Law and Policy ( NYUJILP ) (2005) 663; Chimni, ‘International Institutions Today: An Imperial Global State in the Making’, 15 European Journal of International Law ( EJIL ) (2004) 1; Kingsbury, Krisch and Stewart, ‘The Emergence of Global Administrative Law’, 68 Law and Contemporary Problems (2005) 15; J. Klabbers, A. Peters and G. Ulfstein (eds), The Constitutionalization of International Law (2009).

The terminology is used in Kadelbach, ‘From Public International Law to International Public Law’, in A. von Bogdandy et al . (eds), The Exercise of Public Authority by International Institutions (2010) 33.

E.g., J. Pauwelyn, R.A. Wessel and J. Wouters (eds), Informal International Lawmaking (2012); K.E. Davis et al . (eds), Governance by Indicators: Global Power through Classification and Rankings (2012); J.E. Alvarez, International Organizations as Law-Makers (2005).

See Report of the Second Panel Established pursuant to the Note by the President of the Security Council (S/1999/100) of 30 January 1999, Concerning the Current Humanitarian Situation in Iraq, UN Doc. S/1999/356, 30 March 1999, para. 45.

ECtHR, Nada v. Switzerland , Appl. 10593/08, Judgment of 12 September 2012; C.A. Feinäugle, Hoheitsgewalt im Völkerrecht: Das 1267-Sanktionsregime der UN und seine rechtliche Fassung (2011).

E.g., see Fix-Fierro and López-Ayllón, ‘The Impact of Globalization on the Reform of the State and the Law in Latin America’, 19 Houston Journal of International Law (1996–1997) 785, at 795; J.M. Serna de la Garza, Impacto e implicaciones constitucionales de la globalización en el sistema jurídico mexicano (2012) 111ff; Bradlow, ‘The World Bank, the IMF, and Human Rights’, 6 Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems (1996) 47.

von Bogdandy and Goldmann, ‘Taming and Framing Indicators: A Legal Reconstruction of the OECD’s Programme for International Student Assessment (PISA)’, in K.E. Davis et al . (eds), Governance by Indicators: Global Power through Classification and Rankings (2012) 52.

Further examples in A. von Bogdandy et al. (eds), The Exercise of Public Authority by International Institutions: Advancing International Institutional Law (2010); A. von Bogdandy and I. Venzke (eds), International Judicial Lawmaking (2012). For the overall project that has been ongoing for 10 years, see www.mpil.de/de/pub/forschung/nach-rechtsgebieten/voelkerrecht/ipa.cfm (last visited 22 December 2016).

Chimni, ‘Capitalism, Imperialism, and International Law in the Twenty-First Century’, 14 Oregon Review of International Law (2012) 17; S. Pahuja, Decolonizing International Law: Development, Economic Growth and the Politics of Universality (2011).

This, of course, is not a definition in the sense of a hard and fast rule for classifying and judging complex phenomena as one might expect from lawyers trained in the continental tradition; on that issue, see Reimann, ‘The American Advantage in Global Lawyering’, 78 Rabels Zeitschrift für ausländisches und internationales Privatrecht (2014) 1, at 12–13, 21–23.

Legitimacy and effectiveness are not opposing concepts. Effective political problem solving is a possible source of output legitimacy but certainly not sufficient under a public law paradigm. See the seminal F.W. Scharpf, Governing in Europe: Effective and Democratic? (1999), at 6ff.

Weiler, ‘The International Society for Public Law’, 12 International Journal of Constitutional Law ( IJCL ) (2014) 1.

Janis, ‘Jeremy Bentham and the Fashioning of “International Law”’, 78 American Journal of International Law ( AJIL ) (1984) 405, at 408.

J. Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832), at 208; G.W.F. Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (1821), at para. 333.

H. Triepel, Völkerrecht und Landesrecht (1899); L. Oppenheim, International Law: A Treatise (1905); J. Westlake, International Law (1904); G.F. von Martens, A Compendium of the Law of Nations: Founded on the Treaties and Customs of the Modern Nations of Europe , translated by William Cobbett (1802); more recent authors include Weil, ‘Towards Relative Normativity in International Law?’, 77 AJIL (1983) 413, at 441; Wedgwood, ‘The International Criminal Court: An American View’, 10 EJIL (1999) 93, at 99ff; Hillgruber, ‘Souveränität: Verteidigung eines Rechtsbegriffs’, 57 Juristenzeitung (2002) 1072.

Especially from the vantage point of natural law, J.C. Bluntschli, Das moderne Voelkerrecht der civilisirten Staten als Rechtsbuch dargestellt (1872).

N. Krisch, ‘The Decay of Consent: International Law in an Age of Global Public Goods’, 108 AJIL (2014) 1. This development reaches back about one century. See in detail M. Goldmann, Internationale öffentliche Gewalt. Handlungsformen internationaler Institutionen im Zeitalter der Globalisierung (2015), at 19–93.

Weiler, ‘The Geology of International Law: Governance, Democracy and Legitimacy’, 64 Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht ( ZaöRV ) (2004) 547.

Cf. J. d’Aspremont (ed.), Participants in the International Legal System: Multiple Perspectives on Non-State Actors in International Law (2011). The ambivalent notion of ‘law-making treaties’ testifies to the travails of the private law paradigm, see C. Brölmann, ‘Law-Making Treaties: Form and Function in International Law’, 74 Nordic Journal of International Law (2005) 383.

See the sharp overview in Caruso, ‘Private Law and State-Making in the Age of Globalization’, 39 NYUJILP (2006) 1.

E. Jouannet, The Liberal-Welfarist Law of Nations (2012), at 205–215.

Benvenisti, ‘Collective Action in the Utilization of Shared Freshwater’, 90 AJIL (1996) 384, at 415; Benvenisti, ‘Sovereigns as Trustees of Humanity’, 107 AJIL (2013) 295.

Benvenisti, ‘Collective Action’ supra note 23, at 384–415.

Benvenisti, supra note 2, (2014), at 79–80.

J.L. Goldsmith and E.A. Posner, The Limits of International Law (2005).

Ibid. , at 212.

Ibid. , at 218–219.

E.g., Dunoff and Trachtman, ‘Economic Analysis of International Law’, 24 NYUJILP (1999), at 1; A.T. Guzman, How International Law Works: A Rational Choice Theory (2008).

E.g., Simmons, ‘Money and the Law: Why Comply with the Public International Law of Money?’, 25 NYUJILP (2000) 323; Trachtman, ‘The Economic Structure of the Law of International Organizations’, 15 Chicago Journal of International Law (2014) 162.

Koskenniemi, ‘Global Governance and Public International Law’, 37 Kritische Justiz (2004) 241, at 247ff; Cooney and Lang, ‘Taking Uncertainty Seriously: Adaptive Governance and International Trade’, 18 EJIL (2007) 523. The yardstick is helpfully modified in more recent research: van Aaken, ‘Behavioral International Law and Economics’, 55 Harvard International Law Journal (2014) 421, at 426, 432; Broude, ‘Behavioral International Law’, 163 University of Pennsylvania Law Review ( UPLR ) (2015) 1099, at 1116–1118.

In more detail, see von Bogdandy and Dellavalle, ‘The Lex Mercatoria of Systems Theory: Localisation, Reconstruction and Criticism from a Public Law Perspective’, 4 Transnational Legal Theory (2013) 59.

N. Luhmann, Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft (1997), at 65ff, 92ff, 102ff.

Ibid ., at 48ff.

Seminal: Teubner, ‘Global Bukowina’: Legal Pluralism in the World Society’, in G. Teubner (ed.), Global Law without a State (1997) 3, at 6.

Ibid. , at 40.

G. Teubner, Verfassungsfragmente: Gesellschaftlicher Konstitutionalismus in der Globalisierung (2012), at 82–85.

A. Fischer-Lescano and G. Teubner, Regime-Kollisionen: zur Fragmentierung des globalen Rechts (2006), at 52; Teubner, supra note 37, at 225ff.

For private international law, see Watt, ‘Private International Law Beyond the Schism’, 2 Transnational Legal Theory (2011) 347; for transnational law, see G.-P. Calliess and P. Zumbansen, Rough Consensus and Running Code: A Theory of Transnational Private Law (2009); for global law, see H. Lindahl, Fault Lines of Globalization: Legal Order and the Politics of A-Legality (2013).

P. Zumbansen, ‘Transnational Legal Pluralism’, 1 Transnational Legal Theory (2010) 141; Calliess and Maurer, ‘Transnationales Recht: eine Einleitung’, in G.-P. Calliess (ed.), Transnationales Recht (2014) 1.

Seminal: Rosenau, ‘Governance, Order, and Change in World Politics’, in J.N. Rosenau and E.-O. Czempiel (eds), Governance without Government (1992) 1.

I. Venzke, ‘International Bureaucracies from a Political Science Perspective: Agency, Authority and International Institutional Law’, in A. von Bogdandy et al . (eds), The Exercise of Public Authority by International Institutions: Advancing International Institutional Law (2010) 67.

This distinguishes our approach from J. d’Aspremont, Formalism and the Sources of International Law: A Theory of the Ascertainment of Legal Rules (2011), at 128–130.

Koskenniemi, supra note 31, at 241. On the related liberal bias of international organizations, see Barnett and Finnemore, ‘The Power of Liberal International Organizations’, in M. Barnett and R. Duvall (eds), Power in Global Governance (2005) 161, at 163–169.

Slaughter, ‘The Accountability of Government Networks’, 8 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies (2000–2001) 347.

Koh, ‘Transnational Legal Process’, 75 Nebraska Law Review (1996) 181; Reisman, ‘The Democratization of Contemporary International Law-Making Processes and the Differentiation of Their Application’, in R. Wolfrum and V. Röben (eds), Developments of International Law in Treaty Making (2005) 15, at 24–26.

Hanschmann, ‘Theorie transnationaler Rechtsprozesse’, in S. Buckel, R. Christensen and A. Fischer-Lescano (eds), Neue Theorien des Rechts (2006) 347, at 357.

Koh, supra note 46.

Cf. P. Schiff Berman, Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law beyond Borders (2012).

See E. Schmidt-Aßmann, Das Allgemeine Verwaltungsrecht als Ordnungsidee (2004), at 16–18; N. Walker, Intimations of Global Law (2015), at 90–91. See also Kingsbury, ‘International Law as Inter-Public Law’, in H.S. Richardson and M.S. Williams (eds), Moral Universalism and Pluralism (2009) 167.

Chimni, supra note 2; A. Anghie, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law (2005), at 115.

Koskenniemi, supra note 31, at 241; M. Koskenniemi, ‘The Politics of International Law: 20 Years Later’, 20 EJIL (2009) 7; with different background but similar direction, see Benvenisti and Downs, ‘The Empire’s New Clothes: Political Economy and the Fragmentation of International Law’, 60 Stanford Law Review (2007) 595.

M. Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument (2nd edn, 2005); Kennedy, ‘Theses about International Law Discourse’, 23 German Yearbook of International Law (1980) 353.

M. Koskenniemi, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations (2002), at 495.

H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre (1934), at 109–114; H. Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law , translated by Max Knight (2nd edn, 1967), at 281–284.

D. Kennedy, ‘The Stages of the Decline of the Public/Private Distinction’, 130 UPLR (1981–1982) 1349, at 1352; N. Fraser, Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse, and Gender in Contemporary Social Theory (1989).

In detail, see section 3.B.2 below.

U. Kischel, Rechtsvergleichung (2015), at 101.

Koskenniemi, supra note 31, suggests that the reasons for this divergence of legality and legitimacy lies in the deformalization, fragmentation and the hegemonic traits of the current world order. On these aspects, see also Benvenisti and Downs, supra note 52, at 595. J. von Bernstorff and I. Venzke, ‘Ethos, Ethics and Morality in International Relations’, in R. Wolfrum (ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law (2009).

On administrative review in socialist countries, e.g., G. Brunner, Kontrollfunktion und Kontrollorgane in der Sowjetunion und in Mitteldeutschland (1967); on administrative review in Franco’s Spain, see P.G. Pascual, Los cuerpos de funcionarios de la administración pública española (1960).

For a compelling argument in this regard, see C. Möllers, The Three Branches: A Comparative Model of Separation of Powers (2013), at 4.

C.F. Amerasinghe, Principles of the Institutional Law of International Organizations (2nd edn, 2005); J. Klabbers, An Introduction to International Institutional Law (2nd edn, 2009); H.G. Schermers and N. Blokker, International institutional Law: Unity within Diversity (5th edn, 2011).

Cf. Legality of the Use by a State of Nuclear Weapons in Armed Conflicts , Advisory Opinion, 8 July 1996, ICJ Reports (1996) 75, para. 19; see also Schermers and Blokker, supra note 62, at para. 44. On the autonomy of international organizations, see R. Collins and N.D. White (eds), International Organizations and the Idea of Autonomy (2011).

Kennedy, ‘The Move to Institutions’, 8 Cardozo Law Review (1968) 841.

Klabbers, ‘The Emergence of Functionalism in International Institutional Law: Colonial Inspirations’, 25 EJIL (2014) 645. See also Reinsch, ‘International Unions and Their Administration’, 1 AJIL (1907) 579.

D. Mitrany, A Working Peace System (1943); Mitrany, ‘The Functional Approach to World Organization’, 24 International Affairs (1948) 350.

W.G. Friedmann, The Changing Structure of International Law (1964), at 12.

Ibid. , at 37ff, 213ff.

P. Allott, The Health of Nations: Society and Law beyond the State (2002), at 297.

See Klabbers, ‘The EJIL Foreword: The Transformation of International Organizations Law’, 26 EJIL (2015) 9.

Ibid ., see also A. Boyle and C. Chinkin, The Making of International Law (2007); Pauwelyn, Wessels and Wouters, supra note 4. On competencies, see Ruffert, ‘Zuständigkeitsgrenzen internationaler Organisationen im institutionellen Rahmen der internationalen Gemeinschaft’, 38 Archiv des Völkerrechts (2000) 129; D. Sarooshi, International Organizations and Their Exercise of Sovereign Powers (2005).

A good example for how this can be done is Alvarez, supra note 4.

Friedmann, supra note 67, at 40ff.

Recently, Alvarez, ‘Is Investor-State Arbitration “Public”?’ Institute for International Law and Justice Working Paper no. 6 (2016).

Klabbers, supra note 62.

Cf. Klabbers, Peters and Ulfstein, supra note 2.

For its ancient roots, see Walker, supra note 50, at 87–88. For its thrust, see Peters, ‘Compensatory Constitutionalism: The Function and Potential of Fundamental International Norms and Structures’, 19 Leiden Journal of International Law (2006) 579; see also the editorial Wiener et al ., ‘Global Constitutionalism: Human Rights, Democracy and the Rule of Law’, 1 Global Constitutionalism (2012) 1.

The contrast between horizontal and vertical perceptions of world order becomes apparent by cross-reading the separate opinion of President Guillaume and the joint separate opinion of Judges Higgins, Kooijmans and Buergenthal in the Case Concerning the Arrest Warrant of 11 April 2000 (DR Congo v. Belgium ), Judgment, 14 February 2000, ICJ Reports (2002) 35, at 63.

E.g., Dunoff and Trachtman, ‘A Functional Approach to International Constitutionalization’, in J. Dunoff and J. Trachtman (eds), Ruling the World? (2009) 3; International Law Association, Accountability of International Organisations, Final Report (2004), available at http://www.ila-hq.org/en/committees/index.cfm/cid/9 (last visited 22 December 2016).

Cf. A.A. Cançado Trindade, International Law for Humankind: Towards a New Jus Gentium (2010), at 213; Tomuschat, ‘International Law: Ensuring the Survival of Mankind on the Eve of a New Century: General Course on Public International Law’, 281 Recueil des Cours (1999) 9, at 161–162; Peters, ‘Humanity as the A and Ω of Sovereignty’, 20 EJIL (2009) 513.

Cf. Frowein, ‘Konstitutionalisierung des Völkerrechts’, in K. Dicke et al. (eds), Völkerrecht und Internationales Privatrecht in einem sich globalisierenden internationalen System (2000) 427. This is classified as a semantic strategy, according to Diggelmann and Altwicker, ‘Is There Something Like a Constitution of International Law?’, 68 ZaöRV (2008) 623, at 632ff.

M. Ruffert and C. Walter, Institutionalised International Law (2015); Fassbender, ‘The United Nations Charter as Constitution of the International Community’, 36 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law (1998) 529; D. Cass, The Constitutionalization of the World Trade Organization (2005); Petersmann, ‘Multilevel Trade Governance in the WTO Requires Multilevel Constitutionalism’, in C. Joerges and E.-U. Petersmann (eds), Consitutionalism, Multilevel Trade Governance and Social Regulation (2006) 5.

See, e.g., Peters, supra note 77, at 583–584. On freedom as the overarching concept of modernity, see Hegel, supra note 15; Berlin, ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’, in I. Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (1969) 118; J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1972), para. 32; Preamble of the UN Charter: ‘We the peoples of the United Nations determined … to promote social progress and better standards of life in larger freedom.’ The idea of freedom brings together both public and private law. See M. Auer, Der privatrechtliche Diskurs der Moderne (2014), 15ff.

Kumm, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law: A Constitutionalist Framework of Analysis’, 15 EJIL (2004) 907.

Kumm et al. , ‘How Large Is the World of Global Constitutionalism?’, 3 Global Constitutionalism (2014) 1; M. Koskenniemi, ‘Constitutionalism as Mindset: Reflections on Kantian Themes about International Law and Globalization’, 8 Theoretical Inquiries 8 (2007) 9, at 22.

I. Kant, Zum Ewigen Frieden (1795).

MacCormick, ‘Beyond the Sovereign State’, 56 Modern Law Review ( MLR ) (1993) 1.

E.g., von Bogdandy, ‘Pluralism, Direct Effect, and the Ultimate Say: On the Relationship between International and Domestic Constitutional Law’, 6 IJCL (2008), at 397; on the Kadi cases, see, e.g., M. Avbelj, F. Fontanelli and G. Martinico (eds), Kadi on Trial: A Multifaceted Analysis of the Kadi Trial (2014). Court of First Instance, Kadi v. Council and Commission ( Kadi ), Case T-315/01, Judgment of 21 September 2005.

N. Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law (2011).

E.g., Walker, ‘The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism’, 65 MLR (2002) 317; Peters, ‘Dual Democracy’, in J. Klabbers, A. Peters and G. Ulfstein (eds), The Constitutionalization of International Law (2009) 263; Habermas, ‘Does the Constitutionalization of International Law Still Have a Chance?’, in J. Habermas, The Divided West , translated and edited by C. Cronin (2006), 115, at 141–142.

Habermas, ‘Konstitutionalisierung des Völkerrechts und die Legitimationsprobleme einer verfassten Weltgesellschaft’, in W. Brugger, U. Neumann and Stephan Kirste (eds), Rechtsphilosophie im 21: Jahrhundert (2008) 360, at 362.

Kingsbury, Krisch and Stewart, supra note 2, at 28; Stewart, ‘Remedying Disregard in Global Regulatory Governance: Accountability, Participation, and Responsiveness’, 108 AJIL (2014) 211; recently see also Benvenisti, supra note 2; Walker, supra note 50, at 106.

Kingsbury, ‘Omnilateralism and Partial International Communities: Contributions of the Emerging Global Administrative Law’, 104 Journal of International Law and Diplomacy (2005) 98.

Stewart, ‘US Administrative Law: A Model for Global Administrative Law?’, 68 Law and Contemporary Problems (2005) 63; Esty, ‘Good Governance at the Supranational Scale: Globalizing Administrative Law’, 115 Yale Law Journal (2006) 1490; M. Savino, ‘EU ‘Procedural’ Supranationalism: On Models for Global Administrative Law’ (2006), available at www.law.nyu.edu/sites/default/files/upload_documents/gffsavinopaper.pdf (last visited 22 December 2016).

This call for intra-disciplinary comparison and inspiration has been criticized. Yet almost all elements of international law have been developed with an eye on domestic law. Private law, in particular contracts, is an obvious example. On intra-disciplinarity, see M. Jestaedt and O. Lepsius (eds), Rechtswissenschaftstheorie (2008).

This has remained unchanged in the recent symposium at the occasion of global administrative law’s 10th anniversary, see ‘Symposium: Through the Lens of Time: Global Administrative Law after 10 Years’, 13 IJCL (2015) 463.

Examples include the International Organization on Standardization or the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers.

Stewart and Ratton Sanchez Badin, ‘The World Trade Organization: Multiple Dimensions of Global Administrative Law’, 9 IJCL (2011) 556.

N. Krisch, ‘The Structure of Postnational Authority’, 13 February 2015, available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2564579 (last visited 22 December 2016); S. Cassese, ‘Global Administrative Law: The State of the Art’, 13 IJCL (2015) 465.

This, of course, implies that legal interpretation and construction are not only a mask of ‘political’ considerations.

Cassese, ‘Is There a Global Administrative Law?’, in A. von Bogdandy et al. (eds), The Exercise of Public Authority by International Institutions (2010) 761.

Enroth, ‘The Concept of Authority Transnationalised’, 4 Transnational Legal Theory (2013) 336.

See section 3.C below.

Cf. Goldmann, supra note 18, at 387ff.

Cf. L. Viellechner, Transnationalisierung des Rechts (2013), at 287ff.

Von Bogdandy, Dann and Goldmann, ‘Developing the Publicness of Public International Law: Towards a Legal Framework for Global Governance Activities’, 9 German Law Journal (2008) 1375, at 1393.

E.g., Kadi , supra note 88; Bundesverfassungsgericht, Bananas , Case 2 BvL 1/97, Judgment of 7 June 2000; ECtHR, Bosphorus v. Ireland , Appl. no. 45036/98, Judgment of 30 June 2005.

See section 2.B.2 above.

Some even contest the feasibility of the distinction, see section 2.A.3 above. In addition, Sand, ‘Globalization and the Transcendence of the Public/Private Divide: What Is Public Law under Conditions of Globalization?’, in C. Mac Amhlaigh et al. (eds), After Public Law? (2013) 201, at 204ff; L. Casini, ‘Down the Rabbit-Hole: The Projection of the Public/Private Distinction beyond the State’, 12 IJCL (2014) 402, at 419ff.

Fraser, supra note 56.

Teubner, supra note 37; Viellechner, supra note 105.

OECD Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises (2011), available at www.oecd.org/daf/inv/mne/48004323.pdf (last visited 22 December 2016). From the rich theoretical debate, see Watt, supra note 39, at 400–402.

Kischel, supra note 58, at 345ff.

This goes back to Hegel, supra note 15, at paras 182ff. For contemporary society, cf. T. Parsons, The Structure and Change of the Social System (1951); N. Luhmann, Soziale Systeme: Grundriss einer allgemeinen Theorie (1984); H. Arendt, The Human Condition (1958), at 22ff; recently, see A. Honneth, Das Recht der Freiheit: Grundriß einer demokratischen Sittlichkeit (2011), at 317ff.

Freedland, ‘The Evolving Approach to the Public/Private Distinction in English Law’, in J.-B. Auby and M. Freedland (eds), La distinction du droit public et du droit privé: regards français et britanniques (2004) 101, at 105–106; see also Loughlin, ‘The Nature of Public Law’, in C. Mac Amhlaigh et al. (eds), After Public Law? (2013) 11, at 14–15.

Most notably in the Administrative Procedure Act of 1946, 60 Stat. 237; see Stewart, ‘The Reformation of American Administrative Law’, 88 Harvard Law Review (1974–1975) 1667.

Alvarez, supra note 74.

On this, see section II.A.1 above.

Readers with a background in the common law should note that this function renders the public–private distinction highly important in many domestic legal orders.

Mac Amhlaigh, ‘Defending the Domain of Public Law’, in C. Mac Amlaigh et al. (eds), After Public Law (2012) 103ff (regarding para. 6 of the UK Human Rights Act, 1998, c. 42, which establishes responsibility for public entities only).

Exceptions include the administrative tribunals of international organizations. In detail, see Schermers and Blokker, supra note 62, at 462–467.

Rivero, ‘Existe-t-il un critère du droit administratif?’, 69 Revue du droit public et de la science politique en France et a l’étranger (1953) 279; Cassese, ‘“Le droit tout puissant et unique de la société”: Paradossi del diritto amministrativo’, 59 Rivista trimestrale di diritto pubblico (2009) 879; Kelsen, Pure Theory , supra note 55, at 281ff.

Cf. Avbelj, Fontanelli and Martinico, supra note 88; Kadi , supra note 88.

Although we use ‘common interests’ and ‘common good’ as synonyms, we are aware that they are linked to different traditions of political and legal thought. See A.O. Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests (1977).

E.g., J.-J. Rousseau, Du contrat social ou Principes du droit politique (1762), book 1, ch. VI and VII; Hegel, supra note 15, para. 258; Rawls, supra note 83, at 35ff, 201ff. Recently, see Best and Gheciu, ‘Theorizing the Public as Practices: Transformations of the Public in Historical Contexts’, in J. Best and A. Gheciu (eds), The Return of the Public in Global Governance (2014) 15, at 32.

Arendt, supra note 114, at 38.

Mutatis mutandis , this idea has been applied by the International Court of Justice, in the Certain Expenses of the United Nations (Article 7, paragraph 2, of the Charter ), Advisory Opinion, 20 July 1962, ICJ Reports (1962) 151. Only in cases of gravest shortcomings, the act is null and void. Cf. C-275/10, Residex Capital IV CV v. Gemeente Rotterdam , [2011] ECR I-13067.

Kingsbury and Donaldson, ‘From Bilateralism to Publicness in International Law’, in U. Fastenrath et al. (eds), From Bilateralism to Community Interest (2011) 79, at 84.

Waldron, ‘Public Rule of Law’, NYU School of Law, Public Law Research Paper No. 14–41 (2014), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2480648 (last visited 22 December 2016).

For a review of recent proposals, see Koskenniemi, ‘Projects of World Community’, in A. Cassese (ed.), Realizing Utopia: The Future of International Law (2012) 8. Further, see A.L. Paulus, Die international Gemeinschaft im Völkerrecht (2001), at 9ff; for a definition of publicness on the basis of discourse theory, see Goldmann, ‘A Matter of Perspective. Global Governance and the Distinction between Public and Private Authority (and Not Law)’, 5 Global Constitutionalism (2016) 48.

Note that their capacity to articulate a common interest is the reason why international organizations enjoy legal personality. See Ruffert and Walter, supra note 82.

Simma, ‘From Bilateralism to Community Interest in International Law’, 250 Recueil des cours (1994) 221; Paulus, supra note 131, at 225ff; see also the International Law Commission, Articles on the Responsibility of International Organizations, Doc. A/66/10 (2011), Arts 33(1), 42(b), 48(1)(b).

For a sceptical outlook, see Paulus, supra note 131, at 326–328.

See already von Bogdandy, Goldmann and Dann, supra note 106, at 1381–1382.

The four freedoms of Roosevelt, see F.D. Roosevelt, Four Freedom Speech, State of the Union Address, 6 January 1941; see also the UN Charter, Preamble.

Cf., however, our definition in von Bogdandy and Goldmann, ‘Sovereign Debt Restructurings as Exercises of Public Authority: Towards a Decentralized Sovereign Insolvency Law’, in C. Esposito, J.P. Bohoslavsky and Y. Li (eds), Responsible Sovereign Lending and Borrowing: The Search for Common Principles (2012) 39, at 47, which uses the term ‘liberty’. This should be considered a mistake. In von Bogdandy, Dann and Goldmann, supra note 106, at 1381, we use the term freedom.

Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, General Comment no. 12, 12 May 1999, para. 15; Eide, ‘Economic, Social and Cultural Rights as Human Rights’, in A. Eide, C. Krause and A. Rosas (eds), Economic, Social and Cultural Rights: A Textbook (2001) 9, at 23–24.

In international law, the two concepts are sometimes presented as synonymous, for example in the New Haven School, see Hathaway, ‘America, Defender of Democratic Legitimacy’, 11 EJIL (2000) 121. M. Reisman, The View from the New Haven School of International Law (1992).

J. Raz, The Authority of Law (1979), at 5ff; J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (1988), at 22ff, 53ff, 69.

See examples in note 5 (sanctions against Iraq) and note 6 (UN sanctions list) above. SC Res. 678 (1990). Some might doubt that these acts can still be considered as the public authority of an international institution. We assume that this is the case so long as the institution is not just a mask for one hegemonic state.

Comprehensively on mechanisms for extrinsic motivation. Goldmann, supra note 18, at 337–358.

WTO, United States – Subsidies on Upland Cotton – Report of the Appellate Body , 21 March 2005, WT/DS267/AB/R, at 3.

Occidental Petroleum Corporation and Occidental Exploration and Production Company v. Republic of Ecuador , ICSID Case no. ARB/06/11, Award, 5 October 2012.

On International Monetary Fund (IMF) conditionality, see IMF Guidelines on Conditionality, 25 September 2002, available at www.imf.org/External/np/pdr/cond/2002/eng/guid/092302.htm (last visited 22 December 2016).

Helfer and Slaughter, ‘Toward a Theory of Effective Supranational Adjudication’, 107 Yale Law Journal (1997–1998) 273, at 278; Shany, ‘Assessing the Effectiveness of International Courts: A Goal-Based Approach’, 106 AJIL (2012) 225.

On the Russian praxis of implementing ECtHR decisions, see A. Nußberger, ‘The Reception Process in Russia and Ukraine’, in H. Keller and A. Stone Sweet (eds), A Europe of Rights: The Impact of the ECHR on National Legal Systems (2008) 603.

A.T. Guzmán, How International Law Works: A Rational Choice Theory (2008); D. Shelton, Commitment and Compliance: The Role of Non-Binding Norms in the International Legal System (2000); Ho, ‘Compliance and International Soft Law: Why Do Countries Implement the Basle Accord?’, 5 Journal of International Economic Law (2002) 647, at 647. Against, see Burgstaller, ‘Amenities and Pitfalls of a Reputational Theory of Compliance with International Law’, 76 Nordic Journal of International Law (2007) 39.

Presuming that all legal acts, hard and soft, are authoritative. Pauwelyn, Wessels and Wouters, ‘Informal International Law as Presumptive Law: Exploring New Modes of Law-Making’, in R. Liivoja and J. Petman (eds), International Law-Making (2014) 75 at 89.

Heilmann and Schulte-Kulkmann, ‘Politikdiffusion im Schatten des Parteistaats: Die Integration Chinas in das internationale Regime zur Geldwäschebekämpfung’, 51 Politische Vierteljahresschrift (2010) 251, at 261ff.

Venzke, ‘Semantic Authority, Legal Change, and the Dynamics of International Law’, 12 No Foundations (2015) 1.

Statute of the International Court of Justice 1945, 1 UNTS 993, Art. 59.

WTO, European Communities – Measures Prohibiting the Importation and Marketing of Seal Products – Reports of the Appellate Body , 22 May 2014, WT/DS400/AB/R.

Schill, ‘System Building in Investment Treaty Arbitration and Lawmaking’, in A. von Bogdandy and I. Venzke (eds), International Judicial Lawmaking (2012) 133; see also A. von Bogdandy and I. Venzke, In Whose Name? A Public Law Theory of International Adjudication (2014).

I. Venzke, How Interpretation Makes International Law: On Semantic Change and Normative Twists (2012), at 62–64.

For a well-developed argument in this vein, see H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (1994), at 254–259. See further I. Venzke, ‘Between Power and Persuasion: International Institutions’ Authority in Making Law’, 4 Transnational Legal Theory (2013) 354; d’Aspremont, supra note 43, at 192–194; Friedmann, supra note 67, at 71.

E. Goffman, Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience (1974).

Regarding the psychological foundations, see Ryan and Deci, ‘Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivations: Classic Definitions and New Directions’, 25 Contemporary Educational Psychology (2000) 54.

M. Foucault, Surveiller et punir. Naissance de la prison (1975), at 36.

M. Foucault, L’hermeneutique du sujet: Cours au Collège de France, 1981–1982 (2001), at 241–242; M. Foucault, Securité, territoire, population (1977–1978); M. Foucault, Histoire de la sexualité (1976).

E.g., Noaksson and Jacobsson, ‘The Production of Ideas and Expert Knowledge in OECD: The OECD Jobs Strategy in Contrast with the EU Employment Strategy’, 7 Score Rapportserie (2003) 32; Martens and Balzer, ‘Comparing Governance of International Organisations: The EU, the OECD and Educational Policy’, Transtate Working Paper No. 7 (2004).

Jakobi and Martens, ‘Diffusion durch internationale Organisationen: Die Bildungspolitik der OECD’, in K. Holzinger, H. Jörgens and C. Knill (eds), Transfer, Diffusion und Konvergenz von Politiken (2007) 247.

For a seminal overview, see Tversky and Kahneman, ‘The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice’, 211 Science (1981) 453; see also Chong and Druckman, ‘Framing Theory’, 10 Annual Review of Political Science (2007) 103.

Program for International Student Assessment, available at www.oecd.org/pisa/ (last visited 22 December 2016).

Schäfer, ‘Resolving Deadlock: Why International Organisations Introduce Soft Law’, 12 European Law Journal (2006) 194.

Davis and Kruse, ‘Taking the Measure of Law: The Case of the Doing Business Project’, 32 Law and Social Inquiry (2007) 1095.

Davis, Kingsbury and Merry, ‘Indicators as a Technology of Global Governance’, Institute for International Law and Justice Working Paper No. 2 (2010), at 22ff.

See A. Rosga and M.L. Satterthwaite ‘The Trust in Indicators: Measuring Human Rights’, 27 Berkeley Journal of International Law (2009) 253.

For such an approach, see Martens and Niemann, ‘Governance by Comparison: How Ratings and Rankings Can Impact National Policy Making in Education’, TranState Working Paper No. 139 (2010).

On the concept of standard instruments, see Goldmann, supra note 18, at 399ff.

Von Bogdandy and Goldmann, supra note 8.

Mead, ‘The Return of Geopolitics: The Revenge of the Revisionist Powers’, 93 Foreign Affairs (2015) 69.

Author notes

Email alerts, citing articles via.

  • Recommend to your Library

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1464-3596
  • Print ISSN 0938-5428
  • Copyright © 2024 EJIL
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

  • Personal Profile
  • See all online law products
  • Subscriber Services
  • Guided Tour

Oxford Public International Law

  • Case reports
  • International court decisions
  • Domestic court decisions
  • European court cases
  • Arbitral cases
  • Commentary and analysis
  • Book content
  • Encyclopedia entries
  • International instruments and materials
  • Supporting instruments
  • Institutional rules
  • Resolutions
  • Declarations
  • Air law and law of outer space
  • Diplomacy and consular relations
  • European Union
  • History of international law
  • Human rights
  • Individuals and non-state actors
  • International co-operation
  • International criminal law
  • International economic law
  • International environmental law
  • International humanitarian law
  • International law and international relations
  • International organizations
  • International procedural law
  • International responsibility
  • Law of the sea
  • Law of treaties
  • Relationship between international and domestic law
  • Settlement of disputes
  • Sources, foundations and principles of international law
  • Statehood, jurisdiction of states, organs of states
  • Theory of international law
  • Use of force, war, peace and neutrality
  • Geographic Regions
  • Organizations/Institutions
  • American Organizations/Institutions
  • African Organizations/Institutions
  • Asian Organizations/Institutions
  • European Organizations/Institutions
  • International Organizations/Institutions
  • Middle Eastern Organizations/Institutions
  • Pacific Rim Organizations/Institutions

Recently viewed (0)

  • Save Search
  • Share This Facebook LinkedIn Twitter
  • Collapse All
  • Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU)
  • Eritrea–Ethiopia Claims Commission
  • European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR)
  • Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (ECCC)
  • Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR)
  • International Centre for the Settlement of Investment Disputes (ICSID)
  • International Court of Justice (ICJ)
  • International Criminal Court (ICC)
  • International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR)
  • International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY)
  • International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg
  • International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea (ITLOS)
  • Permanent Court of International Justice (PCIJ)
  • Special Court for Sierra Leone (SCSL)
  • United Nations Commission on International Trade Law (UNCITRAL)
  • United Nations Committee against Torture
  • United Nations Human Rights Committee
  • WTO and GATT Disputes
  • Other International Arbitral Awards
  • Netherlands
  • Philippines
  • Switzerland
  • United Kingdom
  • United States
  • Table of International Instruments
  • List of Abbreviations
  • List of Contributors
  • I Introduction
  • II The Centrality of the Sources of International Law in Theory and Practice
  • III The Enlightenment, Modernity, and the Origins of the Sources of International Law
  • IV The Disagreements about Sources in International Legal Theory and Practice
  • Part I The Histories of the Sources of International Law
  • Part II The Theories of the Sources of International Law
  • Part III The Functions of the Sources of International Law
  • Part IV The Regimes of the Sources of International Law
  • Research Questions
  • Selected Bibliography
  • II Reconstruction from Authorities
  • III Reconstruction From Natural Reason and Natural Law
  • IV Reconstruction from Human Practice and Human History
  • V Conclusion
  • II Roman Law
  • III Canon Law
  • IV Customary Law and Treaties
  • V The History of the Antiquity and Modern History
  • VI Natural Law Versus Positive Law
  • VII The Use of Personal Experience as a Practitioner
  • VIII Conclusion
  • II The Historic, Informative Sources of the Classical Law of Nations: From Jus Commune to Jus Naturae et Gentium (1500–1650)
  • III The Formative Sources of the Classical Law of Nations (1650–1775)
  • IV Concluding Remarks
  • 1 No Consent on Dissent
  • 2 Rare Definitions of ‘Source’
  • 1 No Source of Sources
  • a A Pre-Modern Tradition Continued: Nineteenth-Century ‘Law of Nature and of Nations’
  • b Vorsprung Durch Technik: Modernization through Historical Sources
  • a Monographs on Sources
  • b Defining International Law through its Sources
  • c Explicit Chapters on Sources
  • d Implicit References in International Law Histories
  • e Discussing Sources when Contending Rules
  • f A Dualistic Structure: The ‘Practical’ and the ‘Philosophical’ Law of Nations
  • IV The ‘European Law of Nations’: A New Disciplinary Self-Understanding as a Result of a Paradigm Shift in Sources
  • 1 If not Morality: The Minority Report
  • a The Never-Ending End of Natural Law
  • b Some Classical Candidates for ‘Positivism’
  • 3 Secularization: Divine Law as a Source?
  • 4 Positivism as the End of Natural Law Textbooks?
  • a Nineteenth-Century International Law Sources Theory: Natural Law is Still Alive and Kicking
  • b References to Natural Law in Various Regulatory Fields
  • c Entanglements between Natural and Positive Law
  • 6 A Century of Principles
  • VI Positivism as Legalization of International Law
  • VII Pluralism without a Hierarchy: The (Non-)Missing Systematization of Sources
  • VIII Conclusion: Reluctance to Glance in the Mirror
  • II European International Law in the Nineteenth Century: General Features
  • III The 1920 PCIJ Statute: The Triumph of Legal Positivism Over Ideas of Natural Law
  • IV Conclusion
  • II Compulsory Jurisdiction
  • 1 The Way to General Principles of Law
  • 2 Non Liquet
  • 3 The International Judge
  • 1 The Lotus Case
  • 2 The North Sea Continental Shelf Cases
  • 3 Concluding Reflection
  • 1 The Origins of Article 38
  • 2 The Background: The Advisory Committee of Jurists and the Drafting of Article 38
  • 1 Customary International Law
  • 2 General Principles of Law
  • 1 Acts of International Organizations
  • 2 Unilateral Acts of States
  • V Concluding Remarks and Nostalgia
  • II The New Haven School
  • III Schmitt
  • IV Conclusions
  • II Anti-Formalism in Mónica García-Salmones Rovira’s Chapter
  • III The TWAIL Critique
  • IV Some Additional Puzzles
  • V Empire-Centred and Charter-Centric Approaches
  • VI Beyond Imperial Legal Cosmopolitization
  • VII Towards a Conclusion?
  • II Meta-History and the Phenomenological Method
  • 1 The Apolitical–Amoral Epoché
  • 2 The Contractual–Liberal Epoché
  • IV Phenomenological Residuum and the Reversal of Hegel: The Essence of, and Need for, an Aristotelian Ethical Order
  • II Meta-Theory and Paradigms
  • III Questions About the Sources of International Law
  • IV Early Paradigms of the Sources of International Law
  • V The Article 38 Paradigm
  • II Earlier Conceptions of the Role of History as a Source of Law and of International Law
  • III Later Conceptions on the Role of History as a Source of International Law
  • 1 Customary international law
  • 2 Historic Interpretation
  • 3 Historic titles
  • V History as a Source of Legal Culture
  • II History of International Law as Contemporary Politics
  • III Historians versus Lawyers: A Brief Contrast
  • IV The Setting: The Alien Tort Statute in US Courts
  • V Analysing the Historical Debate
  • VI Conclusion: How the Past Matters in International Law
  • II Why Positivism?
  • III Customary International Law Creation: Orthodox and Informal Legislation Accounts
  • IV The Normative Practice Account of Custom and Custom Formation
  • V Positivism and the Normative Practice Account of Custom and Custom Formation
  • 1 The Problem of the ‘Source’ Metaphor
  • 2 The Stufenbau and the Structure of Legal Orders
  • i Externality
  • ii Coordination
  • iii Derogability
  • b Critique and Construction
  • 1 Options for Structuring the Sources of International Law
  • 2 The Problem of Multiple Original Sources of Law
  • II Variants of Formalism in International Legal Thought and Practice
  • 1 Sources and Content-Determination Formalism
  • 2 Sources and Law-Ascertainment Formalism
  • II Legal Formalism Explained
  • III The Formalism of Sources
  • IV And so to International Law
  • V Formalism and the Nature of Law
  • 1 Taking Meaning and Giving It
  • 2 Interpretations as Specific Kinds of Arguments
  • 1 The Common, Ordinary Meaning
  • 2 The Context
  • a Policy-Oriented Jurisprudence
  • b Integrity and Fit
  • 4 Authors and their Intentions
  • 1 Struggle, Hegemony, and Rhetoric
  • 2 Interpreter’s Biases
  • 3 Interpretative Communities
  • 4 Meaningful Limitations
  • II Existential Interpretations of International Law’s Sources
  • a Constructing International Legal Interpretation from the Sources of International Law
  • b Constructing Sources Doctrine from International Legal Interpretation
  • 2 The Impact of Sources Theory on Interpretation and Interpretative Theory on Sources
  • 3 The Interdependence of Authorities
  • IV Conclusions: Caveats and Consequences in Engaging Interdependence
  • 1 The Disputed Autonomy of International Law
  • 2 Towards a Modern Hermeneutics of International Law
  • 3 The Role of Principles of International Law
  • 1 Sources of Law and Enforcement
  • 2 The Rise of Global Governance
  • 3 Towards a Concept of Authority
  • 1 Public International Law, State Consent, and Functionalism
  • 2 The Demise of State Consent and Functionalism
  • 3 Towards International Public Law
  • Preliminary Material
  • II Turn to Interpretation
  • III The Hermeneutical Enterprise
  • IV Prejudice, Conversation, and Phronesis
  • V Situationality
  • VII Conversations
  • VIII Perspectives
  • II ‘Of Cabbages—and Kings’: MacCormick’s Account of Institutional Facts
  • III The Question of Sovereignty
  • IV The Pervasiveness of Conceptual Uncertainty
  • V Brierly, Fitzmaurice, and Lauterpacht—The Twentieth-Century British Turn to Natural Law in Search of Systemic Completeness
  • VI The New Haven School—Natural Law in Pursuit of Democracy, US Style?
  • VII In the End, Some Conclusions
  • 1 Law as the Last Dogmatic: A Distinctive Ontology Rather than a Science
  • 2 Law as the Exemplary Semiotics
  • 3 Law as Authority: A Hybrid of Auctoritas and Potestas
  • 1 The Explicit Disqualification of Doctrine: The Example of Article 38 of the ICJ Statute
  • 2 The Pragmatic Reinvigoration of Doctrine: Jurisdictio and Doctus Law (Droit Savant)
  • 3 The Need for a ‘Doctrine Savante’ in a Heterogeneous International Society
  • IV Doctrine at the Foundation of the Law of Nations
  • a Scientific Doctrines
  • b Symbolic Doctrines
  • a A Mediating Doctrine
  • b A ‘Doctrine Savante’
  • II The Structure of International Law and the Crucial Nature of the Issue of Sources
  • III Article 38 of the ICJ Statute
  • IV The Multiple Legal Character of Sources
  • II Discerning Three Elements in Ancient Thought
  • III Developing the Three Elements in the Middle Ages
  • IV Internationalizing and Renegotiating the Three Elements in Modernity
  • V The Re-Emergence of the Three Elements in Contemporary International Law
  • VI Conclusion
  • II The Idea of a Legal System
  • III Legal Systems and Sources of Law
  • IV An International Legal System?
  • V An Alternative to the Concept of Legal System
  • VI Consequences for Legitimacy?
  • VII Conclusion
  • 1 The Enduring Notion of Systematicity: A Nineteenth-Century Construction
  • 2 The Enduring Appeal of System-Denken in International Law Thought
  • 1 The Co-Constitutive Relationship between Sources and Systematicity
  • 2 The Socially Constructed Status of Article 38
  • 3 The Necessary Social Practice of Legal Officials
  • 4 The Recognition of Customary International Law by Systemic Officials
  • II The Relationship between Peremptory Norms and the Sources of International Law
  • III The Relationship between Article 103 of the UN Charter and the Sources of International Law
  • II The Non-Hierarchy Thesis
  • III The Treaty Primacy Thesis
  • IV The Custom Primacy Thesis
  • a Hierarchy of Norms
  • b Autonomy of Law
  • c Autonomy of the Legal System in Society
  • d Legal Systems and Morality
  • 1 National Law
  • a Variety of International Law
  • b A Unitary Perspective
  • c Modifications
  • 1 General Principles
  • 3 Practical Reasoning
  • II What is Normativity?
  • III The Normativity of Law
  • IV Full Normativity: Law’s Deep Justification
  • 1 International Law’s Legitimate Authority and Substantive Justification
  • 2 International Law’s Validity: Sources to the Rescue?
  • 1 Treaties: Normativity by Agreement
  • 2 Custom: Normativity through Normative (Aspirational or Reciprocal) Practice
  • II Legitimate Authority and the Law
  • III Consent and the Sources of International Law
  • 1 The Coherence of Sources Doctrine? The Example of Customary International Law
  • 2 The Exhaustiveness of Sources Doctrine? The Deformalization of International Law-Making
  • 3 A Way Forward?
  • II The Concept of Sources of Law
  • III The Sources of International Law
  • IV The Concept of Legitimacy
  • V Requirements of Democratic Legitimacy
  • VI The Democratic Legitimacy of the Sources of International Law
  • II Stories and Ideas
  • III The ‘Subject’ of Sources
  • IV States as Sources
  • V Non-State Actors as Participants
  • VI Pluralism of Sources
  • VII Diversity of Sources
  • VIII A Different International Legal Story
  • 1 The Legal Instruments: Continuity and Change
  • 2 The Court’s ‘Own Source’: General Principles of EU Law
  • 3 The Rejection of Treaty Change through Subsequent Practice
  • 4 The Autonomy of the Legal Order from the ‘Rest’ of International Law
  • 1 International Treaties as the Unchallenged Foundation of the EU Legal Order
  • 2 International Agreements as a Complementary Tool for Interstate Cooperation in the EU Context
  • 3 Treaties and Decisions as Instruments of EU External Relations
  • 1 International Political Bodies Authorized to Enforce International Law Norms
  • 2 IGOs and NGOs Possessing Soft Enforcement Powers
  • 3 International Courts Invested with Power to Order Enforcement Measures
  • 4 States Enforcing International Obligations against Other States
  • 5 Enforcement by Domestic State Organs
  • 1 Judgment Enforcement Procedures
  • 2 Resolutions of International Organizations
  • 1 Preference for Enforcement of Specific Norms
  • 2 Preference for Enforcement of Specialized Regime Norms
  • 3 The Limited Significance of Formal Classifications
  • 4 An Overall Eclectic Picture of International Law Enforcement
  • II Concepts of Enforcement
  • III Sources and Enforcement
  • IV The Sources of International Law and Domestic Courts
  • V Development or Enforcement?
  • 1 International Human Rights as Moral and Legal Rights
  • i The validity and severability of reservations to human rights treaties
  • ii The continuity of human rights treaties
  • iii The erga omnes effects of human rights treaties
  • b The Importance of General Principles of Human Rights Law
  • 1 Human Rights as Dual Domestic and International Legal Rights
  • a Common Intrastate Practice as Customary Human Rights Law
  • b Complementary Human Rights Adjudication
  • 1 Human Rights as Universal Rights
  • a General Customary Human Rights Law
  • b The Integrated Universal Bill of Rights
  • Selected bibliography
  • II Collective Interests Leading to Interstate Treaty Rights and Obligations
  • III The Status of Individuals in Human Rights Treaties
  • IV Law-of-Treaties Consequences Deriving from the Characteristics of Human Rights Treaties Thus Described
  • V Contrasted: Samantha Besson’s Views on Human Rights Treaties
  • 1 Formation of Customary Law and General Principles of International Law
  • 2 Regulation of Treaties
  • 1 The Rome Statute
  • 2 Commitments by Armed Groups
  • 1 Of Sources and Law-Making
  • 2 The Norms at Issue
  • a Security Council Resolutions
  • b Reports of UN Expert Bodies
  • c Reports of Expert Bodies not Commissioned by the UN
  • 2 The Inescapable Thicket of Customary Law’s Elements
  • 3 The Peculiar Law-Making Function of Courts
  • 4 The Singular Place of Nullum Crimen Sine Lege
  • 5 Confronting the Practice and Views of Non-State Actors
  • 1 Special Regimes and the Fear of Fragmentation
  • 2 The Purposes of the Concept of Sources
  • 3 The Scholarly Project of Identifying Sources
  • V IHL and ICL as a Window onto Moral Sources
  • a Stability and Flexibility in IEL Treaty Regimes: The Example of UNCLOS
  • 2 Customary International Law
  • 3 General Principles of Law
  • 4 Judicial Decisions
  • III Soft Law in International Environmental Law-Making
  • IV Conclusion: Sources of International Law from an Environmental Perspective
  • II Interactional International Law and the Sources Question
  • 2 Customary Law
  • 3 General Principles
  • 4 Judicial Decisions and Scholarship
  • 5 Other ‘Sources’ of International Law
  • II The Move to Accountability
  • III The Who–Egypt Advisory Opinion
  • IV Overcoming the Sources Question
  • V To Conclude
  • II The Independent Personality of International Organizations
  • III The Accountability of International Organizations as Independent Actors
  • IV Back to Sources or the Law Binding on International Organizations
  • 1 The WTO is Treaty-Based
  • 2 The WTO is Member-Driven
  • 1 Questioning the Source-Monopoly of WTO Members
  • 2 Questioning the Source-Monopoly of WTO Covered Agreements
  • 3 Questioning the Source-Monopoly of Legally Binding Instruments
  • 1 Two-Tiered Compulsory Dispute Settlement
  • 2 Consensus Decision-Making
  • 3 Membership Diversity
  • 1 ‘Ordinary Meaning’
  • 2 The Unity of the Article 31 Materials
  • 3 The Role of the Article 31 Materials
  • a Paragraphs 31 (1) and 31 (2)
  • b Paragraph 31 (3) (a)
  • c Paragraph 31 (3) (b)
  • i What other law comes within 31 (3) (c)?
  • ii Why is any other law an ‘authentic’ source?
  • III Article 32 and ‘Supplementary Means of Interpretation’
  • II The Sources of International Investment Law: A Primer
  • 1 Overview of the Problem
  • 2 The Nature of Domestic Law: From Fact to Law
  • 3 Domestic Law and the Sources of International Investment Law
  • 2 Cherry-Picking Norms: Of Treatment, Compensation, and their Bonds
  • 3 Explaining the ‘Distance’ between the Law and Arbitral Decisions
  • 2 A Case Study on the Interaction between Formal Sources: The Police Powers Doctrine
  • 3 Unspelt Interactions and the Theory of Sources
  • VI Concluding Observations: The Normative Pull of the Theory of Sources
  • II Definition of IIL and Analytical Approach
  • III Multilateralization through Bilateral Treaties
  • IV The Role of Arbitral Precedent
  • V The Use of Comparative Law
  • VI The Role of Soft Law
  • 1 Reservations
  • 2 Treaty Implementation and Domestic Separation of Powers
  • IV General Principles
  • 1 International Organizations
  • 2 Transnational Regulatory Networks
  • VI Conclusion: Domestic Constitutional Structure and the Doctrine of Sources
  • II The Relevance of Municipal Law for the Sources of International Law
  • III The Jurisgenerative Effect of Domestic Court Decisions
  • IV Transnational Judicial Dialogue and Comparative International Law as Mechanisms of International Law Development
  • V Domestic Law Particularities as a Complicating Factor
  • VI The Danger of Cherry-Picking
  • VII Towards a More Objective Comparative International Law Process
  • VIII Concluding Observations

Lorem ipsum dolor sit amet, consectetuer adipiscing elit, sed diam nonummy nibh euismod tincidunt ut laoreet dolore magna aliquam erat volutpat.

Go to full text on:

  • United Nations

Treaty Establishing the European Community (as amended by other Treaties) (European Union) [2006] OJ 321 E/37 (Date signed: 25th March 1957)

  • External Link

The Sources of International Law: An Introduction

Samantha besson, jean d'aspremont, from: the oxford handbook of the sources of international law, edited by: jean d'aspremont, samantha besson.

This introductory chapter offers a brief overview on the sources of international law. It first highlights the importance of and the controversies surrounding the sources of international law, touching upon the nature, legality, normativity, and legitimacy of international law, as well as the sites and tools of its contestation. The chapter then turns to the historical origins of the sources of international law, asserting that the sources of international law are in fact a product of the Enlightenment project and, arguably, of the liberal doctrine of politics. Finally, the chapter takes a look at how the dominant adherence to the sources of international law has been accompanied by constant contestation among international lawyers about their origins, criteria, functions, unity, and hierarchy. The chapter concludes with a brief summary of the following chapters.

  • [66.249.64.20|185.66.14.133]
  • 185.66.14.133
  • Careers & Service
  • Using the Library
  • Special Collections
  • Legal Data Lab
  • Search the Catalog

     ALERT: The shelter in place order has been lifted, but all UVA Library locations will remain closed today, November 14.

International Law Guide

  • International Courts and Tribunals
  • International Organizations
  • Private International Law
  • Selected Topics in Public International Law

See also...

Foreign Law Guide

General Guides and Resources for Public International Law

  • GlobaLex Research guides to international law (by subject) and foreign law (by jurisdiction) from NYU's Hauser Global Law School Program.

UVA users only

  • ASIL Research Guide to Public International Law An up-to-date guide to treaty and other public international law research with an emphasis on online resources. From the American Society of International Law.

Criminal Law

  • ASIL Research Guide to International Criminal Law
  • Research Guides to the International Criminal Courts for the Former Yugoslavia, Rwanda and Sierra Leone From GlobaLex.
  • Comparative Criminal Procedure: A Selected Bibliography From GlobaLex.
  • International Criminal Court Legal Tools Provides access to documents important to international criminal law, including treaties, judgments and decisions, summaries of domestic criminal justice systems in many countries including relevant statutes or codes, and commentary on international criminal law and other aspects of international law.

Environmental Law

  • ECOLEX: A Gateway to Environmental Law
  • United Nations Environment Programme
  • ASIL Research Guide to International Environmental Law
  • A Basic Guide to International Environmental Legal Research From GlobaLex.

Human Rights and Humanitarian Law

  • UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR)
  • OHCHR Jurisprudence Database Contains recommendations and findings from the various UN human rights committees that consider complaints from individuals.
  • Refworld UNHCR's comprehensive information source on refugee status includes treaties, legislation and court decisions, as well as information organized by country and topic.
  • European Court of Human Rights Pending cases, judgments, basic texts and a complete index to all ECHR judgments.
  • Bayefsky.com: The United Nations Human Rights Treaties
  • ICRC's Customary International Humanitarian Law Database A free online version of their two-volume publication.
  • University of Minnesota Human Rights Library
  • Human Rights Library: Collections on the Inter-American Court of Human Rights and Inter-American Commission on Human Rights From the University of Minnesota.
  • ESCR-Net Caselaw Database Database of domestic, international, and quasi-judicial cases and decisions on economic, social and cultural rights.
  • U.S. Department of State - Bureau of Democracy, Human Rights, and Labor
  • Project Diana: An Online Human Rights Case Archive From Yale Law School.
  • ASIL Research Guide to International Human Rights
  • ASIL Research Guide to International Humanitarian Law
  • International Human Rights Research Guide From GlobaLex.
  • ICJ E-bulletin on Counter-Terrorism and Human Rights International Commission of Jurist's free monthly publication of legal developments in the fields of counter-terrorism and human rights.

Intellectual Property

  • WIPO: World Intellectual Property Organization
  • WIPO Lex Collection of intellectual property legislation (in English) from WIPO member countries.
  • AIPPI - International Association for the Protection of Intellectual Property An international NGO devoted to the "the development and improvement of intellectual property." The Questions/Committees section contains country-by-country reports on specific intellectual property law topics.
  • European Patent Office
  • U.S. Patent & Trademark Office General information, forms, and a free searchable patent and trademark database.
  • U.S. Copyright Office Copyright basics, law, forms, and other materials available through the Library of Congress, the entity responsible for copyrights.
  • ASIL Research Guide to International Intellectual Property Law
  • IP Precedents Database Database of English translations of precedential domestic court decisions on IP topics; from the Research Center for the Legal System of Intellectual Property.

Law of the Sea

  • United Nations: Oceans and Law of the Sea
  • International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea
  • International Seabed Authority
  • UVA Center for Oceans Law & Policy
  • ASIL Research Guide to Law of the Sea

Trade, Investment or Economic Law

  • GATT Documents Online From the WTO.
  • GATT Digital Library From Stanford University.
  • WorldTradeLaw.net
  • International Trade Database: Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods From Pace University.
  • Trans-Lex.org Research platform for transnational commercial law from the Center for Transnational Law, Cologne University, Germany.
  • SICE - Foreign Trade Information System From the Organization of American States.
  • United States International Trade Commission
  • United States Trade Representative
  • Harmonized Tariff Schedule

UVA Law School users only

  • ASIL Research Guide to International Economic Law
  • ASIL Research Guide to International Commercial Arbitration
  • Research Guide on the Harmonization of International Commercial Law From GlobaLex.

Women's Rights

  • Women's Human Rights Resources From the University of Toronto.
  • Women's Human Rights Documents From the University of Minnesota.
  • Women's Rights Links From the University of Minnesota.
  • Last Updated: Jul 12, 2023 10:02 AM
  • URL: https://libguides.law.virginia.edu/international
  • Privacy Statement   |  
  • University of Virginia   |  
  • Emergency Information

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Public International Law

Profile image of Hema Pandey

The paper is all about the Transit Right of Landlocked States, specially focused on Transit Right of Nepal under the UN Convention on Law of Sea, A brief study.

Related Papers

Anujin Onon

public international law research paper pdf

Vijay P A R S A D Jayshwal

Transit right for the landlocked countries are not only subject to the moral treatment but entitled to get recognition and enforcement. The transit right although developed in the form of principles but it is duly recognized by the international court of justice in number of cases. The subject to bilateral agreement must be eroded from the realization of this right. The most part of the UNCLOSIII are taken as part of the customary international law with fulfilling the objective and subjective requirement. So today, the need for separate bilateral agreement is merely the myth of coastal state. Key Words: Transit, Customary International law, Coastal State

Endalcachew Bayeh

The United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea 1982 provided rights for land-locked states on the sea. More importantly, the convention provided them with the right of access to and from the seas and freedom of transit. However, the law makes such rights subject to the agreements to be made by land-locked and transit states. This, in turn, depends on the prevailing relations between the concerned states. If they are not in a smooth relation, the transit states may not be willing to negotiate and thereby put impediments on the land-locked states’ free transit. The political will and commitment of transit states highly conditioned the rights of land-locked states. The denial of free transit, in turn, affects the rights of land-locked states on the different maritime regimes. Land-locked states have no absolute right of access to and from the seas and freedom of transit. Hence, the study concludes that to give practical effect to those rights, negotiating bilateral and multilateral agreements with the transit states has a crucial and irreplaceable role.

Paschal Obiora

For decades, most landlocked States have been faced with a deluge of hitches resulting from their inability to secure access to seaports. These problems have greatly hindered the economic development of these nations. To ease their sufferings, States without access to the seas have sought successive legal innovations to assert and enforce their right of access based on the international law principle of servitude. This study traces the evolution of international law innovations relating to free access to and from the seas for landlocked States. A comparative and evolutionary stroll from the Statute of Barcelona 1921 to the United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea 1982, found that indeed, landlocked States are vested with the rights of access to the seas using the transit routes of their neighboring transit States. Regrettably, these rights seem to be more theoretical than practical as they are subject to the political whims and caprices of transit States. The enjoyment of these rights by landlocked States is contingent upon a successful negotiation between the concerned landlocked State and its transit State. The study further analyses the cogency of negotiating bilateral and/or multilateral agreements dealing with the question of transit for landlocked States. The study concludes that reciprocal negotiations with transit States have a crucial and irreplaceable role to play in giving practical effect to those rights.

Malik Khushal Rahim

International Law regarding Territorial Soverignty, Airspace Law, Space Law, UN Law of the Sea and International Rivers/ Watercourses.

Buffalo Human Rights Law Review

Halil Rahman Basaran

The cornerstone of international law in providing stability in international relations is the sovereign equality of States, and both the Responsiblity to Protect and the Landlocked States clash with this bedrock of international law. The challenge put to international law by the existence and persistence of these two concepts questions the fine line that delineates international politics and international law. The result is the disclosure of the fragility that exists within the fabric of international law.

Nishith Sheth

Brill | Nijhoff

Pranjali Kanel

Asian Yearbook of International Law, Volume 26 (2020). This is an open-access chapter distributed under the terms of the CC BY-NC 4.0 license.

Sea is a large body of water that is surrounded by the land. It is a crucial part of human trade and commerce, voyage, mineral extraction, power generation and is also considered as an essential source of blue economy nowadays. International law of the sea is a law of maritime space that peacefully settles the global disputes on maritime boundary between or among the States and defines various jurisdictions of the maritime zones as well as the rights and obligations of the coastal States in these zones, especially with regard to the conservation of marine environment and biodiversity. The key objective of this piece of academic research is to demonstrate a brief overview of the international law of the sea with a special emphasize on the sources and legal framework of this law. This study also strives to focus the civil and criminal liability, jurisdictions, rights and obligations of the coastal states with regard to the different maritime zones. Furthermore this study delineates the rules and extent of using these maritime zones in the light of various treaty provisions on the international law of the sea where different adjudicated cases are also presented along with a profound scrutiny upon their fact, issues, judgment and reasoning.

Karolina Mickutė

The high seas are not only one of the major areas of the world's ocean, but also a source of many lucrative resources, which may be used by all states, whether coastal or landlocked , under the freedom of the high seas which is a general principle of international law. However, the principle is not unconditional as the activities of states at the high seas are subject to the regulations prescribed under the United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea (UNCLOS). Equality of states operating at the high seas leads to the exclusivity of the flag state jurisdiction and the principle of non-interdiction of its vessels. Nevertheless, UNCLOS foresees exceptions to the jurisdiction of flag states. The article analyses, inter alia, the preconditions of exercising flag state jurisdiction, the possibilities and peculiarities of non-state actor interference particularly regarding cases of piracy and pre-emptive self-defence.

RELATED PAPERS

Revue Française de Gestion

Julienne Brabet

International Journal of Advanced Computer Science and Applications

Jasmine Saini

International Aquatic Research

Nguyen Tuan Anh

Associate Professor Ts. Dr. Gasim Hayder

International Journal of Gynecology & Obstetrics

janet Yagoda SHagam

Environmental Engineering and Management Journal

Istvan Raduly

International Journal of Biochemistry Research & Review

kouakou koffi

Acta Universitaria

Annals of Forest Science

susana barreiro

Scientific Reports

indra taufiq

AIP Conference Proceedings

Pietro Colangelo

Cuadernos de Extensión Universitaria

Paula Abdala

Contexto Internacional

Miguel Retiguin herrera

Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery

Bandırma Onyedi Eylül Üniversitesi Sosyal Bilimler Araştırmaları dergisi

Sinan Kıyanç

Human Immunology

Rathimalar Ayakannu

Urologia internationalis

Andras Hoznek

rtytrewer htytrer

Irina Al-Khairi

arXiv (Cornell University)

Monnie McGee

Analytical Sciences

Ali mohammad-khah

Chemical Communications

Huanting Liu

Francisco De Arruda Machado

Zeitschrift Fur Klinische Psychologie Und Psychotherapie

Sabine Walper

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

IMAGES

  1. (PDF) PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW PRIVATE INTERNATIONAL LAW OR LEGAL CONFLICT

    public international law research paper pdf

  2. Public International Law Notes

    public international law research paper pdf

  3. International Law

    public international law research paper pdf

  4. (PDF) CODES AND NOTES ON PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW by PORFERIO JR. and

    public international law research paper pdf

  5. International law research paper

    public international law research paper pdf

  6. Public International Law Essay

    public international law research paper pdf

VIDEO

  1. Public International Law(303) LLB first year examination question paper #newcourse

  2. Chaos & Calm // Meme Animation

  3. PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW PART 2

  4. Public International Law #unsolvedpaper #llb #ddu

  5. public international law

  6. #public international law m.a final paper political science mgsu bikaner 2023

COMMENTS

  1. 3655 PDFs

    Explore the latest full-text research PDFs, articles, conference papers, preprints and more on PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW. Find methods information, sources, references or conduct a literature ...

  2. PDF Researching Public International Law

    The chapter format of the ERG is designed to be used by students, teachers, practitioners and researchers as a self-guided tour of relevant, quality, up-to-date online resources covering important areas of international law. The ERG also serves as a ready-made teaching tool at graduate and undergraduate levels.

  3. PDF Public International Law: Treaties and International Organizations

    2.3 Treaty Formation. We will now discuss how a treaty is formed and discuss some of the challenges that can arise in this process. Treaty formation involves four basic steps: 1) negotiation and drafting; 2) authentication and adoption; 3) expressing consent; and 4) entry into force.

  4. PDF An Introduction to Public International Law

    978-1-108-42145-4 — An Introduction to Public International Law Cecily Rose , Niels Blokker , Daniëlla Dam-de Jong , Simone van den Driest , Robert Heinsch , Erik Koppe , Nico Schrijver ... education, learning, and research at the highest international levels of excellence. www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org ...

  5. PDF The Sources of International Law

    Tarullo for their research assistance, readings, and comments. This article is one part of a larger study of public international legal doctrine being published in 1987 by No- ... Sources of International Law, in MANUAL OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 116 (M. Sorenson ed. 1968) (a classic treatise summary); Baxter, Treaties and Custom, 129

  6. Public International Law

    Language. Public International Law: A Multi-Perspective Approach is a comprehensive yet critical introduction to the diverse field of public international law. Bringing together a unique range of perspectives from around the world and from different theoretical approaches, this textbook introduces both the overarching questions and doctrines of ...

  7. [PDF] An Introduction to Public International Law

    Law, Political Science. Written for students working in a range of disciplines, this textbook provides an accessible, balanced, and nuanced introduction to the field of public international law. It explains the basic concepts and legal frameworks of public international law while acknowledging the field's inherent complexities and controversies.

  8. PDF Bonn Research Papers on Public International Law

    institute for public international law BONN RESEARCH PAPERS . ON PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW. Paper No 15 /2019, 7 October 2019. The United States under President Trump: Gravedigger of International Law . STEFAN TALMON. The full text of this paper can be downloaded without charge from the . Social Science Research Network electronic library at:

  9. PDF INTERNATIONAL LAW AND HISTORY

    eld of public international law. It publishes works on international law that are of a theoretical, historical, cross-disciplinary or doctrinal nature. The series also welcomes books providing insights from private international law, comparative law and trans-national studies which inform international legal thought and practice more generally.

  10. From Public International to International Public Law: Translating

    International institutional law focuses on international organizations as subjects of international law, describing both their externally relevant activities and their internal law with a view to carving out common principles embedded in the legal design and practices of all international institutions. 62 For international public law ...

  11. Oxford Public International Law: The Sources of International Law: An

    This introductory chapter offers a brief overview on the sources of international law. It first highlights the importance of and the controversies surrounding the sources of international law, touching upon the nature, legality, normativity, and legitimacy of international law, as well as the sites and tools of its contestation. The chapter then turns to the historical origins of the sources ...

  12. PDF Public International Law in Practice Legal Foundations/Sources of

    Group exercise 3. Prepare a list of matters which are not clear in the today's class. Discuss how the international system and the regional system are relevant to your professional activities; Discuss what could be done to increase the impact of the universal and regional systems on domestic law and practice; and.

  13. International Law Guide

    This is the complete archive of collected courses, Recueil des Cours, in international law dating from 1923 to the near-present. It also contains the official publications from workshops organized by the Academy. Its thorough annotations make it a valuable resource for research in international law.

  14. International Law and Interdisciplinarity by Sergio Dellavalle

    Open PDF in Browser. Add Paper to My Library ... Faculty of Law; Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International Law; Goethe University Frankfurt - Cluster of Excellence Normative Orders ... (May 1, 2020). Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law & International Law (MPIL) Research Paper No. 2020-14, Available at SSRN ...

  15. Full article: Public international law, international taxation and tax

    A. The public international law foundation of international taxation. International taxation is not a definite concept, but an aspect of PIL. International taxation can, however, be described as an area of knowledge pertaining to the international aspects of cross-border activities which can be regulated throughout domestic law or throughout (bilateral and regional-multilateral) tax treaties.

  16. The Legitimacy of International Law by Paul B. Stephan :: SSRN

    Stephan, Paul B., The Legitimacy of International Law (January 17, 2020). PALGRAVE HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL POLITICAL THEORY (Palgrave MacMillan: New York, Howard Williams, David Boucher, Peter Sutch & David A. Reidy, eds., forthcoming 2021), Virginia Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 2020-05, Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com ...

  17. (PDF) INTRODUCTION TO PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW

    By introducing the foundations of the legal reasoning underlying public international law, the extensive volume offers essential tools for any international lawyer, regardless of the specific field of specialization. Dealing expansively with subjects, sources and guarantees of international law, university students, scholars and practitioners ...

  18. International Journal of Public Law and Policy

    Objectives. IJPLAP's main objective is to be the leading forum for information and critical discussion from a variety of international perspectives in the constantly evolving area of law and government.The world is changing fast and governments are facing many public policy challenges, legal issues of public interest and public policy relating to the many political, economic and social issues ...

  19. (PDF) Public International Law

    Download Free PDF. View PDF. Transit Right of Landlocked States under International Law:"With Reference to Nepal's Transit Right via India based on Transit Treaty between Nepal and India" Term Paper in the subject of Public International Law L.L.B. 3rd Year 11 May 2011 Hema Pandey Kathmandu School of Law Purbanchal University fTable of Contents ...

  20. PDF Relationship between international and municipal law: A case study of India

    This research paper provides a comprehensive analysis of this relationship. Further this paper discusses the relationship between international law and municipal law with special reference to Indian practice. Indeed, the study ... Public International Law has been defined by J.G. Starke as

  21. Marxist Approaches to International Law: An Outline

    Abstract. Despite having a rather long and influential pedigree, Marxist approaches to law and international law in particular, largely remained in the margins of the discipline, even within critical circles. Yet, in the last decades, Marxist scholarship in international law has witnessed somewhat of a 'revival'.

  22. 18llb042 (Public International Law Research Paper)

    18llb042(Public International Law Research Paper) - Free download as Word Doc (.doc / .docx), PDF File (.pdf), Text File (.txt) or read online for free. this is my research paper on the public international law