The Law Dictionary

Your Free Online Legal Dictionary • Featuring Black’s Law Dictionary, 2nd Ed.

HYPOTHESIS Definition & Legal Meaning

Definition & citations:.

A supposition, assumption, or theory; a theory set up by the prosecution,on a criminal trial, or by the defense, as an explanation of the facts in evidence,and a ground for inferring guilt or innocence, as the case may be, or asindicating a probable or possible motive for the crime.

This article contains general legal information but does not constitute professional legal advice for your particular situation. The Law Dictionary is not a law firm, and this page does not create an attorney-client or legal adviser relationship. If you have specific questions, please consult a qualified attorney licensed in your jurisdiction.

Browse Legal Articles

Business Formation

Business Law

Child Custody & Support

Criminal Law

Employment & Labor Law

Estate Planning

Immigration

Intellectual Property

Landlord-Tenant

Motor Vehicle Accidents

Personal Injury

Real Estate & Property Law

Traffic Violations

Browse by Area of Law

Powered by Black’s Law Dictionary, Free 2nd ed., and The Law Dictionary .

About The Law Dictionary

Terms and Conditions

Privacy Policy

  • TheFreeDictionary
  • Word / Article
  • Starts with
  • Free toolbar & extensions
  • Word of the Day
  • Free content

An assumption or theory.

During a criminal trial, a hypothesis is a theory set forth by either the prosecution or the defense for the purpose of explaining the facts in evidence. It also serves to set up a ground for an inference of guilt or innocence, or a showing of the most probable motive for a criminal offense.

  • criminology
  • Dred Scott v. Sandford
  • fingerprint
  • Indirect Evidence
  • Kelsen, Hans
  • Kelsinian jurisprudence
  • natural law
  • Second Treatise on Government
  • Hunter, Elmo Bolton
  • hunting and felony charges
  • hunting with hounds
  • Huntley Hearing
  • Hurtado v. California
  • Husband and Wife
  • husband and wife on mortgage
  • Husband died, wife accused of identity theft
  • Husband in jail for possession
  • Husband taken to jail for outstanding ticket
  • Husband tested positive for drugs at work
  • hybrid bill
  • Hypothecate
  • hypothecation
  • Hypothetical Question
  • Ictus orbis
  • Id certum est quod certum reddi potest
  • Id perfectum est quod ex omnibus suis partibus constat
  • Id possumus quod de jure possumus
  • Id quod nostrum est
  • Idem agens et patiens esse non potest
  • Idem est facere
  • Idem est nihil dicere et insufficienter dicere
  • Idem est non probari et non esse; non deficit jus
  • Idem est scire aut scire debet aut potuisse
  • Idem non esse et non apparet
  • Idem semper antecedenti proximo refertur
  • Idem sonans
  • identification parade
  • Hypothermia After Cardiac Arrest
  • Hypothermia After Cardiac Arrest Registry
  • hypothermia blanket
  • hypothermia therapy
  • hypothermia treatment
  • Hypothermia, induced
  • hypothermic
  • hypothermic anesthesia
  • hypothermic circulatory arrest
  • Hypothermic machine perfusion
  • hypothermicly
  • Hypothèse Extraterrestre
  • Hypothesis Driven Lexical Adaptation
  • Hypothesis test
  • Hypothesis testing
  • hypothesis testing sampling
  • hypothesis to test
  • Hypothesis-Based Testing
  • Hypothesis-Oriented Algorithm for Clinicians
  • hypothesise
  • hypothesised
  • hypothesiser
  • hypothesisers
  • hypothesises
  • Facebook Share

The Law Dictionary

TheLaw.com Law Dictionary & Black's Law Dictionary 2nd Ed.

A supposition, assumption, or theory; a theory set up by the prosecution, on a criminal trial, or by the defense, as an explanation of the facts in evidence, and a ground for Inferring guilt or Innocence, as the case may be, or as indicating a probable or possible motive for the crime.

No related posts found

  • Legal Terms
  • Editorial Guidelines
  • © 1995 – 2016 TheLaw.com LLC

Hypothesis, Model, Theory, and Law

Dorling Kindersley / Getty Images

  • Physics Laws, Concepts, and Principles
  • Quantum Physics
  • Important Physicists
  • Thermodynamics
  • Cosmology & Astrophysics
  • Weather & Climate

hypothesis legal term

  • M.S., Mathematics Education, Indiana University
  • B.A., Physics, Wabash College

In common usage, the words hypothesis, model, theory, and law have different interpretations and are at times used without precision, but in science they have very exact meanings.

Perhaps the most difficult and intriguing step is the development of a specific, testable hypothesis. A useful hypothesis enables predictions by applying deductive reasoning, often in the form of mathematical analysis. It is a limited statement regarding the cause and effect in a specific situation, which can be tested by experimentation and observation or by statistical analysis of the probabilities from the data obtained. The outcome of the test hypothesis should be currently unknown, so that the results can provide useful data regarding the validity of the hypothesis.

Sometimes a hypothesis is developed that must wait for new knowledge or technology to be testable. The concept of atoms was proposed by the ancient Greeks , who had no means of testing it. Centuries later, when more knowledge became available, the hypothesis gained support and was eventually accepted by the scientific community, though it has had to be amended many times over the year. Atoms are not indivisible, as the Greeks supposed.

A model is used for situations when it is known that the hypothesis has a limitation on its validity. The Bohr model of the atom , for example, depicts electrons circling the atomic nucleus in a fashion similar to planets in the solar system. This model is useful in determining the energies of the quantum states of the electron in the simple hydrogen atom, but it is by no means represents the true nature of the atom. Scientists (and science students) often use such idealized models  to get an initial grasp on analyzing complex situations.

Theory and Law

A scientific theory or law represents a hypothesis (or group of related hypotheses) which has been confirmed through repeated testing, almost always conducted over a span of many years. Generally, a theory is an explanation for a set of related phenomena, like the theory of evolution or the big bang theory . 

The word "law" is often invoked in reference to a specific mathematical equation that relates the different elements within a theory. Pascal's Law refers an equation that describes differences in pressure based on height. In the overall theory of universal gravitation developed by Sir Isaac Newton , the key equation that describes the gravitational attraction between two objects is called the law of gravity .

These days, physicists rarely apply the word "law" to their ideas. In part, this is because so many of the previous "laws of nature" were found to be not so much laws as guidelines, that work well within certain parameters but not within others.

Scientific Paradigms

Once a scientific theory is established, it is very hard to get the scientific community to discard it. In physics, the concept of ether as a medium for light wave transmission ran into serious opposition in the late 1800s, but it was not disregarded until the early 1900s, when Albert Einstein proposed alternate explanations for the wave nature of light that did not rely upon a medium for transmission.

The science philosopher Thomas Kuhn developed the term scientific paradigm to explain the working set of theories under which science operates. He did extensive work on the scientific revolutions that take place when one paradigm is overturned in favor of a new set of theories. His work suggests that the very nature of science changes when these paradigms are significantly different. The nature of physics prior to relativity and quantum mechanics is fundamentally different from that after their discovery, just as biology prior to Darwin’s Theory of Evolution is fundamentally different from the biology that followed it. The very nature of the inquiry changes.

One consequence of the scientific method is to try to maintain consistency in the inquiry when these revolutions occur and to avoid attempts to overthrow existing paradigms on ideological grounds.

Occam’s Razor

One principle of note in regards to the scientific method is Occam’s Razor (alternately spelled Ockham's Razor), which is named after the 14th century English logician and Franciscan friar William of Ockham. Occam did not create the concept—the work of Thomas Aquinas and even Aristotle referred to some form of it. The name was first attributed to him (to our knowledge) in the 1800s, indicating that he must have espoused the philosophy enough that his name became associated with it.

The Razor is often stated in Latin as:

entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem
or, translated to English:
entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity

Occam's Razor indicates that the most simple explanation that fits the available data is the one which is preferable. Assuming that two hypotheses presented have equal predictive power, the one which makes the fewest assumptions and hypothetical entities takes precedence. This appeal to simplicity has been adopted by most of science, and is invoked in this popular quote by Albert Einstein:

Everything should be made as simple as possible, but not simpler.

It is significant to note that Occam's Razor does not prove that the simpler hypothesis is, indeed, the true explanation of how nature behaves. Scientific principles should be as simple as possible, but that's no proof that nature itself is simple.

However, it is generally the case that when a more complex system is at work there is some element of the evidence which doesn't fit the simpler hypothesis, so Occam's Razor is rarely wrong as it deals only with hypotheses of purely equal predictive power. The predictive power is more important than the simplicity.

Edited by Anne Marie Helmenstine, Ph.D.

  • Scientific Hypothesis, Model, Theory, and Law
  • Einstein's Theory of Relativity
  • What Is a Paradigm Shift?
  • Wave Particle Duality and How It Works
  • Scientific Method
  • Oversimplification and Exaggeration Fallacies
  • Kinetic Molecular Theory of Gases
  • Understanding Cosmology and Its Impact
  • The History of Gravity
  • The Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
  • Tips on Winning the Debate on Evolution
  • Geological Thinking: Method of Multiple Working Hypotheses
  • The Life and Work of Albert Einstein
  • Newton's Law of Gravity
  • De Broglie Hypothesis
  • What Is a Scientific or Natural Law?

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

The Legal Concept of Evidence

The legal concept of evidence is neither static nor universal. Medieval understandings of evidence in the age of trial by ordeal would be quite alien to modern sensibilities (Ho 2003–2004) and there is no approach to evidence and proof that is shared by all legal systems of the world today. Even within Western legal traditions, there are significant differences between Anglo-American law and Continental European law (see Damaška 1973, 1975, 1992, 1994, 1997). This entry focuses on the modern concept of evidence that operates in the legal tradition to which Anglo-American law belongs. [ 1 ] It concentrates on evidence in relation to the proof of factual claims in law. [ 2 ]

It may seem obvious that there must be a legal concept of evidence that is distinguishable from the ordinary concept of evidence. After all, there are in law many special rules on what can or cannot be introduced as evidence in court, on how evidence is to be presented and the uses to which it may be put, on the strength or sufficiency of evidence needed to establish proof and so forth. But the law remains silent on some crucial matters. In resolving the factual disputes before the court, the jury or, at a bench trial, the judge has to rely on extra-legal principles. There have been academic attempts at systematic analysis of the operation of these principles in legal fact-finding (Wigmore 1937; Anderson, Schum, and Twining 2009). These principles, so it is claimed, are of a general nature. On the basis that the logic in “drawing inferences from evidence to test hypotheses and justify conclusions” is governed by the same principles across different disciplines (Twining and Hampsher-Monk 2003: 4), ambitious projects have been undertaken to develop a cross-disciplinary framework for the analysis of evidence (Schum 1994) and to construct an interdisciplinary “integrated science of evidence” (Dawid, Twining, and Vasilaki 2011; cf. Tillers 2008).

While evidential reasoning in law and in other contexts may share certain characteristics, there nevertheless remain aspects of the approach to evidence and proof that are distinctive to law (Rescher and Joynt 1959). Section 1 (“conceptions of evidence”) identifies different meanings of evidence in legal discourse. When lawyers talk about evidence, what is it that they are referring to? What is it that they have in mind? Section 2 (“conditions for receiving evidence”) approaches the concept of legal evidence from the angle of what counts as evidence in law. What are the conditions that the law imposes and must be met for something to be received by the court as evidence? Section 3 (“strength of evidence”) shifts the attention to the stage where the evidence has already been received by the court. Here the focus is on how the court weighs the evidence in reaching the verdict. In this connection, three properties of evidence will be discussed: probative value, sufficiency, and degree of completeness.

1. Conceptions of Evidence: What does Evidence Refer to in Law?

2.1.1 legal significance of relevance, 2.1.2 conceptions of logical relevance, 2.1.3 logical relevance versus legal relevance, 2.2 materiality and facts-in-issue, 2.3.1 admissibility and relevance, 2.3.2 admissibility or exclusionary rules, 3.1 probative value of specific items of evidence, 3.2.1 mathematical probability and the standards of proof, 3.2.2 objections to using mathematical probability to interpret standards of proof, 3.3 the weight of evidence as the degree of evidential completeness, other internet resources, related entries.

Stephen (1872: 3–4, 6–7) long ago noted that legal usage of the term “evidence” is ambiguous. It sometimes refers to that which is adduced by a party at the trial as a means of establishing factual claims. (“Adducing evidence” is the legal term for presenting or producing evidence in court for the purpose of establishing proof.) This meaning of evidence is reflected in the definitional section of the Indian Evidence Act (Stephen 1872: 149). [ 3 ] When lawyers use the term “evidence” in this way, they have in mind what epistemologists would think of as “objects of sensory evidence” (Haack 2004: 48). Evidence, in this sense, is divided conventionally into three main categories: [ 4 ] oral evidence (the testimony given in court by witnesses), documentary evidence (documents produced for inspection by the court), and “real evidence”; the first two are self-explanatory and the third captures things other than documents such as a knife allegedly used in committing a crime.

The term “evidence” can, secondly, refer to a proposition of fact that is established by evidence in the first sense. [ 5 ] This is sometimes called an “evidential fact”. That the accused was at or about the scene of the crime at the relevant time is evidence in the second sense of his possible involvement in the crime. But the accused’s presence must be proved by producing evidence in the first sense. For instance, the prosecution may call a witness to appear before the court and get him to testify that he saw the accused in the vicinity of the crime at the relevant time. Success in proving the presence of the accused (the evidential fact) will depend on the fact-finder’s assessment of the veracity of the witness and the reliability of his testimony. (The fact-finder is the person or body responsible for ascertaining where the truth lies on disputed questions of fact and in whom the power to decide on the verdict vests. The fact-finder is also called “trier of fact” or “judge of fact”. Fact-finding is the task of the jury or, for certain types of cases and in countries without a jury system, the judge.) Sometimes the evidential fact is directly accessible to the fact-finder. If the alleged knife used in committing the crime in question (a form of “real evidence”) is produced in court, the fact-finder can see for himself the shape of the knife; he does not need to learn of it through the testimony of an intermediary.

A third conception of evidence is an elaboration or extension of the second. On this conception, evidence is relational. A factual proposition (in Latin, factum probans ) is evidence in the third sense only if it can serve as a premise for drawing an inference (directly or indirectly) to a matter that is material to the case ( factum probandum ) (see section 2.2 below for the concept of materiality). The fact that the accused’s fingerprints were found in a room where something was stolen is evidence in the present sense because one can infer from this that he was in the room, and his presence in the room is evidence of his possible involvement in the theft. On the other hand, the fact that the accused’s favorite color is blue would, in the absence of highly unusual circumstances, be rejected as evidence of his guilt: ordinarily, what a person’s favorite color happens to be cannot serve as a premise for any reasonable inference towards his commission of a crime and, as such, it is irrelevant (see discussion of relevance in section 2.1 below). In the third sense of “evidence”, which conceives of evidence as a premise for a material inference, “irrelevant evidence” is an oxymoron: it is simply not evidence. Hence, this statement of Bentham (1825: 230): [ 6 ]

To say that testimony is not pertinent, is to say that it is foreign to the case, has no connection with it, and does not serve to prove the fact in question; in a word, it is to say, that it is not evidence.

There can be evidence in the first sense without evidence in the second or third sense. To pursue our illustration, suppose it emerges during cross-examination of the expert that his testimony of having found a finger-print match was a lie. Lawyers would describe this situation as one where the “evidence” (the testimony of the expert) fails to prove the fact that it was originally produced to prove and not that no “evidence” was adduced on the matter. Here “evidence” is used in the first sense—evidence as testimony—and the testimony remains in the court’s record whether it is believed or not. But lawyers would also say that, in the circumstances, there is no “evidence” that the accused was in the room, assuming that there was nothing apart from the discredited expert testimony of a fingerprint match to establish his presence there. Here, the expert’s testimony is shown to be false and fails to establish that the accused’s fingerprints were found in the room, and there is no (other) factual basis for believing that he was in the room. The factual premise from which an inference is sought to be drawn towards the accused’s guilt is not established.

Fourthly, the conditions for something to be received (or, in technical term “admitted”) as evidence at the trial are sometimes included in the legal concept of evidence. (These conditions are discussed in section 2 below.) On this conception, legal evidence is that which counts as evidence in law. Something may ordinarily be treated as evidence and yet be rejected by the court. Hearsay is often cited as an example. It is pointed out that reliance on hearsay is a commonplace in ordinary life. We frequently rely on hearsay in forming our factual beliefs. In contrast, “hearsay is not evidence” in legal proceedings (Stephen 1872: 4–5). As a general rule, the court will not rely on hearsay as a premise for an inference towards the truth of what is asserted. It will not allow a witness to testify in court that another person X (who is not brought before the court) said that p on a certain occasion (an out-of-court statement) for the purpose of proving that p .

In summary, at least four possible conceptions of legal evidence are in currency: as an object of sensory evidence, as a proposition of fact, as an inferential premise and as that which counts as evidence in law. The sense in which the term “evidence” is being used is seldom made explicit in legal discourse although the intended meaning will often be clear from the context.

2. Conditions for Receiving Evidence: What Counts as Evidence in Law?

This section picks up on the fourth conception of evidence. To recall, something will be accepted by the court as evidence—it is, to use Montrose’s term, receivable as evidence in legal proceedings—only if three basic conditions are satisfied: relevance , materiality, and admissibility (Montrose 1954). These three conditions of receivability are discussed in turn below.

2.1 Relevance

The concept of relevance plays a pivotal role in legal fact-finding. Thayer (1898: 266, 530) articulates its significance in terms of two foundational principles of the law of evidence: first, without exception, nothing which is not relevant may be received as evidence by the court and secondly, subject to many exceptions and qualifications, whatever is relevant is receivable as evidence by the court. Thayer’s view has been influential and finds expression in sources of law, for example, in Rule 402 of the Federal Rules of Evidence in the United States. [ 7 ] Thayer claims, and it is now widely accepted, that relevance is a “logical” and not a legal concept; in section 2.1.3 , we will examine this claim and the dissent expressed by Wigmore. Leaving aside the dissenting view for the moment, we will turn first to consider possible conceptions of relevance in the conventional sense of logical relevance.

Evidence may be adduced in legal proceedings to prove a fact only if the fact is relevant. Relevance is a relational concept. No fact is relevant in itself; it is relevant only in relation to another fact. The term “probable” is often used to describe this relation. We see two instances of this in the following well-known definitions. According to Stephen (1886: 2, emphasis added):

The word “relevant” means that any two facts to which it is applied are so related to each other that according to the common course of events one either taken by itself or in connection with other facts proves or renders probable the past, present, or future existence or non-existence of the other.

The second definition is contained in the United States’ Federal Rule of Evidence 401 which (in its restyled version) states that evidence is relevant if “it has a tendency to make a fact more or less probable than it would be without the evidence” (emphasis added). The word “probable” in these and other standard definitions is sometimes construed as carrying the mathematical meaning of probability. [ 8 ] In a leading article, Lempert gave this example to show how relevance turns on the likelihood ratio. The prosecution produces evidence that the perpetrator’s blood found at the scene of the crime is type A. The accused has the same blood type. Suppose fifty percent of the suspect population has type A blood. If the accused is in fact guilty, the probability that the blood found at the scene will be type A is 1.0. But if he is in fact innocent, the probability of finding type A blood at the scene is 0.5—that is, it matches the background probability of type A blood from the suspect population. The likelihood ratio is the ratio of the first probability to the second—1.0:0.5 or, more simply, 2:1. Evidence is considered relevant so long as the likelihood ratio is other than 1:1 (Lempert 1977). If the ratio is 1:1, that means that the probability of the evidence is the same whether the accused is guilty or innocent.

The conventional view is that relevance in law is a binary concept: evidence is either relevant or it is not. So long as the likelihood ratio is other than 1:1, the evidence is considered relevant. [ 9 ] However, the greater the likelihood ratio deviates from 1:1, the higher the so-called probative value of the evidence (that is, on one interpretation of probative value). We will take a closer look at probative value in section 3.1 below.

While the likelihood ratio may be useful as a heuristic device in analysing evidential reasoning, it is controversial as to whether it captures correctly the concept of relevance. In the first place, it is unclear that the term “probable” in the standard definitions of relevance was ever intended as a reference to mathematical probability. Some have argued that relevance should be understood broadly such that any evidence would count as relevant so long as it provides some reason in support of the conclusion that a proposition of fact material to the case is true or false (Pardo 2013: 576–577).

The mathematical conception of relevance has been disputed. At a trial, it is very common for the opposing sides to present competing accounts of events that share certain features. To use Allen’s example, the fact that the accused drove to a particular town on a particular day and time is consistent with the prosecution’s case that he was driving there to commit a murder and also with the defence’s case that he was driving there to visit his mother. This fact, being a common feature of both sides’ explanations of the material events, is as consistent with the hypothesis of guilt as with the hypothesis of innocence. On the likelihood ratio conception of relevance, this fact should be irrelevant and hence evidence of it should not be allowed to be adduced. But in such cases, the court will let the evidence in (Park et al. 2010: 10). The mathematical theory of relevance cannot account for this. (For critical discussion of this claim, see section 4.2 of the entry on legal probabilism .) It is argued that an alternative theory of relevance better fits legal practice and is thus to be preferred. On an explanatory conception of relevance, evidence is relevant if it is explained by or provides a reason for believing the particular explanation of the material events offered by the side adducing the evidence, and it remains relevant even where, as in our example, the evidence also supports or forms part of the explanation offered by the opponent (Pardo and Allen 2008: 241–2; Pardo 2013: 600).

One possible response to the above challenge to the likelihood ratio theory of relevance is to deny that it was ever meant to be the exclusive test of relevance. Evidence is relevant if the likelihood ratio is other than 1:1. But evidence may also be relevant on other grounds, such as when it provides for a richer narrative or helps the court in understanding other evidence. It is for these reasons that witnesses are routinely allowed to give their names and parties may present diagrams, charts and floor plans (so-called “demonstrative evidence”) at the trial (McCormick 2013: 995). The admission of evidence in the scenario painted by Allen above has been explained along a similar line (Park et al. 2010: 16).

The concept of relevance examined in the preceding section is commonly known as “logical relevance”. This is somewhat of a misnomer: “Relevance is not a matter of logic, but depends on matters of fact” (Haack 2004: 46). In our earlier example, the relevance of the fact that the accused has type A blood depends obviously on the state of the world. On the understanding that relevance is a probabilistic relation, it is tempting to think that in describing relevance as “logical”, one is subscribing to a logical theory of probability (cf. Franklin 2011). However, the term “logical relevance” was not originally coined with this connotation in mind. In the forensic context, “logic” is used loosely and refers to the stock of background beliefs or generalisations and the type of reasoning that judges and lawyers are fond of labelling as “commonsense” (MacCrimmon 2001–2002; Twining 2006: 334–335).

A key purpose of using the adjective “logical” is to flag the non-legal character of relevance. As Thayer (1898: 269) famously claimed, relevance “is an affair of logic and not of law.” This is not to say that relevance has no legal dimension. The law distinguishes between questions of law and questions of fact. An issue of relevance poses a question of law that is for the judge to decide and not the jury, and so far as relevance is defined in legal sources (for example, in Federal Rule of Evidence 401 mentioned above), the judge must pay heed to the legal definition. But legal definitions of relevance are invariably very broad. Relevance is said to be a logical, and non-legal, concept in the sense that in answering a question of relevance and in applying the definition of relevance, the judge has necessarily to rely on extra-legal resources and is not bound by legal precedents. Returning to Federal Rule of Evidence 401, it states generally that evidence is relevant if “it has a tendency to make a fact more or less probable than it would be without the evidence”. In deciding whether the evidence sought to be adduced does have this tendency, the judge has to look outside the law. Thayer was most insistent on this. As he put it, “[t]he law furnishes no test of relevancy. For this, it tacitly refers to logic and general experience” (Thayer 1898: 265). That the accused’s favorite color is blue is, barring extraordinary circumstances, irrelevant to the question of his intention to commit theft. It is not the law that tells us so but “logic and general experience”. On Thayer’s view, the law does not control or regulate the assessment of relevance; it assumes that judges are already in possession of the (commonsense) resources to undertake this assessment.

Wigmore adopts a different position. He argues, against Thayer, that relevance is a legal concept. There are two strands to his contention. The first is that for evidence to be relevant in law, “a generally higher degree of probative value” is required “than would be asked in ordinary reasoning”:

legal relevance denotes…something more than a minimum of probative value. Each single piece of evidence must have a plus value. (cf. Pattenden 1996–7: 373)

As Wigmore sees it, the requirement of “plus value” guards against the jury “being satisfied by matters of slight value, capable to being exaggerated by prejudice and hasty reasoning” (Wigmore 1983b: 969, cf. 1030–1031). Opponents of Wigmore acknowledge that there may be sound policy reasons for excluding evidence of low probative value. Receiving the evidence at the trial might raise a multiplicity of issues, incur too much time and expense, confuse the jurors or produce undue prejudice in their mind. When the judge excludes evidence for any of these reasons, and the judge has the discretion to do so in many countries, the evidence is excluded despite it being relevant (e.g., United States’ Federal Rule of Evidence 403). Relevance is a relation between facts and the aforesaid reasons for exclusion are extrinsic to that relation; they are grounded in considerations such as limitation of judicial resources and jury psychology. The notion of “plus value” confuses relevance with extraneous considerations (James 1941; Trautman 1952).

There is a second strand to Wigmore’s contention that relevance is a legal concept. Relevance is legal in the sense that the judge is bound by previously decided cases (“judicial precedents”) when he has to make a ruling on the relevance of a proposed item of evidence.

So long as Courts continue to declare…what their notions of logic are, just so long will there be rules of law which must be observed. (Wigmore 1983a: 691)

Wigmore cites in support the judgment of Cushing C.J. in State v LaPage where it was remarked:

[T]here are many instances in which the evidence of particular facts as bearing on particular issues has been so often the subject of discussion in courts of law, and so often ruled upon, that the united logic of a great many judges and lawyers may be said to furnish…the best evidence of what may be properly called common -sense, and thus to acquire the authority of law. (1876 57 N.H. 245 at 288 [Supreme Court, New Hampshire])

Wigmore’s position on relevance is strangely at odds with his strong stand against the judge being bound by judicial precedents in assessing the weight or credibility of evidence (Wigmore 1913). More importantly, the second strand of his argument also does not sit well with the first strand. If, as Wigmore contends, evidence must have a plus value to make it legally relevant, the court has to consider the probative value of the evidence and to weigh it against the amount of time and expense likely to be incurred in receiving the evidence, the availability of other evidence, the risk of the evidence misleading or confusing the trier of fact and so forth. Given that the assessment of plus value and, hence, legal relevance is so heavily contextual, it is difficult to see how a judicial precedent can be of much value in another case in determining a point of legal relevance (James 1941: 702).

We have just considered the first condition of receivability, namely, relevance. That fact A is relevant to fact B is not sufficient to make evidence of fact A receivable in court. In addition, B must be a “material” fact. The materiality of facts in a particular case is determined by the law applicable to that case. In a criminal prosecution, it depends on the law which defines the offence with which the accused is charged and at a civil trial, the law which sets out the elements of the legal claim that is being brought against the defendant (Wigmore 1983a, 15–19; Montrose 1954: 536–537).

Imagine that the accused is prosecuted for the crime of rape and the alleged victim’s behaviour (fact A ) increases the probability that she had consented to have sexual intercourse with the accused (fact B ). On the probabilistic theory of relevance that we have considered, A is relevant to B . Now suppose that the alleged victim is a minor. Under criminal law, it does not matter whether she had consented to the sexual intercourse. If B is of no legal consequence, the court will not allow evidence of A to be adduced for the purpose of proving B : the most obvious reason is that it is a waste of time to receive the evidence.

Not all material facts are necessarily in dispute. Suppose the plaintiff sues the defendant for breach of contract. Under the law of contract, to succeed in this action, the plaintiff must prove the following three elements: that there was a contract between the parties, that the defendant was in breach of the contract, and that the plaintiff had suffered loss as a result of that breach. The defendant may concede that there was a contract and that he was in breach of it but deny that the plaintiff had suffered any loss as a result of that breach. In such a situation, only the last of the material facts is disputed. Following Stephen’s terminology, a disputed material fact is called a “fact in issue” (Stephen 1872: 9).

The law does not allow evidence to be adduced to prove facts that are immaterial. Whether evidence may be adduced to prove a material fact may depend on whether the material fact is disputed; for instance, the requirement that it must be disputed exists under Rule 210 of the Evidence Code of California but not Rule 401 of the Federal Rules of Evidence in the United States. “Relevance” is often used in the broader sense that encompasses the concepts under discussion. Evidence is sometimes described as “irrelevant” not for the reason that no logical inference can be drawn to the proposition that is sought to be proved (in our example, A is strictly speaking relevant to B ) but because that proposition is not material or not disputed (in our example, B is not material). [ 10 ] This broader usage of the term “relevance”, though otherwise quite harmless, does not promote conceptual clarity because it runs together different concepts (see James 1941: 690–691; Trautman 1952: 386; Montrose 1954: 537).

2.3 Admissibility

A further condition must be satisfied for evidence to be received in legal proceedings. There are legal rules that prohibit evidence from being presented at a trial even though it is relevant to a factual proposition that is material and in issue. These rules render the evidence to which they apply “inadmissible” and require the judge to “exclude” it. Two prominent examples of such rules of admissibility or rules of exclusion are the rule against hearsay evidence and the rule against character evidence. This section considers the relation between the concept of relevance and the concept of admissibility. The next section ( section 2.3.2 ) discusses general arguments for and against exclusionary or admissibility rules.

Here, again, the terminology is imprecise. Admissibility and receivability are not clearly distinguished. It is common for irrelevant evidence, or evidence of an immaterial fact to be described as “inadmissible”. What this means is that the court will refuse to receive evidence if it is irrelevant or immaterial. But, importantly, the court also excludes evidence for reasons other than irrelevance and immateriality. For Montrose, there is merit in restricting the concept of “inadmissibility” to the exclusion of evidence based on those other reasons (Montrose 1954: 541–543). If evidence is rejected on the ground of irrelevance, it is, as Thayer (1898: 515) puts it, “the rule of reason that rejects it”; if evidence is rejected under an admissibility or exclusionary rule, the rejection is by force of law. The concepts of admissibility and materiality should also be kept apart. This is because admissibility or exclusionary rules serve purposes and rationales that are distinct from the law defining the crime or civil claim that is before the court and it is this law that determines the materiality of facts in the dispute.

Thayer (1898: 266, 530) was influential in his view that the law of evidence has no say on logical relevance and that its main business is in dealing with admissibility. If the evidence is logically irrelevant, it must for that reason be excluded. If the evidence is logically relevant, it will be received by the court unless the law—in the form of an exclusionary or admissibility rule—requires its exclusion. In this scheme, the concept of relevance and the concept of admissibility are distinct: indeed, admissibility rules presuppose the relevance of the evidence to which they apply.

Stephen appears to hold a different view, one in which the concept of admissibility is apparently absorbed by the concept of relevance. Take, for example, Stephen’s analysis of the rule that in general no evidence may be adduced to prove “statements as to facts made by persons not called as witnesses”, in short, hearsay (Stephen 1872: 122). As a general rule, no evidence may be given of hearsay because the law prohibits it. The question then arises as to the rationale for this prohibition. Stephen’s answer to this question is often taken to be that hearsay is not “relevant” and he is criticised for failing to see the difference between relevance and admissibility (Whitworth 1881: 3; Thayer 1898: 266–268; Pollock 1876, 1899; Wigmore 1983a: §12). His critics point out that hearsay has or can have probative value and evidence of hearsay is excluded despite or regardless of its relevance. On the generalisation that there is no smoke without fire, the fact that a person claimed that p in a statement made out-of-court does or can have a bearing on the probability that p , and p may be (logically relevant to) a material fact in the dispute.

Interestingly, Stephen seemed to have conceded as much. He acknowledged that a policeman or a lawyer engaged in preparing a case would be negligent if he were to shut his ears to hearsay. Hearsay is one of those facts that are “apparently relevant but not really so” (Stephen 1872: 122; see also Stephen 1886: xi). In claiming that hearsay is irrelevant, Stephen appears to be merely stating the effect of the law: the law requires that hearsay be treated as irrelevant. He offered a variety of justifications for excluding hearsay evidence: its admissibility would “present a great temptation to indolent judges to be satisfied with second-hand reports” and “open a wide door to fraud”, with the result that “[e]veryone would be at the mercy of people who might tell a lie, and whose evidence could neither be tested nor contradicted” (Stephen 1872: 124–125). For his detractors, these are reasons of policy and fairness and it disserves clarity to sneak such considerations into the concept of relevance.

Although there is force to the criticism that Stephen had unhelpfully conflated admissibility and relevance (understood as logical relevance), something can perhaps be said in his defence. Exclusionary rules or rules of admissibility—at any rate, many of them—are more accurately seen as excluding forms of reasoning rather than prohibiting proof of certain types of facts (McNamara 1986). This is certainly true of the hearsay rule. On one authoritative definition of the rule (decision of the Privy Council in Subramaniam v PP , (1956) 1 Weekly Law Reports 965), what it prohibits is the use of a hearsay statement to prove the truth of the facts asserted therein. [ 11 ] The objection is to the drawing of the inference that p from X ’s out-of-court statement that p where X is not available to be examined in court. But the court will allow the evidence of X ’s hearsay statement to be admitted—it will allow proof of the statement— where the purpose of adducing the evidence is to persuade the court that X did make the statement and this fact is relevant for some other purpose. For instance, it may be relevant as to the state of mind of the person hearing the statement, and his state of mind may be material to his defence of having acted under duress. Hence, two writers have commented that “there is no such thing as hearsay evidence , only hearsay uses ” (Roberts and Zuckerman 2010: 385).

Other admissibility rules are also more accurately seen as targeted at forms of reasoning and not types of facts. In the United States, Federal Rule of Evidence 404(a)(1) bars the use of evidence of a person’s character “to prove that on a particular occasion the person acted in accordance with the character” and Federal Rule of Evidence 404(b)(1) provides that evidence of a crime or wrong

is not admissible to prove a person’s character in order to show that on a particular occasion the person acted in accordance with the character.

It is doubtful that evidence of a person’s character and past behaviour can have no probabilistic bearing on his behaviour on a particular occasion; on a probabilistic conception of relevance, it is difficult to see why the evidence is not relevant. Even so, there may be policy, moral or other reasons for the law to prohibit certain uses of character evidence. In declaring a fact as irrelevant for a particular purpose, we are not necessarily saying or implying anything about probability. We may be expressing a normative judgment. For policy, moral or other reasons, the law takes the position that hearsay or the accused’s character or previous misconduct must not be used as the premise for a particular line of reasoning. The line of reasoning might be morally objectionable (“give a dog a bad name and hang him for it”) or it might be unfair to permit the drawing of the inference when the opponent was not given a fair opportunity to challenge it (as in the hearsay situation) (Ho 2008: chs. 5, 6). If we take a normative conception of relevance instead of a logical or probabilistic one, it is not an abuse of language to describe inadmissible evidence as irrelevant if what is meant is that the evidence ought not to be taken into account in a certain way.

On one historical account, admissibility or exclusionary rules are the product of the jury system where citizens untrained in assessing evidence sit as judges of fact. These rules came about because it was thought necessary to keep away from inexperienced jurors certain types of evidence that may mislead or be mishandled by them—for instance, evidence to which they are likely to give too much weight or that carries the risk of creating unfair prejudice in their minds (Thayer 1898; Wigmore 1935: 4–5). Epistemic paternalism is supposedly at play (Leiter 1997: 814–5; Allen and Leiter 2001: 1502). Subscription to this theory has generated pressure for the abolition of exclusionary rules with the decline of the jury system and the replacement of lay persons with professional judges as triers of fact. There is doubt as to the historical accuracy of this account; at any rate, it does not appear capable of explaining the growth of all exclusionary rules (Morgan 1936–37; Nance 1988: 278–294).

Even if the theory is right, it does not necessarily follow that exclusionary rules should be abolished once the jury system is removed. Judges may be as susceptible to the same cognitive and other failings as the jury and there may be the additional risk that judges may over-estimate their own cognitive and intellectual abilities in their professional domain. Hence, there remains a need for the constraints of legal rules (Schauer 2006: 185–193). But the efficacy of these rules in a non-jury system is questionable. The procedural reality is that judges will have to be exposed to the evidence in order to decide on its admissibility. Since a judge cannot realistically be expected to erase the evidence from his mind once he has decided to exclude it, there seems little point in excluding the evidence; we might as well let the evidence in and allow judge to give the evidence the probative value that it deserves (Mnookin 2006; Damaška 2006; cf. Ho 2008: 44–46).

Bentham was a strong critic of exclusionary rules. He was much in favour of “freedom of proof” understood as free access to information and the absence of formal rules that restrict such access (Twining 2006: 232, n 65). The direct object of legal procedure is the “rectitude of decision”, by which he means the correct application of substantive law to true findings of facts. The exclusion of relevant evidence—evidence capable of casting light on the truth—is detrimental to this end. Hence, no relevant evidence should be excluded; the only exceptions he would allow are where the evidence is superfluous or its production would involve preponderant delay, expense or vexation (Bentham 1827: Book IX; Bentham 1825: Book VII; Twining 1985: ch. 2). Bentham’s argument has been challenged on various fronts. It is said that he overvalued the pursuit of truth, undervalued procedural fairness and procedural rights, and placed too much faith in officials, underestimating the risk of abuse when they are given discretion unfettered by rules (Twining 1985: 70–71).

Even if we agree with Bentham that rectitude of decision is the aim of legal procedure and that achieving accuracy in fact-finding is necessary to attain this aim, it is not obvious that a rule-based approach to admissibility will undermine this aim in the long run. Schauer has defended exclusionary rules of evidence along a rule-consequentialist line. Having the triers of fact follow rules on certain matters instead of allowing them the discretion to exercise judgment on a case-by-case basis may produce the greatest number of favourable outcomes in the aggregate. It is in the nature of a formal rule that it has to be followed even when doing so might not serve the background reason for the rule. If hearsay evidence is thought to be generally unreliable, the interest of accuracy may be better served overall to require such evidence to be excluded without regard to its reliability in individual cases. Given the imperfection of human reason and our suspicion about the reasoning ability of the fact-finder, allowing decisions to be taken individually on the reliability and admissibility of hearsay evidence might over time produce a larger proportion of misjudgements than on the rule-based approach (Schauer 2006: 180–185; Schauer 2008). However, this argument is based on a large assumption about the likely effects of having exclusionary rules and not having them, and there is no strong empirical basis for thinking that the consequences are or will be as alleged (Goldman 1999: 292–295; Laudan 2006: 121–122).

Other supporters of exclusionary rules build their arguments on a wide range of different considerations. The literature is too vast to enter into details. Here is a brief mention of some arguments. On one theory, some exclusionary rules are devices that serve as incentives for lawyers to produce the epistemically best evidence that is reasonably available (Nance 1988, 2016: 195–201). For example, if lawyers are not allowed to rely on second-hand (hearsay) evidence, they will be forced to seek out better (first-hand) evidence. On another theory, exclusionary rules allocate the risks of error. Again, consider hearsay. The problem with allowing a party to rely on hearsay evidence is that the opponent has no opportunity to cross-examine the original maker of the statement and is thus deprived of an important means of attacking the reliability of the evidence. Exclusionary rules in general insulate the party against whom the evidence is sought to be adduced from the risks of error that the evidence, if admitted, would have introduced. The distribution of such risks is said to be a political decision that should not be left to the discretion of individual fact-finders (Stein 2005; cf. Redmayne 2006 and Nance 2007a: 154–164). It has also been argued that the hearsay rule and the accompanying right to confront witnesses promote the public acceptance and stability of legal verdicts. If the court relies on direct evidence, it can claim superior access to the facts (having heard from the horse’s mouth, so to speak) and this also reduces the risk of new information emerging after the trial to discredit the inference that was drawn from the hearsay evidence (the original maker of the statement might turn up after the trial to deny the truth of the statement that was attributed to him) (Nesson 1985: 1372–1375; cf. Park 1986; Goldman 1999: 282; Goldman 2005: 166–167).

3. Strength of Evidence

The decision whether to allow a party to adduce a particular item of evidence is one that the judge has to make and arises in the course of a trial. Section 2 above dealt with the conditions that must be satisfied for a witness’s testimony, a document or an object to be received as evidence. At the end of the trial, the fact-finder must consider all the evidence that has been presented and reach a verdict. Although verdict deliberation is sometimes subjected to various forms of control through legal devices such as presumptions and corroboration rules, such control is limited and the fact-finder is expected to exercise personal judgment in the evaluation of evidence (Damaška 2019). Having heard or seen the evidence, the fact-finder now has to evaluate or ‘weigh’ it in reaching the verdict. Weight can refer to any of the following three properties of evidence: (a) the probative value of individual items of evidence, (b) the sufficiency of the whole body of evidence adduced at the trial in meeting the standard of proof, or (c) the relative completeness of this body of evidence. The first two aspects of weight are familiar to legal practitioners but the third has been confined to academic discussions. These three ideas are discussed in the same order below.

In reaching the verdict, the trier of fact has to assess the probative value of the individual items of evidence which have been received at the trial. The concept of probative value can also play a role at the prior stage (which was the focus in section 2 ) where the judge has to make a ruling on whether to receive the evidence in the first place. In many legal systems, if the judge finds the probative value of a proposed item of evidence to be low and substantially outweighed by countervailing considerations, such as the risk of causing unfair prejudice or confusion, the judge can refuse to let the jury hear or see the evidence (see, e.g., Rule 403 of the United States’ Federal Rules of Evidence).

The concept of probative value (or, as it is also called, probative force) is related to the concept of relevance. Section 2.1.2 above introduced and examined the claim that the likelihood ratio is the measure of relevance. To recapitulate, the likelihood of an item of evidence, E (in our previous example, the likelihood of a blood type match) given a hypothesis H (that the accused is in fact guilty) is compared with the likelihood of E given the negation of H (that the accused is in fact innocent). Prior to the introduction of E , one may have formed some belief about H based on other evidence that one already has. This prior belief does not affect the likelihood ratio since its computation is based on the alternative assumptions that H is true and that H is false (Kaye 1986a; Kaye and Koehler 2003; cf. Davis and Follette 2002 and 2003). Rulings on relevance are made by the judge when objections of irrelevance are raised in the course of the trial. The relevance of an item of evidence is supposedly assessed on its own, without consideration of other evidence, and, indeed, much of the other evidence may have yet to presented at the point when the judge rules on the relevance of a particular item of evidence (Mnookin 2013: 1544–5). [ 12 ]

Probative value, as with relevance, has been explained in terms of the likelihood ratio (for detailed examples, see Nance and Morris 2002; Finkelstein and Levin 2003). It was noted earlier that evidence is either relevant or not, and, on the prevailing understanding, it is relevant so long as the likelihood ratio deviates from 1:1. But evidence can be more or less probative depending on the value of the likelihood ratio. In our earlier example, the probative value of a blood type match was 1.0:0.5 (or 2:1) as 50% of the suspect population had the same blood type as the accused. But suppose the blood type is less common and only 25% of the suspect population has it. The probative value of the evidence is now 1.0:0.25 (or 4:1). In both cases, the evidence is relevant; but the probative value is greater in the latter than in the former scenario. It is tempting to describe probative value as the degree of relevance but this would be misleading as relevance in law is a binary concept.

There is a second way of thinking about probative value. On the second view, but not on the first, the probative value of an item of evidence is assessed contextually. The probative value of E may be low given one state of the other evidence and substantial given a different body of other evidence (Friedman 1986; Friedman and Park 2003; cf. Davis and Follette 2002, 2003). Where the other evidence shows that a woman had died from falling down an escalator at a mall while she was out shopping, her husband’s history of spousal battery is unlikely to have any probative value in proving that he was responsible for her death. But where the other evidence shows that the wife had died of injuries in the matrimonial home, and the question is whether the injuries were sustained from an accidental fall from the stairs or inflicted by the husband, the same evidence of spousal battery will now have significant probative value.

On the second view, the probative value of an item of evidence ( E ) is not measured simply by the likelihood ratio as it is on the first view. Probative value is understood as the degree to which E increases (or decreases) the probability of the proposition or hypothesis ( H ) in support of (or against) which E is led. The probative value of E is measured by the difference between the probability of H given E (the posterior probability) and the probability of H absent E (the prior probability) (Friedman 1986; James 1941: 699).

Probative value of \(E = P(H | E) - P(H)\)

\(P(H | E)\) (the posterior probability) is derived by applying Bayes’ theorem—that is, by multiplying the prior probability by the likelihood ratio (see discussion in section 3.2.2 below). On the present view, while the likelihood ratio does not itself measure the probative value of E , it is nevertheless a crucial component in the assessment.

A major difficulty with both of the mathematical conceptions of probative value that we have just examined is that for most evidence, obtaining the figures necessary for computing the likelihood ratio is problematic (Allen 1991: 380). Exceptionally, quantitative base rates data exist, as in our blood type example. Where objective data is unavailable, the fact-finder has to draw on background experience and knowledge to come up with subjective values. In our blood type example, a critical factor in computing the likelihood ratio was the percentage of the “suspect population” who had the same blood type as the accused. “Reference class” is the general statistical term for the role that the suspect population plays in this analysis. How should the reference class of “suspect population” be defined? Should we look at the population of the country as a whole or of the town or the street where the alleged murder occurred? What if it occurred at an international airport where most the people around are foreign visitors? Or what if it is shown that both the accused and the victim were at the time of the alleged murder inmates of the same prison? Should we then take the prison population as the reference class? The distribution of blood types may differ according to which reference class is selected. Sceptics of mathematical modelling of probative value emphasize that data from different reference classes will have different explanatory power and the choice of the reference class is open to—and should be subjected to—contextual argument and requires the exercise of judgment; there is no a priori way of determining the correct reference class. (On the reference class problem in legal factfinding, see, in addition to references cited in the rest of this section, Colyvan, Regan, and Ferson 2001; Tillers 2005; Allen and Roberts 2007.)

Some writers have proposed quantifiable ways of selecting, or assisting in the selection, of the appropriate reference class. On one suggestion, the court does not have to search for the optimal reference class. A general characteristic of an adversarial system of trial is that the judge plays a passive role; it is up to the parties to come up with the arguments on which they want to rely and to produce evidence in support of their respective arguments. This adversarial setting makes the reference class problem more manageable as the court need only to decide which of the reference classes relied upon by the parties is to be preferred. And this can be done by applying one of a variety of technical criteria that statisticians have developed for comparing and selecting statistical models (Cheng 2009). Another suggestion is to use the statistical method of “feature selection” instead. The ideal reference class is defined by the intersection of all relevant features of the case, and a feature is relevant if it is correlated to the matter under enquiry (Franklin 2010, 2011: 559–561). For instance, if the amount of drug likely to be smuggled is reasonably believed to co-vary with the airport through which it is smuggled, the country of origin and the time period, and there is no evidence that any other feature is relevant on which data is available, the ideal reference class is the class of drug smugglers passing through that airport originating from that country and during that time period. Both suggestions have self-acknowledged limitations: not least, they depend on the availability of suitable data. Also, as Franklin stresses, while statistical methods “have advice to offer on how courts should judge quantitative evidence”, they do so “in a way that supplements normal intuitive legal argument rather than replacing it by a formula” (Franklin 2010: 22).

The reference class problem is not confined to the probabilistic assessment of the probative value of individual items of evidence. It is a general difficulty with a mathematical approach to legal proof. In particular, the same problem arises on a probabilistic interpretation of the standard of proof when the court has to determine whether the standard is met based on all the evidence adduced in the case. This topic is explored in section 3.2 below but it is convenient at this juncture to illustrate how the reference class problem can also arise in this connection. Let it be that the plaintiff sues Blue Bus Company to recover compensation for injuries sustained in an accident. The plaintiff testifies, and the court believes on the basis of his testimony, that he was run down by a recklessly driven bus. Unfortunately, it was dark at the time and he cannot tell whether the bus belonged to Blue Bus Company. Assume further that there is also evidence which establishes that Blue Bus Company owns 75% of the buses in the town where the accident occurred and the remaining 25% is owned by Red Bus Company. No other evidence is presented. To use the data as the basis for inferring that there is 0.75 probability that the bus involved in the accident was owned by Blue Bus Company would seem to privilege the reference class of “buses operating in the town” over other possible reference classes such as “buses plying the street where the accident occurred” or “buses operating at the time in question” (Allen and Pardo 2007a: 109). Different reference classes may produce very different likelihood ratios. It is crucial how the reference class is chosen and this is ultimately a matter of argument and judgment. Any choice of reference class (other than the class that shares every feature of the particular incident, which is, in effect, the unique incident itself) is in principle contestable.

Critics of the mathematization of legal proof raise this point as an example of inherent limitations to the mathematical modelling of probative value (Allen and Pardo 2007a). [ 13 ] Allen and Pardo propose an alternative, the explanatory theory of legal proof. They claim that this theory has the advantage of avoiding the reference class problem because it does not attempt to quantify probative value (Pardo 2005: 374–383; Pardo and Allen 2008: 261, 263; Pardo 2013: 600–601). Suppose a man is accused of killing his wife. Evidence is produced of his extra-marital affair. The unique probative value of the accused’s infidelity cannot be mathematically computed from statistical base rates of infidelity and uxoricides (husbands murdering wives). In assessing its probative value, the court should look instead at how strongly the evidence of infidelity supports the explanation of the material events put forward by the side adducing the evidence and how strongly it challenges the explanation offered by the opponent. For instance, the prosecution may be producing the evidence to buttress its case that the accused wanted to get rid of his wife so that he could marry his mistress, and the defence may be advancing the alternative theory that the couple was unusual in that they condoned extra-marital affairs and had never let it affect their loving relationship. How much probative value the evidence of infidelity has depends on the strength of the explanatory connections between it and the competing hypotheses, and this is not something that can be quantified.

But the disagreement in this debate is not as wide as it might appear. The critics concede that formal models for evaluating evidence in law may be useful. What they object to is

scholarship arguing … that such models establish the correct or accurate probative value of evidence, and thus implying that any deviations from such models lead to inaccurate or irrational outcomes. (Allen and Pardo 2007b: 308)

On the other side, it is acknowledged that there are limits to mathematical formalisation of evidential reasoning in law (Franklin 2012: 238–9) and that context, argument and judgment do play a role in identifying the reference class (Nance 2007b).

3.2 Sufficiency of Evidence and the Standards of Proof

In the section 3.1 above, we concentrated on the weight of evidence in the sense of probative value of individual items of evidence. The concept of weight can also apply to the total body of evidence presented at the trial; here “weight” is commonly referred to as the “sufficiency of evidence”. [ 14 ] The law assigns the legal burden of proof between parties to a dispute. For instance, at a criminal trial, the accused is presumed innocent and the burden is on the prosecution to prove that he is guilty as charged. To secure a conviction, the body of evidence presented at the trial must be sufficient to meet the standard of proof. Putting this generally, a verdict will be given in favour of the side bearing the legal burden of proof only if, having considered all of the evidence, the fact-finder is satisfied that the applicable standard of proof is met. The standard of proof has been given different interpretations.

On one interpretation, the standard of proof is a probabilistic threshold. In civil cases, the standard is the “balance of probabilities” or, as it is more popularly called in the United States, the “preponderance of evidence”. The plaintiff will satisfy this standard and succeed in his claim only if there is, on all the evidence adduced in the case, more than 0.5 probability of his claim being true. At criminal trials, the standard for a guilty verdict is “proof beyond a reasonable doubt”. Here the probabilistic threshold is thought to be much higher than 0.5 but courts have eschewed any attempt at authoritative quantification. Typically, a notional value, such as 0.9 or 0.95, is assumed by writers for the sake of discussion. For the prosecution to secure a guilty verdict, the evidence adduced at the trial must establish the criminal charge to a degree of probability that crosses this threshold. Where, as in the United States, there is an intermediate standard of “clear and convincing evidence” which is reserved for special cases, the probabilistic threshold is said to lie somewhere between 0.5 and the threshold for proof beyond reasonable doubt.

Kaplan was among the first to employ decision theory to develop a framework for setting the probabilistic threshold that represents the standard of proof. Since the attention in this area of the law tends to be on the avoidance of errors and their undesirable consequences, he finds it convenient to focus on disutility rather than utility. The expected disutility of an outcome is the product of the disutility (broadly, the social costs) of that outcome and the probability of that outcome. Only two options are generally available to the court: in criminal cases, it must either convict or acquit the accused and in civil cases, it has to give judgment either for the plaintiff or for the defendant. At a criminal trial, the decision should be made to convict where the expected disutility of a decision to acquit is greater than the expected disutility of a decision to convict. This is so as to minimize the expected disutilities. To put this in the form of an equation:

P is the probability that the accused is guilty on the basis of all the evidence adduced in the case, Dag is the disutility of acquitting a guilty person and Dci is the disutility of convicting an innocent person. A similar analysis applies to civil cases: the defendant should be found liable where the expected disutility of finding him not liable when he is in fact liable exceeds the expected disutility of finding him liable when he is in fact not liable.

On this approach, a person should be convicted of a crime only where P is greater than:

The same formula applies in civil cases except that the two disutilities ( Dag and Dci ) will have to be replaced by their civil equivalents (framed in terms of the disutility of awarding the judgment to a plaintiff who in fact does not deserve it and disutility of awarding the judgment to a defendant who in fact does not deserve it). On this formula, the crucial determinant of the standard of proof is the ratio of the two disutilities. In the civil context, the disutility of an error in one direction is deemed equal to the disutility of an error in the other direction. Hence, a probability of liability of greater than 0.5 would suffice for a decision to enter judgment against the defendant (see Redmayne 1996: 171). The situation is different at a criminal trial. Dci , the disutility of convicting an innocent person is considered far greater than Dag , the disutility of acquitting a guilty person. [ 15 ] Hence, the probability threshold for a conviction should be much higher than 0.5 (Kaplan 1968: 1071–1073; see also Cullison 1969).

An objection to this analysis is that it is incomplete. It is not enough to compare the costs of erroneous verdicts. The utility of an accurate conviction and the utility of an accurate acquittal should also be considered and factored into the equation (Lillquist 2002: 108). [ 16 ] This results in the following modification of the formula for setting the standard of proof:

Ucg is the utility of convicting the guilty, Uag is the utility of acquitting the guilty, Uai is the utility of acquitting the innocent and Uci the utility of convicting the innocent.

Since the relevant utilities depend on the individual circumstances, such as the seriousness of the crime and the severity of the punishment, the decision-theoretic account of the standard of proof would seem, on both the simple and the modified version, to lead to the conclusion that the probabilistic threshold should vary from case to case (Lillquist 2002; Bartels 1981; Laudan and Saunders 2009; Ribeiro 2019). In other words, the standard of proof should be a flexible or floating one. This view is perceived to be problematic.

First, it falls short descriptively. The law requires the court to apply a fixed standard of proof for all cases within the relevant category. In theory, all criminal cases are governed by the same high standard and all civil cases are governed by the same lower standard. That said, it is unclear whether factfinders in reality adhere strictly to a fixed standard of proof (see Kaplow 2012: 805–809).

The argument is better interpreted as a normative argument—as advancing the claim about what the law ought to be and not what it is. The standard of proof ought to vary from case to case. But this proposal faces a second objection. For convenience, the objection will be elaborated in the criminal setting; in principle, civil litigants have the same two rights that we shall identify. According to Dworkin (1981), moral harm arises as an objective moral fact when a person is erroneously convicted of a crime. Moral harm is distinguished from the bare harm (in the form of pain, frustration, deprivation of liberty and so forth) that is suffered by a wrongfully convicted and punished person. While accused persons have the right not to be convicted if innocent, they do not have the right to the most accurate procedure possible for ascertaining their guilt or innocence. However, they do have the right that a certain weight or importance be attached to the risk of moral harm in the design of procedural and evidential rules that affect the level of accuracy. Accused persons have the further right to a consistent weighting of the importance of moral harm and this further right stems from their right to equal concern and respect. Dworkin’s theory carries an implication bearing on the present debate. It is arguable that to adopt a floating standard of proof would offend the second right insofar as it means treating accused persons differently with respect to the evaluation of the importance of avoiding moral harm. This difference in treatment is reflected in the different level of the risk of moral harm to which they are exposed.

There is a third objection to a floating standard of proof. Picinali (2013) sees fact-finding as a theoretical exercise that engages the question of what to believe about the disputed facts. What counts as “reasonable” for the purposes of applying the standard of proof beyond reasonable doubt is accordingly a matter for theoretical as opposed to practical reasoning. Briefly, theoretical reasoning is concerned with what to believe whereas practical reasoning is about what to do. Only reasons for belief are germane in theoretical reasoning. While considerations that bear on the assessment of utility and disutility provide reasons for action, they are not reasons for believing in the accused’s guilt. Decision theory cannot therefore be used to support a variable application of the standard of proof beyond reasonable doubt.

The third criticism of a flexible standard of proof does not directly challenge the decision-theoretic analysis of the standard of proof. On that analysis, it would seem that the maximisation of expected utility is the criterion for selecting the appropriate probabilistic threshold to apply and it plays no further role in deciding whether that threshold, once selected, is met on the evidence adduced in the particular case. It is not incompatible with the decision-theoretic analysis to insist that the question of whether the selected threshold is met should be governed wholly by epistemic considerations. However, it is arguable that what counts as good or strong enough theoretical reason for judging, and hence believing, that something is true is dependent on the context, such as what is at stake in believing that it is true. More is at stake at a trial involving the death penalty than in a case of petty shop-lifting; accordingly, there should be stronger epistemic justification for a finding of guilt in the first than in the second case. Philosophical literature on epistemic contextualism and on interest-relative accounts of knowledge and justified belief has been drawn upon to support a variant standard of proof (Ho 2008: ch. 4; see also Amaya 2015: 525–531). [ 17 ]

The premise of the third criticism is that the trier of fact has to make a finding on a disputed factual proposition based on his belief in the proposition. This is contentious. Beliefs are involuntary; we cannot believe something by simply deciding to believe it. The dominant view is that beliefs are context-independent; at any given moment, we cannot believe something in one context and not believe it in another. On the other hand, legal fact-finding involves choice and decision making and it is dependent on the context; for example, evidence that is strong enough to justify a finding of fact in a civil case may not be strong enough to justify the same finding in a criminal case where the standard of proof is higher. It has been argued that the fact-finder has to base his findings not on what he believes but what he accepts (Cohen 1991, 1992: 117–125, Beltrán 2006; cf. Picinali 2013: 868–869). Belief and acceptance are propositional attitudes: they are different attitudes that one can have in relation to a proposition. As Cohen (1992: 4) explains:

to accept that p is to have or adopt a policy of deeming, positing or postulating that p —i.e. of including that proposition or rule among one’s premises for deciding what to do or think in a particular context.

Understanding standards of proof in terms of mathematical probabilities is controversial. It is said to raise a number of paradoxes (Cohen 1977; Allen 1986, 1991; Allen and Leiter 2001; Redmayne 2008). Let us return to our previous example. The defendant, Blue Bus Company, owns 75% of the buses in the town where the plaintiff was injured by a recklessly driven bus and the remaining 25% is owned by Red Bus Company. No other evidence is presented. Leaving aside the reference class problem discussed above, there is a 0.75 probability that the accident was caused by a bus owned by the defendant. On the probabilistic interpretation of the applicable standard of proof (that is, the balance of probabilities), the evidence should be sufficient to justify a verdict in the plaintiff’s favour. But most lawyers would agree that the evidence is insufficient. Another familiar hypothetical scenario is set in the criminal context (Nesson 1979: 1192–1193). Twenty five prisoners are exercising in a prison yard. Twenty four of them suddenly set upon a guard and kill him. The remaining prisoner refuses to participate. We cannot in the ensuing confusion identify the prisoner who refrained from the attack. Subsequently, one prisoner is selected randomly and prosecuted for the murder of the guard. Those are the only facts presented at the trial. The applicable standard is proof beyond a reasonable doubt. Assume that the probabilistic threshold of this standard is 0.95. On the statistical evidence, there is a probability of 0.96 that the defendant is criminally liable. [ 18 ] Despite the statistical probability of liability exceeding the threshold, it is widely agreed that the defendant must be acquitted. In both of the examples just described, why is the evidence insufficient and what does this say about legal standards of proof?

Various attempts have been made to find the answers (for surveys of these attempts, see Enoch and Fisher 2015: 565–571; Redmayne 2008, Ho 2008: 135–143, 168–170; Gardiner 2019b; section 6 of the entry on legal probabilism ). It has been argued that meeting a legal standard of proof is not merely or fundamentally a matter of adducing evidence to establish a mathematical probability of liability beyond a certain level. Standards of proof should be interpreted in epistemic rather than probabilistic terms. According to one interpretation, the evidence is sufficient to satisfy a standard of proof only if it is capable of justifying full or outright belief in the material facts that constitute legal liability and bare statistical evidence, as in our examples, cannot justify such a belief. (Nelkin 2021; Smith 2018; Buchak 2014; Ho 2008: 89–99.) On Smith’s account, the statistical evidence in our two examples fails to justify belief in the proposition that the defendant is liable because the evidence does not normically support that proposition. Evidence normically supports a proposition just in case the situation in which the evidence is true and the proposition is false is less normal, in the sense of requiring more explanation, than the situation in which the evidence and the proposition are both true. Where all that we have is statistical evidence, it could just so happen that the material proposition is false (it could just so happen that the accident-causing bus was red or that the accused was the one who refused to join in the murder), so no further explanation is needed where the proposition is false than where it is true (Smith 2018).

On a different epistemic interpretation, the evidence is sufficient to meet a legal standard of proof, and a finding of legal liability is permissible, only if the factfinder can gain knowledge of the defendant’s liability—to be precise, of the material facts establishing such liability—from the evidence (Duff et al. 2007: 87–91; Pardo 2010; for a critical overview of knowledge-centered accounts, see Gardiner forthcoming). High probability of liability alone will not suffice. On more subtle knowledge-centered theories, the standards of proof are met only if, on the available evidence, there is a sufficiently high probability that the fact finder knows that the defendant is liable (Littlejohn 2020 and 2021; Blome-Tillmann 2017), or only if the fact finder’s credence in the defendant’s liability exceeds the relevant legal threshold and the credence constitutes knowledge (Moss 2018). It is further claimed that the relevant knowledge necessary for a finding of liability cannot be obtained from statistical evidence alone (Littlejohn 2020 and 2021; Blome-Tillmann 2017; Moss 2018 and forthcoming). According to Thomson, this is because the statistical evidence (to take our first example, the 75% ownership of blue buses) is not causally connected with the fact sought to be proved and cannot guarantee the truth of the relevant belief (that the bus which caused the accident was blue) (Thomson 1986). An alternative argument is that knowledge requires the ruling out of all relevant alternatives and, to take our prison scenario, there is no evidence that addresses the possibility that the defendant was the one who refrained from joining in the attack or the possibility that the defendant is less likely to be guilty than an arbitrary prisoner in the yard. (See Moss forthcoming; Moss 2018: 213. Gardiner 2019a adapts the relevant alternatives framework to model legal standards of proof in a non-mathematical way while eschewing a knowledge account of those standards.) Another possible explanation for the failure to know relies on the notion of sensitivity. The belief that the defendant is liable is not sensitive to the truth where it is based on bare statistical evidence; in the bus example, evidence of the market share of buses remain the same whether it is true or not that a blue bus caused the accident (cf. Enoch, Spectre, and Fisher 2012; Enoch and Fisher 2015; Enoch and Spectre 2019 – while suggesting that the lack of knowledge has generally to do with the insensitivity of the belief, the authors deny that knowledge should matter to the imposition of legal liability). Yet another explanation is that it is unsafe to find a person liable on bare statistical evidence. Though safety is sometimes treated as a condition of knowledge (in that knowledge requires a true belief that is safe), one can treat safety as a condition for finding the defendant liable without also taking the position that the finding must be based on knowledge of liability. Safety is commonly understood in terms of whether a belief formed on the same basis would be true in close possible worlds. Roughly, a finding of liability is unsafe where it can easily be wrong in the sense that little in the actual world needs to change for it to be wrong. Whether the requirement of safety can explain why judgment should not entered against the defendant in our two hypothetical cases would depend on whether it can easily happen that the accident-causing bus was red or that the accused is innocent. (See Pritchard 2015 and 2018; Pardo 2018; cf. Gardiner 2020.) While theorizing of standards of proof in epistemic terms has gathered pace in recent years, it is criticised for relying on unrealistic hypotheticals that fail to attend to the actual operation of legal systems and for making impossible epistemological demands (Allen 2020).

There is another paradox in the mathematical interpretation of the standard of proof. This is the “conjunction paradox”. To succeed in a civil claim (or a criminal prosecution), the plaintiff (or the prosecution) will have to prove the material facts—or “elements”—that constitute the civil claim (or criminal charge) that is before the court (see discussion of “materiality” in section 2.2 above). Imagine a claim under the law of negligence that rests on two elements: a breach of duty of care by the defendant (element A ) and causation of harm to the plaintiff (element B ). To win the case, the plaintiff is legally required to prove A and B . For the sake of simplicity, let A and B be mutually independent events. Suppose the evidence establishes A to a probability of 0.6 and B to a probability of 0.7. On the mathematical interpretation of the civil standard of proof, the plaintiff should succeed in his claim since the probability with respect to each of the elements exceeds 0.5. However, according to the multiplication rule of conventional probability calculus, the probability that A and B are both true is the product of their respective probabilities; in this example, it is only 0.42 (obtained by multiplying 0.6 with 0.7). Thus, the overall probability is greater that the defendant deserves to win than that the plaintiff deserves to win, and yet the verdict is awarded in favour of the plaintiff.

One way of avoiding the conjunction paradox is to take the position that it should not be enough for each element to cross the probabilistic threshold; the plaintiff (or the prosecution) should win only if the probability of the plaintiff’s (or prosecution’s) case as a whole exceeds the applicable probabilistic threshold. So, in our example, the plaintiff should lose since the overall probability is below 0.5. But this suggested solution is unsatisfactory. The required level of overall probability would then turn on how many elements the civil claim or criminal charge happens to have. The greater the number of elements, the higher the level of probability to which, on average, each of them must be proved. This is thought to be arbitrary and hence objectionable. As two commentators noted, the legal definition of theft contains more elements than that for murder. Criminal law is not the same in all countries. We may take the following as a convenient approximation of what the law is in some countries: murder is (1) an act that caused the death of a person (2) that was done with the intention of causing the death, and to constitute theft, there must be (1) an intention to take property, (2) dishonesty in taking the property, (3) removal of the property from the possession of another person, and (4) lack of consent by that person. Since the offence of theft contains twice the number of elements as compared to murder, the individual elements for theft would have to be proved to a much higher level of probability (in order for the probability of their conjunction to cross the overall threshold) than the individual elements for the much more serious crime of murder (Allen and Leiter 2001: 1504–5). This is intuitively unacceptable.

Another proposal for resolving the conjunction paradox is move away from thinking of the standard of proof as a quantified threshold of absolute probability and to construe it, instead, as a probability ratio. The fact-finder has to compare the probability of the evidence adduced at the trial under the plaintiff’s theory of the case with the probability of the evidence under the defendant’s theory of the case (the two need not add to 1), and award the verdict to the side with a higher probability (Cheng 2013). One criticism of this interpretation of the standard of proof is that it ignores, and does not provide a basis for ignoring, the margin by which one probability exceeds the other, and the difference in probability may vary significantly for different elements of the case (Allen and Stein 2013: 598).

There is a deeper problem with the probabilistic conception of the standard of proof. There does not seem to be a satisfactory interpretation of probability that suits the forensic context. The only plausible candidate is the subjective meaning of probability according to which probability is construed as the strength of belief. The evidence is sufficient to satisfy the legal standard of proof on a disputed question of fact—for example, it is sufficient to justify the positive finding of fact that the accused killed the victim—only if the fact-finder, having considered the evidence, forms a sufficiently strong belief that the accused killed the victim. Guidance on how to process evidence and form beliefs can be found in a mathematical theorem known as Bayes’ theorem; it is the method by which an ideal rational fact-finder would revise or update his beliefs in the light of new evidence. [ 19 ] To return to our earlier hypothetical scenario, suppose the fact-finder initially believes the odds of the accused being guilty is 1:1 (“prior odds”) or, putting this differently, that there is a 0.5 probability of guilt. The fact-finder then receives evidence that blood of type A was found at the scene of the crime and that the accused has type A blood. Fifty percent of the population has this blood type. On the Bayesian approach, the posterior odds are calculated by multiplying the prior odds (1:1) by the likelihood ratio (which, as we saw in section 2.1.2 above, is 2:1). The fact-finder’s belief in the odds of guilt should now be revised to 2:1; the probability of guilt is now increased to 0.67 (Lempert 1977).

The subjectivist Bayesian theory of legal fact-finding has come under attack (see generally Amaya 2015: 82–93; Pardo 2013: 591). First, as we already saw in section 3.1 , ascertainment of the likelihood ratios is highly problematic. Secondly, the Bayesian theory is not sensitive to the weight of evidence which, roughly put, is the amount of evidence that is available. This criticism and the concept of weight are further explored in section 3.3 .

Thirdly, while the Bayesian theorem offers a method for updating probabilities in the light of new evidence, it is silent on what the initial probability should be. In a trial setting, the initial probability cannot be set at zero since this means certainty in the innocence of the accused. No new evidence can then make any difference; whatever the likelihood ratio of the evidence, multiplying it by zero (the prior probability) will still end up with a posterior probability of zero. On the other hand, starting with an initial probability is also problematic. This is especially so in a criminal case. To start a trial with some probability of guilt is to have the fact-finder harbouring some initial belief that the accused is guilty and this is not easy to reconcile with the presumption of innocence. (Tribe 1971: 1368–1372; cf. Posner 1999: 1514, suggesting starting the trial with prior odds of 50:50, criticized by Friedman 2000. The problem of fixing the prior probability is said to disappear if we base fact-finding simply on likelihood ratios: Sullivan, 2019: 45–59.)

Fourthly, we have thus far relied for ease of illustration on highly simplified—and therefore unrealistic—examples. In real cases, there are normally multiple and dependent items of evidence and the probabilities of all possible conjunctions of these items, which are numerous, will have to be computed. These computations are far too complex to be undertaken by human beings (Callen 1982: 10–15). The impossibility of complying with the Bayesian model undermines its prescriptive value.

Fifthly, according to Haack, the Bayesian theory has it the wrong way round. What matters is not the strength of the fact-finder’s belief itself. The standard of proof should be understood instead in terms of what it is reasonable for the fact-finder to believe in the light of the evidence presented, and this is a matter of the degree to which the belief is warranted by the evidence. Evidence is legally sufficient where it warrants the contested factual claim to the degree required by law. Whether a factual claim is warranted by the evidence turns on how strongly the evidence supports the claim, on how independently secure the evidence is, and on how much of the relevant evidence is available to the fact-finder (that is, the comprehensiveness of the evidence—see further discussion in section 3.3 below). Haack is against identifying degrees of warrant with mathematical probabilities. Degrees of warrant do not conform to the axioms of the standard probability calculus. For instance, where the evidence is weak, neither p nor not- p may be warranted; in contrast, the probability of p and the probability of not- p must add up to 1. Further, where the probability of p and the probability of q are both less than 1, the probability of p and q , being the product of the probability of p and the probability of q , is less than the probability of either. On the other hand, the degree of warrant for the conjunction of p and q may be higher than the warrant for either. [ 20 ] (See Haack 2004, 2008a,b, 2012, 2014 for the legal application of her general theory of epistemology. For her general theory of epistemology, see Haack 1993: ch. 4; Haack 2009: ch. 4; Haack 2003: ch. 3.)

Sixthly, research in experimental psychology suggests that fact-finders do not evaluate pieces of evidence one-by-one and in the unidirectional manner required under the mathematical model (Amaya 2015: 114–5). A holistic approach is taken instead where the discrete items of evidence are integrated into large cognitive structures (variously labelled as “mental models”, “stories”, “narratives” and “theories of the case”), and they are assessed globally against the legal definition of the crime or civil claim that is in dispute (Pennington and Hastie 1991, 1993; Pardo 2000). The reasoning does not progress linearly from evidence to a conclusion; it is bi-directional, going forward and backward: as the fact-finder’s consideration of the evidence inclines him towards a particular verdict, his leaning towards that conclusion will often produce a revision of his original perception and his assessment of the evidence (Simon 2004, 2011).

The holistic nature of evidential reasoning as revealed by these studies has inspired alternative theories that are of a non-mathematical nature. One alternative, already mentioned, is the “explanatory” or “relative plausibility” theory advanced by Allen together with Pardo and other collaborators (Allen 1986, 1991, 1994; Pardo 2000; Allen and Leiter 2001; Allen and Jehl 2003; Pardo and Allen 2008; Allen and Pardo 2019; cf. Nance 2001, Friedman 2001). [ 21 ] They contend that fact-finders do not reason in the fashion portrayed by the Bayesian model. Instead, they engage in generating explanations or hypotheses on the available evidence by a process of abductive reasoning or drawing “inferences to the best explanation”, and these competing explanations or hypotheses are compared in the light of the evidence. [ 22 ] The comparison is not of a hypothesis with the negation of that hypothesis, where the probability of a hypothesis is compared with the probability of its negation. Instead, the comparison is of one hypothesis with one or more particular alternative hypotheses as advocated by a party or as constructed by the fact-finder himself. On this approach, the plausibility of X, the factual account of the case that establishes the accused’s guilt or defendant’s liability, is compared with the plausibility of a hypothesis Y, a specific alternative account that points to the accused’s innocence or the defendant’s non-liability, and there may be more than one such specific alternative account.

On this theory, the evidence is sufficient to satisfy the preponderance of proof standard when the best-available hypothesis that explains the evidence and the underlying events include all of the elements of the claim. Thus, in a negligence case, the best-available hypothesis would have to include a breach of duty of care by the plaintiff and causation of harm to the defendant as these are the elements that must be proved to succeed in the legal claim. For the intermediate “clear-and-convincing” standard of proof, the best-available explanation must be substantially better than the alternatives. To establish the standard of proof beyond reasonable doubt, there must be a plausible explanation of the evidence that includes all of the elements of the crime and, in addition, there must be no plausible explanation that is consistent with innocence (Pardo and Allen 2008: 238–240; Pardo 2013: 603–604).

The relative plausibility theory itself is perceived to have a number of shortcomings. [ 23 ] First, the theory portrays the assessment of plausibility as an exercise of judgment that involves employment of various criteria such as coherence, consistency, simplicity, consilience, and more. However, the theory is sketchy on the meaning of plausibility and the criteria for evaluating plausibility are left largely unanalyzed. [ 24 ]

A second criticism of the relative plausibility theory is that, despite the purported utilisation of “inference to the best explanation” reasoning, the verdict is not controlled by the best explanation. For instance, even if the prosecution’s hypothesis is better than the defence’s hypothesis, neither may be very good. In these circumstances, the court must reject the prosecution’s hypothesis even though it is the best of alternatives (Laudan 2007). One suggested mitigation of this criticism is to place some demand on the epistemic effort that the trier of fact must take (for example, by being sufficiently diligent and thorough) in constructing the set of hypotheses from which the best is to be chosen (Amaya 2009: 155).

The third criticism is targeted at holistic theories of evidential reasoning in general and not specifically at the relative plausibility theory. While it may be descriptively true that fact-finders decide verdicts by holistic evaluation of the plausibility of competing explanations, hypotheses, narratives or factual theories that are generated from the evidence, such forms of reasoning may conceal bias and prejudice that stand greater chances of exposure under a systematic approach such as Bayesian analysis (Twining 2006: 319; Simon 2004, 2011; Griffin 2013). A hypothesis constructed by the fact-finder may be shaped subconsciously by a prejudicial generalisation or background belief about the accused based on a certain feature, say, his race or sexual history. Individuating this feature and subjecting it to Bayesian scrutiny has the desirable effect of putting the generalisation or background belief under the spotlight and forcing the fact-finder to confront the problem of prejudice.

A third idea of evidential weight is prompted by this insight from Keynes (1921: 71):

As the relevant evidence at our disposal increases, the magnitude of the probability of the argument may either decrease or increase, according as the new knowledge strengthens the unfavourable or the favourable evidence; but something seems to have increased in either case,—we have a more substantial basis upon which to rest our conclusion. I express this by saying that an accession of new evidence increases the weight of an argument. New evidence will sometimes decrease the probability of an argument, but it will always increase its “weight”.

This idea of evidential weight has been applied by some legal scholars in assessing the sufficiency of evidence in satisfying legal standards of proof. [ 25 ] At its simplest, we may think of weight in the context of legal fact-finding as the amount of evidence before the court. Weight is distinguishable from probability. The weight of evidence may be high and the mathematical probability low, as in the situation where the prosecution adduces a great deal of evidence tending to incriminate the accused but the defence has an unshakeable alibi (Cohen 1986: 641). Conversely, the state of evidence adduced in a case might establish a sufficient degree of probability—high enough to cross the supposed threshold of proof on the mathematical conception of the standard of proof—and yet lack adequate weight. In the much-discussed gate-crasher’s paradox, the only available evidence shows that the defendant was one of a thousand spectators at a rodeo show and that only four hundred and ninety nine tickets were issued. The defendant is sued by the show organiser for gate-crashing. The mathematical probability that the defendant was a gate-crasher is 0.501 and this meets the probabilistic threshold for civil liability. But, according to the negation principle of mathematical probability, there is probability of 0.499 that the defendant did pay for his entrance. In these circumstances, it is intuitively unjust to find him liable (Cohen 1977: 75). A possible explanation for not finding him liable is that the evidence is too flimsy or of insufficient weight.

Proponents of the mathematical conception of the standard of proof have stood their ground even while acknowledging that weight has a role to play in the Bayesian analysis of probative value and the sufficiency of evidence. If a party does not produce relevant evidence that is in his possession, resulting in the court facing an evidential deficiency, it may draw an adverse inference against him when computing the posterior probability (Kaye 1986b: 667; Friedman 1997). One criticism of this approach is that, in the absence of information about the missing evidence, the drawing of the adverse inference is open to the objection of arbitrariness (Nance 2008: 274). A further objection is that the management of parties’ conduct relating to evidence preservation and presentation should be left to judges and not to the jury. What a judge may do to optimize evidential weight is to impose a burden of producing evidence on a party and to make the party suffer an adverse finding of fact if he fails to produce the evidence. This will serve as an incentive for the party to act in a manner that promotes the interest in evidential completeness (Nance 2008, 2010, 2016).

Cohen suggests that the standard of proof should be conceived entirely as a matter of evidential weight which, on his theory, is a matter of the number of tests or challenges to which a factual hypothesis is subjected to in court. He offers an account of legal fact-finding in terms of an account of inductive probability that was inspired by the work of writers such as Francis Bacon and J.S. Mill. Inductive probability operates differently from the classical calculus of probability. It is based on inductive support for the common-sense generalisation that licences the drawing of the relevant inference. Inductive support for a generalisation is graded according to the number of tests that it has passed, or, putting this in another way, by the degree of its resistance to falsification by relevant variables. The inductive probability of an argument is equal to the reliability grade of the inductive support for the generalisation which covers the argument.

Proof beyond reasonable doubt represents the maximum level of inductive probability. The prosecution may try to persuade the court to infer that the accused was guilty of burglary by producing evidence to establish that he was found in the vicinity of the victim’s house late at night with the stolen object on him. This inference is licensed by the generalisation that normally if a stranger is found immediately after a burglary in possession of the stolen object, he intentionally removed it himself. The defence may try to defeat the inference by showing that the generalization does not apply in the particular case, for example, by presenting evidence to show that the accused had found the object on the street. The prosecution’s hypothesis is now challenged or put to the test. As a counter-move, it may produce evidence to establish that the object could not have been lying in the street as alleged. If the generalisations on which the prosecution’s case rest survive challenges by the defence at every possible point, then guilt is proved beyond reasonable doubt. [ 26 ] The same reasoning structure applies in the civil context except that in a civil case, the plaintiff succeeds in proof on the preponderance of evidence so long as the conclusion to be proved by him is more inductively probable than its negation. (Cohen 1977, 1986; cf. Schum 1979.) [ 27 ]

Cohen’s theory seems to require that each test to which a hypothesis is put can be unequivocally and objectively resolved. But usually this is not the case. In our example, we may not be entirely convinced that the accused found or did not find the object on the street, and our evaluation would involve the exercise of judgment that is no less subjective as the sort of judgments required when applying the standard probabilistic conception of proof (Nance 2008: 275–6; Schum 1994: 261).

  • Abimbola, A., 2001, “Abductive Reasoning in Law: Taxonomy and Inference to the Best Explanation”, Cardozo Law Review , 22: 1683–1689.
  • Aitken, C., P. Roberts, and G. Jackson, 2010, Fundamentals of Probability and Statistical Evidence in Criminal Proceedings: Guidance for Judges, Lawyers, Forensic Scientists and Expert Witnessess , London: Royal Statistical Society. [ Aitken, Roberts, and Jackson 2010 available online ]
  • Allen, R., 1986, “A Reconceptualization of Civil Trials”, Boston University Law Review , 66: 401–437.
  • –––, 1991, “The Nature of Juridical Proof”, Cardozo Law Review , 13: 373–422.
  • –––, 1992, “The Myth of Conditional Relevancy”, Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review , 25: 871–884.
  • –––, 1994, “Factual Ambiguity and a Theory of Evidence”, Northwestern University Law Review , 88: 604–640.
  • –––, 2020, “Naturalized Epistemology and the Law of Evidence Revisited”, Quaestio Facti: International Journal on Evidential Reasoning , 2: 1–32.
  • Allen, R. and S. Jehl, 2003, “Burdens of Persuasion in Civil Cases: Algorithms v. Explanations”, Michigan State Law Review , 4: 893–944.
  • Allen, R. and B. Leiter, 2001, “Naturalized Epistemology and the Law of Evidence”, Virginia Law Review , 87: 1491–1550.
  • Allen, R. and M. Pardo, 2007a, “The Problematic Value of Mathematical Models of Evidence”, Journal of Legal Studies , 36: 107–140.
  • –––, 2007b, “Probability, Explanation and Inference: a Reply”, International Journal of Evidence and Proof , 11: 307–317.
  • –––, 2019, “Relative Plausibility and its Critics”, International Journal of Evidence and Proof , 23: 5–59.
  • Allen, R. and P. Roberts (eds.), 2007, International Journal of Evidence and Proof (Special Issue on the Reference Class Problem) , vol. 11, no.4.
  • Allen, R. and A. Stein, 2013, “Evidence, Probability and the Burden of Proof”, Arizona Law Review , 55: 557–602.
  • Amaya, A., 2008, “Justification, Coherence, and Epistemic Responsibility in Legal Fact-finding”, Episteme , 5: 306–319.
  • –––, 2009, “Inference to the Best Explanation”, in Legal Evidence and Proof: Statistics, Stories and Logic , H. Kaptein, H. Prakken, and B. Verheij (eds.), Burlington: Ashgate, pp. 135–159.
  • –––, 2011, “Legal Justification by Optimal Coherence”, Ratio Juris , 24: 304–329.
  • –––, 2013, “Coherence, Evidence, and Legal Proof”, Legal Theory , 19: 1–43.
  • –––, 2015, The Tapestry of Reason: An Inquiry into the Nature of Coherence and its Role in Legal Argument , Oxford: Hart and Portland.
  • Anderson, T., D. Schum, and W. Twining, 2009, Analysis of Evidence , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3 rd edition.
  • Ball, V., 1980, “The Myth of Conditional Relevancy”, Georgia Law Review , 14: 435–469.
  • Bartels, R., 1981, “Punishment and the Burden of Proof in Criminal Cases: A Modest Proposal”, Iowa Law Review , 66: 899–930.
  • Beltrán, J., 2006, “Legal Proof and Fact Finders’ Beliefs”, Legal Theory , 12: 293–314.
  • Bentham, J., 1825, A Treatise on Judicial Evidence , M. Dumont (ed.), London: Paget.
  • –––, 1827, Rationale of Judicial Evidence, Specially Applied to English Practice , J. Mill (ed.), London: Hunt and Clarke.
  • Blackstone, W., 1770, Commentaries on the Laws of England , vol. 4, Dublin.
  • Blome-Tillmann, M., 2017, “‘More Likely Than Not’ – Knowledge First and the Role of Bare Statistical Evidence in Courts of Law”, in Knowledge First: Approaches in Epistemology and Mind , J. Carter, E. Gordon, and B. Jarvis (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 278–292.
  • Buchak, L., 2014, “Belief, Credence, and Norms”, Philosophical Studies , 169: 285–311.
  • Callen, C., 1982, “Notes on a Grand Illusion: Some Limits on the Use of Bayesian Theory in Evidence Law”, Indiana Law Journal , 57: 1–44.
  • Cheng, E., 2009, “A Practical Solution to the Reference Class Problem”, Columbia Law Review , 109: 2081–2105.
  • –––, 2013, “Reconceptualising the Burden of Proof”, Yale Law Journal , 122: 1254–1279.
  • Cohen, L., 1977, The Probable and the Provable , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1986, “The Role of Evidential Weight in Criminal Proof”, Boston University Law Review , 66: 635–649.
  • –––, 1991, “Should a Jury Say What It Believes or What It Accepts?”, Cardozo Law Review , 13: 465–483.
  • –––, 1992, An Essay on Belief and Acceptance , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Colyvan, M., H. Regan, and S. Ferson, 2001, “Is it a Crime to Belong to a Reference Class?”, Journal of Political Philosophy , 9: 168–181.
  • Cullison, A., 1969, “Probability Analysis of Judicial Fact-finding: A Preliminary Outline of the Subjective Approach”, Toledo Law Review , 1: 538–598.
  • Damaška, M., 1973, “Evidentiary Barriers to Conviction and Two Models of Criminal Procedure: A Comparative Study”, University of Pennsylvania Law Review , 121: 506–589.
  • –––, 1975, “Presentation of Evidence and Factfinding Precision”, University of Pennsylvania Law Review , 123: 1083–1105.
  • –––, 1992, “Of Hearsay and Its Analogues”, Minnesota Law Review , 76: 425–458.
  • –––, 1994, “Propensity Evidence in Continental Legal Systems”, Chicago Kent Law Review , 70: 55–67.
  • –––, 1997, Evidence Law Adrift , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • –––, 2006, “The Jury and the Law of Evidence: Real and Imagined Interconnections”, Law, Probability and Risk , 5: 255–265.
  • –––, 2019, Evaluation of Evidence: Pre-modern and Modern Approaches , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Davis, D. and W. Follette, 2002, “Rethinking the Probative Value of Evidence: Base Rates, Intuitive Profiling and the ‘ Post diction’ of Behavior”, Law and Human Behavior , 26: 133–158.
  • –––, 2003, “Toward an Empirical Approach to Evidentiary Ruling”, 27 Law and Human Behavior , 27: 661–684.
  • Dawid, P., W. Twining, and M. Vasilaki, 2011, Evidence, Inference and Enquiry , Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy.
  • Duff, A., et al., 2007, The Trial on Trial (Volume 3: Towards a Normative Theory of the Criminal Trial), Oxford: Hart.
  • Dworkin, R., 1981, “Principle, Policy, Procedure”, in Crime, Proof and Punishment, Essays in Memory of Sir Rupert Cross , C. Tapper (ed.), London: Butterworths, pp. 193–225.
  • Eggleston, R., 1983, Evidence, Probability and Proof , London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 2 nd edition.
  • Enoch, D., L. Spectre, and T. Fisher, 2012, “Statistical Evidence, Sensitivity, and the Legal Value of Knowledge”, Philosophy and Public Affairs , 40(3): 197–224.
  • Enoch, D. and L. Spectre, 2019, “Sensitivity, Safety, and the Law: a Reply to Pardo”, Legal Theory , 25: 178–199.
  • Enoch, D. and T. Fisher, 2015, “Sense and ‘Sensitivity’: Epistemic and Instrumental Approaches to Statistical Evidence”, Stanford Law Review , 67: 557–611.
  • Finkelstein, M. and B. Levin, 2003, “On the Probative Value of Evidence from a Screening Search”, Jurimetrics , 43: 265–290.
  • Franklin, J., 2010, “Feature Selection Methods for Solving the Reference Class Problem: Comment on Edward K. Cheng, ‘A Practical Solution to the Reference Class Problem’”, Columbia Law Review Sidebar , 110: 12–23.
  • –––, 2011, “The Objective Bayesian Conceptualisation of Proof and Reference Class Problems”, Sydney Law Review , 33: 545–561.
  • –––, 2012, “Discussion Paper: How much of Commonsense and Legal Reasoning is Formalizable? A Review of Conceptual Obstacles”, Law, Probability and Risk , 11: 225–245.
  • Friedman, R., 1986, “A Close Look at Probative Value”, Boston University Law Review , 33: 733–759.
  • –––, 1994, “Conditional Probative Value: Neoclassicism Without Myth”, Michigan Law Review , 93:439–484.
  • –––, 1997, “Dealing with Evidential Deficiency”, Cardozo Law Review , 18: 1961–1986.
  • –––, 2000, “A Presumption of Innocence, Not of Even Odds”, Stanford Law Review , 52:873–887.
  • –––, 2001, “‘E’ is for Eclectic: Multiple Perspectives on Evidence”, Virginia Law Review , 87: 2029–2054.
  • Friedman, R. and R. Park, 2003, “Sometimes What Everybody Thinks They Know Is True”, Law and Human Behavior , 27: 629–644.
  • Gardiner, G., 2019a, “The Reasonable and the Relevant: Legal Standards of Proof”, Philosophy and Public Affairs , 47: 288–318.
  • –––, 2019b, “Legal Burdens of Proof and Statistical Evidence”, in The Routledge Handbook of Applied Epistemology , in D. Coady and J. Chase (eds.), Oxford: Routledge.
  • –––, 2020, “Profiling and Proof: Are Statistics Safe?”, Philosophy , 95: 161–183.
  • –––, forthcoming, “Legal Evidence and Knowledge”, in M. Lasonen-Aarnio and C. Littlejohn (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Evidence , Oxford: Routledge.
  • Goldman, A., 1999, Knowledge in a Social World , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2002, “Quasi-Objective Bayesianism and Legal Evidence”, Jurimetrics , 42: 237–260.
  • –––, 2005, “Legal Evidence” in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory , M. Goldring and W. Edmundson (eds.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 163–175.
  • Griffin, L., 2013, “Narrative, Truth, and Trial”, Georgetown Law Journal , 101: 281–335.
  • Haack, S., 1993, Evidence and Inquiry, Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2003, “Clues to the Puzzle of Scientific Evidence: a More-So Story” in S. Haack, Defending Science: Within Reasons , New York: Prometheus, pp. 57–91.
  • –––, 2004, “Epistemology Legalized: or, Truth, Justice and the American Way”, American Journal of Jurisprudence , 49: 43–61.
  • –––, 2008a, “Proving Causation: The Holism of Warrant and the Atomism of Daubert ”, Journal of Health and Biomedical Law , 4: 253–289.
  • –––, 2008b, “Warrant, Causation, and the Atomism of Evidence Law”, Episteme , 5: 253–266.
  • –––, 2009, Evidence and Inquiry: A Pragmatist Reconstruction of Epistemology , New York: Prometheus (expanded edition of Haack 1993).
  • –––, 2012, “The Embedded Epistemologist: Dispatches from the Legal Front”, Ratio Juris , 25: 206–235.
  • –––, 2014, “Legal Probabilism: An Epistemological Dissent” in S. Haack, Evidence Matters: Science, Proof, and Truth in the Law , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 47–77.
  • Ho, H.L., 2003–2004, “The Legitimacy of Medieval Proof”, Journal of Law and Religion , 19: 259–298.
  • –––, 2008, A Philosophy of Evidence Law: Justice in the Search for Truth , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Jackson, J. and S. Doran, 2010, “Evidence” in A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory , 2 nd edition, D. Patterson (ed.), Malden, MA : Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 177–187.
  • James, G., 1941, “Relevancy, Probability and the Law”, California Law Review , 29: 689–705.
  • Josephson, J., 2001, “On the Proof Dynamics of Inference to the Best Explanation”, Cardozo Law Review 22: 1621–1643.
  • Kaplan, J., 1968, “Decision Theory and the Fact-finding Process”, Stanford Law Review , 20: 1065–1092.
  • Kaplow, L., 2012, “Burden of Proof”, Yale Law Journal , 121: 738–859.
  • Kaye, D., 1986a, “Quantifying Probative Value”, Boston University Law Review , 66: 761–766.
  • –––, 1986b, “Do We Need a Calculus of Weight to Understand Proof Beyond Reasonable Doubt?”, Boston University Law Review , 66: 657–672.
  • Kaye, D. and J. Koehler, 2003, “The Misquantification of Probative Value”, Law and Human Behavior , 27: 645–659.
  • Keynes, J., 1921, A Treatise on Probability , London: MacMillan.
  • Laudan, L., 2006, Truth, Error, and Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal Epistemology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2007, “Strange Bedfellows: Inference to the Best Explanation and the Criminal Standard of Proof”, International Journal of Evidence and Proof , 11: 292–306.
  • Laudan, L. and H. Saunders, 2009, “Re-Thinking the Criminal Standard of Proof: Seeking Consensus about the Utilities of Trial Outcomes”, International Commentary on Evidence , 7(2), article 1 (online journal).
  • Lawson, G., 2017, Evidence of the Law: Proving Legal Claims , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Leiter, B., 1997, “Why Even Good Philosophy of Science Would Not Make for Good Philosophy of Evidence”, Brigham Young University Law Review , 803–819.
  • Lempert, R., 1977, “Modeling Relevance”, Michigan Law Review , 75: 1021–1057.
  • Lillquist, E., 2002, “Recasting Reasonable Doubt: Decision Theory and the Virtues of Variability”, University of California Davies Law Review , 36: 85–197.
  • Littlejohn, C., 2020, “Truth, Knowledge, and the Standard of Proof in Criminal Law”, Synthese , 197: 5253–5286.
  • –––, 2021, “Justified Belief and Just Conviction” in The Social Epistemology of Legal Trials , Z. Hoskins and J. Robson (eds.), New York: Routledge, pp. 106–123.
  • MacCrimmon, M., 2001–2002, “What is ‘Common’ about Common Sense?: Cautionary Tales for Travelers Crossing Disciplinary Boundaries”, Cardozo Law Review , 22: 1433–1460.
  • McCormick, C., 2013, McCormick on Evidence , K. Broun et al. (eds.), St. Paul, Minnesota: Thomson Reuters/WestLaw, 7 th edition.
  • McNamara, P., 1986, “The Canons of Evidence: Rules of Exclusion or Rules of Use?”, Adelaide Law Review , 10: 341–364.
  • Mnookin, J., 2006, “Bifurcation and the Law of Evidence”, University of Pennsylvania Law Review PENNumbra , 155: 134–145.
  • –––, 2013, “Atomism, Holism, and the Judicial Assessment of Evidence”, University of California at Los Angeles Law Review , 60: 1524–1585.
  • Montrose, J., 1954, “Basic Concepts of the Law of Evidence”, Law Quarterly Review , 70: 527–555.
  • Morgan, E., 1929, “Functions of Judge and Jury in the Determination of Preliminary Questions of Fact”, Harvard Law Review , 43: 165–191.
  • –––, 1936–37, “The Jury and the Exclusionary Rules of Evidence”, University of Chicago Law Review , 4: 247–258.
  • Moss, S., 2018, Probabilistic Knowledge , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, forthcoming, “Knowledge and Legal Proof” in Oxford Studies in Epistemology (Volume 7), T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nance, D., 1988, “The Best Evidence Principle”, Iowa Law Review , 73: 227–297.
  • –––, 1990, “Conditional Relevance Reinterpreted”, Boston University Law Review , 70: 447–507.
  • –––, 2001, “Naturalized Epistemology and the Critique of Evidence Theory”, Virginia Law Review , 87: 1551–1618.
  • –––, 2007a, “Allocating the Risk of Error”, Legal Theory , 13: 129–164.
  • –––, 2007b, “The Reference Class Problem and Mathematical Models of Inference”, International Journal of Evidence and Proof , 11: 259–273.
  • –––, 2008, “The Weights of Evidence”, Episteme , 5: 267–281.
  • –––, 2010, “Adverse Inferences About Adverse Inferences: Restructuring Juridical Roles for Responding to Evidence Tampering by Parties to Litigation”, Boston University Law Review , 90: 1089–1146.
  • –––, 2016, The Burdens of Proof – Discriminatory Power, Weight of Evidence and Tenacity of Belief , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nance, D. and S. Morris, 2002, “An Empirical Assessment of Presentation Formats for Trace Evidence with a Relatively Large and Quantifiable Random Match Probability”, Jurimetrics , 42: 403–447.
  • Nelkin, D., 2021, “Rational Belief and Statistical Evidence — Blame, Bias and the Law” in Lotteries, Knowledge, and Rational Belief , I. Douven (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 6–27.
  • Nesson, C., 1979, “Reasonable Doubt and Permissive Inferences: the Value of Complexity”, Harvard Law Review , 92: 1187–1225.
  • –––, 1985, “The Evidence or the Event? On Judicial Proof and the Acceptability of Verdicts”, Harvard Law Review , 98: 1357–1392.
  • Pardo, M., 2000, “Juridical Proof, Evidence, and Pragmatic Meaning: Toward Evidentiary Holism”, Northwestern University Law Review , 95: 399–442.
  • –––, 2005, “The Field of Evidence and the Field of Knowledge”, Law and Philosophy , 24: 321–392.
  • –––, 2007, “The Political Morality of Evidence Law”, International Commentary on Evidence , 5(2), essay 1 (online journal).
  • –––, 2010, “The Gettier Problem and Legal Proof”, Legal Theory , 16: 37–57.
  • –––, 2013, “The Nature and Purpose of Evidence Theory”, Vanderbilt Law Review , 66: 547–613.
  • –––, 2018, “Safety vs. Sensitivity: Possible Worlds and the Law of Evidence”, Legal Theory , 24: 50–75.
  • Pardo, M.S. and R.J. Allen, 2008, “Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation”, Law and Philosophy , 27: 223–268.
  • Park, R., 1986, “The Hearsay Rule and the Stability of Verdicts: A Response to Professor Nesson”, Minnesota Law Review , 70: 1057–1072.
  • Park, R. et al., 2010, “Bayes Wars Redivivus: An Exchange”, International Commentary on Evidence , 8(1), article 1 (online journal).
  • Pattenden, R., 1996–7, “The Discretionary Exclusion of Relevant Evidence in English Civil Proceedings”, International Journal of Evidence and Proof , 1: 361–385.
  • Pennington, N. and R. Hastie, 1991, “A Cognitive Model of Juror Decision Making: The Story Model”, Cardozo Law Review , 13: 519–557.
  • –––, 1993, “The Story Model for Juror Decision-making” in Inside the Juror: The Psychology of Juror Decision Making , R. Hastie (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 192–221.
  • Picinali, F., 2013, “Two Meanings of ‘Reasonableness’: Dispelling the ‘Floating’ Reasonable Doubt”, Modern Law Review , 76: 845–875.
  • Pollock, F., 1876, “Stephen’s Digest of the Law of Evidence”, The Forthnightly Review , 20: 383–394.
  • –––, 1899, “Review of A Preliminary Treatise on Evidence at the Common Law by James Bradley Thayer, Law Quarterly Review ”, 15: 86–87.
  • Posner, R., 1999, “An Economic Approach to the Law of Evidence”, Stanford Law Review , 51: 1477–1546.
  • Pritchard, D., 2015, “Risk”, Metaphilosophy , 46: 436–461.
  • –––, 2018, “Legal Risk, Legal Evidence and the Arithmetic of Criminal Justice”, Jurisprudence , 9: 108–119.
  • Rescher, N. and C. Joynt, 1959, “Evidence in History and in the Law”, Journal of Philosophy , 56: 561–578.
  • Redmayne, M., 1996, “Standards of Proof in Civil Litigation”, Modern Law Review , 62: 167–195.
  • –––, 2006, “The Structure of Evidence Law”, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , 26: 805–822.
  • –––, 2008, “Exploring the Proof Paradoxes”, Legal Theory , 14: 281–309.
  • Ribeiro, G., 2019, “The Case for Varying Standards of Proof”, San Diego Law Review , 56: 161–219.
  • Roberts, P. and C. Aitken, 2014, The Logic of Forensic Proof: Inferential Reasoning in Criminal Evidence and Forensic Science , London: Royal Statistical Society. [ Roberts and Aitken 2014 available online ]
  • Roberts, P. and A. Zuckerman, 2010, Criminal Evidence , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 nd edition.
  • Robertson, B. and G. Vignaux, 1995, Interpreting Evidence: Evaluating Forensic Science in the Courtroom , Chichester: John Wiley.
  • Schauer, F., 2006, “On the Supposed Jury-Dependence of Evidence Law”, University of Pennsylvania Law Review , 155: 165–202.
  • –––, 2008, “In Defense of Rule-Based Evidence Law: And Epistemology Too”, Episteme 5: 295–305.
  • Schum, D., 1979, “A Review of a Case Against Blaise Pascal and His Heirs”, Michigan Law Review , 77:446–483.
  • –––, 1994, The Evidential Foundations of Probabilistic Reasoning , New York: John Wiley & Sons.
  • –––, 1998, “Legal Evidence and Inference” in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy , E. Craig (ed.), London: Routledge, pp. 500–506.
  • –––, 2001, “Species of Abductive Reasoning in Fact Investigation in Law”, Cardozo Law Review , 22:1645–1681.
  • Simon, D., 2004, “A Third View of the Black Box: Cognitive Coherence in Legal Decision Making”, University of Chicago Law Review , 71: 511–586.
  • –––, 2011, “Limited Diagnosticity of Criminal Trials”, Vanderbilt Law Review , 64: 143–223.
  • Smith, M., 2018, “When Does Evidence Suffice for Conviction?”, Mind , 127: 1193–1218.
  • Stein, A., 2005, Foundations of Evidence Law , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stephen, J., 1872, The Indian Evidence Act, with an Introduction on the Principles of Judicial Evidence , Calcutta: Thacker, Spink & Co.
  • –––, 1886, A Digest of the Law of Evidence , London: William Clowes & Sons, 5 th edition.
  • Sullivan, S., 2019, “A Likelihood Story: The Theory of Legal Fact-finding”, University of Colorado Law Review , 90: 1–66.
  • Thayer, J., 1898, A Preliminary Treatise on Evidence at the Common Law , Boston: Little, Brown & Co.
  • Thomson, J., 1986, “Liability and Individualized Evidence”, Law and Contemporary Problems , 49(3): 199–219.
  • Tillers, P., 2005, “If Wishes were Horses: Discursive Comments on Attempts to Prevent Individuals from Being Unfairly Burdened by their Reference Classes”, Law, Probability and Risk , 4: 33–39.
  • –––, 2008, “Are there Universal Principles or Forms of Evidential Inference? Of Inference Networks and Onto-Epistemology” in Crime, Procedure and Evidence in a Comparative and International Context , J. Jackson, M. Langer, and P. Tillers (eds.), Oxford: Hart, pp. 179–198.
  • Tillers, P. and E. Green (eds.), 1988, Probability and Inference in the Law of Evidence: The Limits and Uses of Bayesianism , Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Trautman, H., 1952, “Logical or Legal Relevancy: A Conflict in Theory”, Vanderbilt Law Review , 5: 385–413.
  • Tribe, L., 1971, “Trial by Mathematics: Precision and Ritual in the Legal Process”, Harvard Law Review , 84: 1329–1393
  • Twining, W., 1985, Theories of Evidence: Bentham and Wigmore , London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
  • –––, 2006, Rethinking Evidence: Exploratory Essays , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2 nd edition.
  • Twining, W. and I. Hampsher-Monk, 2003, Evidence and Inference in History and Law: Interdisciplinary Dialogues , Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.
  • Whitworth, G., 1881, The Theory of Relevancy for the Purpose of Judicial Evidence , Bombay: Thacker & Co.
  • Wigmore, J., 1913, “Review of A Treatise on Facts, or the Weight and Value of Evidence by Charles C. Moore”, Illinois Law Review , 3: 477–478.
  • –––, 1935, A Students’ Textbook of the Law of Evidence , Brooklyn: Foundation Press.
  • –––, 1937, Science of Judicial Proof, as Given by Logic, Psychology, and General Experience and Illustrated in Judicial Trials , Boston: Little, Brown and Co.
  • –––, 1983a, Evidence in Trials at Common Law , vol. 1, P. Tillers (ed.), Boston: Little, Brown and Co.
  • –––, 1983b, Evidence in Trials at Common Law , vol. 1A, P. Tillers (ed.), Boston: Little, Brown and Co.
  • Wills, W., 1852, An Essay on the Principles of Circumstantial Evidence , Philadelphia: T & J W Johnson, reprint from the third London edition.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Legal Information Institute , at Cornell Law School. This site makes available the full text of the Federal Rules of Evidence with commentaries by the Advisory Committee on Rules.
  • Statistics and the Law , page at the Royal Statistical Society.

Bayes’ Theorem | epistemology | evidence | legal probabilism | probability, interpretations of

Copyright © 2021 by Hock Lai Ho < lawhohl @ nus . edu . sg >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Theories, Hypotheses, and Laws: Definitions, examples, and their roles in science

by Anthony Carpi, Ph.D., Anne E. Egger, Ph.D.

Listen to this reading

Did you know that the idea of evolution had been part of Western thought for more than 2,000 years before Charles Darwin was born? Like many theories, the theory of evolution was the result of the work of many different scientists working in different disciplines over a period of time.

A scientific theory is an explanation inferred from multiple lines of evidence for some broad aspect of the natural world and is logical, testable, and predictive.

As new evidence comes to light, or new interpretations of existing data are proposed, theories may be revised and even change; however, they are not tenuous or speculative.

A scientific hypothesis is an inferred explanation of an observation or research finding; while more exploratory in nature than a theory, it is based on existing scientific knowledge.

A scientific law is an expression of a mathematical or descriptive relationship observed in nature.

Imagine yourself shopping in a grocery store with a good friend who happens to be a chemist. Struggling to choose between the many different types of tomatoes in front of you, you pick one up, turn to your friend, and ask her if she thinks the tomato is organic . Your friend simply chuckles and replies, "Of course it's organic!" without even looking at how the fruit was grown. Why the amused reaction? Your friend is highlighting a simple difference in vocabulary. To a chemist, the term organic refers to any compound in which hydrogen is bonded to carbon. Tomatoes (like all plants) are abundant in organic compounds – thus your friend's laughter. In modern agriculture, however, organic has come to mean food items grown or raised without the use of chemical fertilizers, pesticides, or other additives.

So who is correct? You both are. Both uses of the word are correct, though they mean different things in different contexts. There are, of course, lots of words that have more than one meaning (like bat , for example), but multiple meanings can be especially confusing when two meanings convey very different ideas and are specific to one field of study.

  • Scientific theories

The term theory also has two meanings, and this double meaning often leads to confusion. In common language, the term theory generally refers to speculation or a hunch or guess. You might have a theory about why your favorite sports team isn't playing well, or who ate the last cookie from the cookie jar. But these theories do not fit the scientific use of the term. In science, a theory is a well-substantiated and comprehensive set of ideas that explains a phenomenon in nature. A scientific theory is based on large amounts of data and observations that have been collected over time. Scientific theories can be tested and refined by additional research , and they allow scientists to make predictions. Though you may be correct in your hunch, your cookie jar conjecture doesn't fit this more rigorous definition.

All scientific disciplines have well-established, fundamental theories . For example, atomic theory describes the nature of matter and is supported by multiple lines of evidence from the way substances behave and react in the world around us (see our series on Atomic Theory ). Plate tectonic theory describes the large scale movement of the outer layer of the Earth and is supported by evidence from studies about earthquakes , magnetic properties of the rocks that make up the seafloor , and the distribution of volcanoes on Earth (see our series on Plate Tectonic Theory ). The theory of evolution by natural selection , which describes the mechanism by which inherited traits that affect survivability or reproductive success can cause changes in living organisms over generations , is supported by extensive studies of DNA , fossils , and other types of scientific evidence (see our Charles Darwin series for more information). Each of these major theories guides and informs modern research in those fields, integrating a broad, comprehensive set of ideas.

So how are these fundamental theories developed, and why are they considered so well supported? Let's take a closer look at some of the data and research supporting the theory of natural selection to better see how a theory develops.

Comprehension Checkpoint

  • The development of a scientific theory: Evolution and natural selection

The theory of evolution by natural selection is sometimes maligned as Charles Darwin 's speculation on the origin of modern life forms. However, evolutionary theory is not speculation. While Darwin is rightly credited with first articulating the theory of natural selection, his ideas built on more than a century of scientific research that came before him, and are supported by over a century and a half of research since.

  • The Fixity Notion: Linnaeus

Figure 1: Cover of the 1760 edition of Systema Naturae.

Figure 1: Cover of the 1760 edition of Systema Naturae .

Research about the origins and diversity of life proliferated in the 18th and 19th centuries. Carolus Linnaeus , a Swedish botanist and the father of modern taxonomy (see our module Taxonomy I for more information), was a devout Christian who believed in the concept of Fixity of Species , an idea based on the biblical story of creation. The Fixity of Species concept said that each species is based on an ideal form that has not changed over time. In the early stages of his career, Linnaeus traveled extensively and collected data on the structural similarities and differences between different species of plants. Noting that some very different plants had similar structures, he began to piece together his landmark work, Systema Naturae, in 1735 (Figure 1). In Systema , Linnaeus classified organisms into related groups based on similarities in their physical features. He developed a hierarchical classification system , even drawing relationships between seemingly disparate species (for example, humans, orangutans, and chimpanzees) based on the physical similarities that he observed between these organisms. Linnaeus did not explicitly discuss change in organisms or propose a reason for his hierarchy, but by grouping organisms based on physical characteristics, he suggested that species are related, unintentionally challenging the Fixity notion that each species is created in a unique, ideal form.

  • The age of Earth: Leclerc and Hutton

Also in the early 1700s, Georges-Louis Leclerc, a French naturalist, and James Hutton , a Scottish geologist, began to develop new ideas about the age of the Earth. At the time, many people thought of the Earth as 6,000 years old, based on a strict interpretation of the events detailed in the Christian Old Testament by the influential Scottish Archbishop Ussher. By observing other planets and comets in the solar system , Leclerc hypothesized that Earth began as a hot, fiery ball of molten rock, mostly consisting of iron. Using the cooling rate of iron, Leclerc calculated that Earth must therefore be at least 70,000 years old in order to have reached its present temperature.

Hutton approached the same topic from a different perspective, gathering observations of the relationships between different rock formations and the rates of modern geological processes near his home in Scotland. He recognized that the relatively slow processes of erosion and sedimentation could not create all of the exposed rock layers in only a few thousand years (see our module The Rock Cycle ). Based on his extensive collection of data (just one of his many publications ran to 2,138 pages), Hutton suggested that the Earth was far older than human history – hundreds of millions of years old.

While we now know that both Leclerc and Hutton significantly underestimated the age of the Earth (by about 4 billion years), their work shattered long-held beliefs and opened a window into research on how life can change over these very long timescales.

  • Fossil studies lead to the development of a theory of evolution: Cuvier

Figure 2: Illustration of an Indian elephant jaw and a mammoth jaw from Cuvier's 1796 paper.

Figure 2: Illustration of an Indian elephant jaw and a mammoth jaw from Cuvier's 1796 paper.

With the age of Earth now extended by Leclerc and Hutton, more researchers began to turn their attention to studying past life. Fossils are the main way to study past life forms, and several key studies on fossils helped in the development of a theory of evolution . In 1795, Georges Cuvier began to work at the National Museum in Paris as a naturalist and anatomist. Through his work, Cuvier became interested in fossils found near Paris, which some claimed were the remains of the elephants that Hannibal rode over the Alps when he invaded Rome in 218 BCE . In studying both the fossils and living species , Cuvier documented different patterns in the dental structure and number of teeth between the fossils and modern elephants (Figure 2) (Horner, 1843). Based on these data , Cuvier hypothesized that the fossil remains were not left by Hannibal, but were from a distinct species of animal that once roamed through Europe and had gone extinct thousands of years earlier: the mammoth. The concept of species extinction had been discussed by a few individuals before Cuvier, but it was in direct opposition to the Fixity of Species concept – if every organism were based on a perfectly adapted, ideal form, how could any cease to exist? That would suggest it was no longer ideal.

While his work provided critical evidence of extinction , a key component of evolution , Cuvier was highly critical of the idea that species could change over time. As a result of his extensive studies of animal anatomy, Cuvier had developed a holistic view of organisms , stating that the

number, direction, and shape of the bones that compose each part of an animal's body are always in a necessary relation to all the other parts, in such a way that ... one can infer the whole from any one of them ...

In other words, Cuvier viewed each part of an organism as a unique, essential component of the whole organism. If one part were to change, he believed, the organism could not survive. His skepticism about the ability of organisms to change led him to criticize the whole idea of evolution , and his prominence in France as a scientist played a large role in discouraging the acceptance of the idea in the scientific community.

  • Studies of invertebrates support a theory of change in species: Lamarck

Jean Baptiste Lamarck, a contemporary of Cuvier's at the National Museum in Paris, studied invertebrates like insects and worms. As Lamarck worked through the museum's large collection of invertebrates, he was impressed by the number and variety of organisms . He became convinced that organisms could, in fact, change through time, stating that

... time and favorable conditions are the two principal means which nature has employed in giving existence to all her productions. We know that for her time has no limit, and that consequently she always has it at her disposal.

This was a radical departure from both the fixity concept and Cuvier's ideas, and it built on the long timescale that geologists had recently established. Lamarck proposed that changes that occurred during an organism 's lifetime could be passed on to their offspring, suggesting, for example, that a body builder's muscles would be inherited by their children.

As it turned out, the mechanism by which Lamarck proposed that organisms change over time was wrong, and he is now often referred to disparagingly for his "inheritance of acquired characteristics" idea. Yet despite the fact that some of his ideas were discredited, Lamarck established a support for evolutionary theory that others would build on and improve.

  • Rock layers as evidence for evolution: Smith

In the early 1800s, a British geologist and canal surveyor named William Smith added another component to the accumulating evidence for evolution . Smith observed that rock layers exposed in different parts of England bore similarities to one another: These layers (or strata) were arranged in a predictable order, and each layer contained distinct groups of fossils . From this series of observations , he developed a hypothesis that specific groups of animals followed one another in a definite sequence through Earth's history, and this sequence could be seen in the rock layers. Smith's hypothesis was based on his knowledge of geological principles , including the Law of Superposition.

The Law of Superposition states that sediments are deposited in a time sequence, with the oldest sediments deposited first, or at the bottom, and newer layers deposited on top. The concept was first expressed by the Persian scientist Avicenna in the 11th century, but was popularized by the Danish scientist Nicolas Steno in the 17th century. Note that the law does not state how sediments are deposited; it simply describes the relationship between the ages of deposited sediments.

Figure 3: Engraving from William Smith's 1815 monograph on identifying strata by fossils.

Figure 3: Engraving from William Smith's 1815 monograph on identifying strata by fossils.

Smith backed up his hypothesis with extensive drawings of fossils uncovered during his research (Figure 3), thus allowing other scientists to confirm or dispute his findings. His hypothesis has, in fact, been confirmed by many other scientists and has come to be referred to as the Law of Faunal Succession. His work was critical to the formation of evolutionary theory as it not only confirmed Cuvier's work that organisms have gone extinct , but it also showed that the appearance of life does not date to the birth of the planet. Instead, the fossil record preserves a timeline of the appearance and disappearance of different organisms in the past, and in doing so offers evidence for change in organisms over time.

  • The theory of evolution by natural selection: Darwin and Wallace

It was into this world that Charles Darwin entered: Linnaeus had developed a taxonomy of organisms based on their physical relationships, Leclerc and Hutton demonstrated that there was sufficient time in Earth's history for organisms to change, Cuvier showed that species of organisms have gone extinct , Lamarck proposed that organisms change over time, and Smith established a timeline of the appearance and disappearance of different organisms in the geological record .

Figure 4: Title page of the 1859 Murray edition of the Origin of Species by Charles Darwin.

Figure 4: Title page of the 1859 Murray edition of the Origin of Species by Charles Darwin.

Charles Darwin collected data during his work as a naturalist on the HMS Beagle starting in 1831. He took extensive notes on the geology of the places he visited; he made a major find of fossils of extinct animals in Patagonia and identified an extinct giant ground sloth named Megatherium . He experienced an earthquake in Chile that stranded beds of living mussels above water, where they would be preserved for years to come.

Perhaps most famously, he conducted extensive studies of animals on the Galápagos Islands, noting subtle differences in species of mockingbird, tortoise, and finch that were isolated on different islands with different environmental conditions. These subtle differences made the animals highly adapted to their environments .

This broad spectrum of data led Darwin to propose an idea about how organisms change "by means of natural selection" (Figure 4). But this idea was not based only on his work, it was also based on the accumulation of evidence and ideas of many others before him. Because his proposal encompassed and explained many different lines of evidence and previous work, they formed the basis of a new and robust scientific theory regarding change in organisms – the theory of evolution by natural selection .

Darwin's ideas were grounded in evidence and data so compelling that if he had not conceived them, someone else would have. In fact, someone else did. Between 1858 and 1859, Alfred Russel Wallace , a British naturalist, wrote a series of letters to Darwin that independently proposed natural selection as the means for evolutionary change. The letters were presented to the Linnean Society of London, a prominent scientific society at the time (see our module on Scientific Institutions and Societies ). This long chain of research highlights that theories are not just the work of one individual. At the same time, however, it often takes the insight and creativity of individuals to put together all of the pieces and propose a new theory . Both Darwin and Wallace were experienced naturalists who were familiar with the work of others. While all of the work leading up to 1830 contributed to the theory of evolution , Darwin's and Wallace's theory changed the way that future research was focused by presenting a comprehensive, well-substantiated set of ideas, thus becoming a fundamental theory of biological research.

  • Expanding, testing, and refining scientific theories
  • Genetics and evolution: Mendel and Dobzhansky

Since Darwin and Wallace first published their ideas, extensive research has tested and expanded the theory of evolution by natural selection . Darwin had no concept of genes or DNA or the mechanism by which characteristics were inherited within a species . A contemporary of Darwin's, the Austrian monk Gregor Mendel , first presented his own landmark study, Experiments in Plant Hybridization, in 1865 in which he provided the basic patterns of genetic inheritance , describing which characteristics (and evolutionary changes) can be passed on in organisms (see our Genetics I module for more information). Still, it wasn't until much later that a "gene" was defined as the heritable unit.

In 1937, the Ukrainian born geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky published Genetics and the Origin of Species , a seminal work in which he described genes themselves and demonstrated that it is through mutations in genes that change occurs. The work defined evolution as "a change in the frequency of an allele within a gene pool" ( Dobzhansky, 1982 ). These studies and others in the field of genetics have added to Darwin's work, expanding the scope of the theory .

  • Evolution under a microscope: Lenski

More recently, Dr. Richard Lenski, a scientist at Michigan State University, isolated a single Escherichia coli bacterium in 1989 as the first step of the longest running experimental test of evolutionary theory to date – a true test meant to replicate evolution and natural selection in the lab.

After the single microbe had multiplied, Lenski isolated the offspring into 12 different strains , each in their own glucose-supplied culture, predicting that the genetic make-up of each strain would change over time to become more adapted to their specific culture as predicted by evolutionary theory . These 12 lines have been nurtured for over 40,000 bacterial generations (luckily bacterial generations are much shorter than human generations) and exposed to different selective pressures such as heat , cold, antibiotics, and infection with other microorganisms. Lenski and colleagues have studied dozens of aspects of evolutionary theory with these genetically isolated populations . In 1999, they published a paper that demonstrated that random genetic mutations were common within the populations and highly diverse across different individual bacteria . However, "pivotal" mutations that are associated with beneficial changes in the group are shared by all descendants in a population and are much rarer than random mutations, as predicted by the theory of evolution by natural selection (Papadopoulos et al., 1999).

  • Punctuated equilibrium: Gould and Eldredge

While established scientific theories like evolution have a wealth of research and evidence supporting them, this does not mean that they cannot be refined as new information or new perspectives on existing data become available. For example, in 1972, biologist Stephen Jay Gould and paleontologist Niles Eldredge took a fresh look at the existing data regarding the timing by which evolutionary change takes place. Gould and Eldredge did not set out to challenge the theory of evolution; rather they used it as a guiding principle and asked more specific questions to add detail and nuance to the theory. This is true of all theories in science: they provide a framework for additional research. At the time, many biologists viewed evolution as occurring gradually, causing small incremental changes in organisms at a relatively steady rate. The idea is referred to as phyletic gradualism , and is rooted in the geological concept of uniformitarianism . After reexamining the available data, Gould and Eldredge came to a different explanation, suggesting that evolution consists of long periods of stability that are punctuated by occasional instances of dramatic change – a process they called punctuated equilibrium .

Like Darwin before them, their proposal is rooted in evidence and research on evolutionary change, and has been supported by multiple lines of evidence. In fact, punctuated equilibrium is now considered its own theory in evolutionary biology. Punctuated equilibrium is not as broad of a theory as natural selection . In science, some theories are broad and overarching of many concepts, such as the theory of evolution by natural selection; others focus on concepts at a smaller, or more targeted, scale such as punctuated equilibrium. And punctuated equilibrium does not challenge or weaken the concept of natural selection; rather, it represents a change in our understanding of the timing by which change occurs in organisms , and a theory within a theory. The theory of evolution by natural selection now includes both gradualism and punctuated equilibrium to describe the rate at which change proceeds.

  • Hypotheses and laws: Other scientific concepts

One of the challenges in understanding scientific terms like theory is that there is not a precise definition even within the scientific community. Some scientists debate over whether certain proposals merit designation as a hypothesis or theory , and others mistakenly use the terms interchangeably. But there are differences in these terms. A hypothesis is a proposed explanation for an observable phenomenon. Hypotheses , just like theories , are based on observations from research . For example, LeClerc did not hypothesize that Earth had cooled from a molten ball of iron as a random guess; rather, he developed this hypothesis based on his observations of information from meteorites.

A scientist often proposes a hypothesis before research confirms it as a way of predicting the outcome of study to help better define the parameters of the research. LeClerc's hypothesis allowed him to use known parameters (the cooling rate of iron) to do additional work. A key component of a formal scientific hypothesis is that it is testable and falsifiable. For example, when Richard Lenski first isolated his 12 strains of bacteria , he likely hypothesized that random mutations would cause differences to appear within a period of time in the different strains of bacteria. But when a hypothesis is generated in science, a scientist will also make an alternative hypothesis , an explanation that explains a study if the data do not support the original hypothesis. If the different strains of bacteria in Lenski's work did not diverge over the indicated period of time, perhaps the rate of mutation was slower than first thought.

So you might ask, if theories are so well supported, do they eventually become laws? The answer is no – not because they aren't well-supported, but because theories and laws are two very different things. Laws describe phenomena, often mathematically. Theories, however, explain phenomena. For example, in 1687 Isaac Newton proposed a Theory of Gravitation, describing gravity as a force of attraction between two objects. As part of this theory, Newton developed a Law of Universal Gravitation that explains how this force operates. This law states that the force of gravity between two objects is inversely proportional to the square of the distance between those objects. Newton 's Law does not explain why this is true, but it describes how gravity functions (see our Gravity: Newtonian Relationships module for more detail). In 1916, Albert Einstein developed his theory of general relativity to explain the mechanism by which gravity has its effect. Einstein's work challenges Newton's theory, and has been found after extensive testing and research to more accurately describe the phenomenon of gravity. While Einstein's work has replaced Newton's as the dominant explanation of gravity in modern science, Newton's Law of Universal Gravitation is still used as it reasonably (and more simply) describes the force of gravity under many conditions. Similarly, the Law of Faunal Succession developed by William Smith does not explain why organisms follow each other in distinct, predictable ways in the rock layers, but it accurately describes the phenomenon.

Theories, hypotheses , and laws drive scientific progress

Theories, hypotheses , and laws are not simply important components of science, they drive scientific progress. For example, evolutionary biology now stands as a distinct field of science that focuses on the origins and descent of species . Geologists now rely on plate tectonics as a conceptual model and guiding theory when they are studying processes at work in Earth's crust . And physicists refer to atomic theory when they are predicting the existence of subatomic particles yet to be discovered. This does not mean that science is "finished," or that all of the important theories have been discovered already. Like evolution , progress in science happens both gradually and in short, dramatic bursts. Both types of progress are critical for creating a robust knowledge base with data as the foundation and scientific theories giving structure to that knowledge.

Table of Contents

  • Theories, hypotheses, and laws drive scientific progress

Activate glossary term highlighting to easily identify key terms within the module. Once highlighted, you can click on these terms to view their definitions.

Activate NGSS annotations to easily identify NGSS standards within the module. Once highlighted, you can click on them to view these standards.

What is a law in science?

The one thing a scientific law doesn't explain is why the phenomenon exists or what causes it.

Illustration of Isaac Newton’s universal law of gravitation.

  • Scientific theory vs. scientific law

Scientific laws and mathematics

Do laws change, examples of scientific laws, additional resources, bibliography.

In general, a scientific law is the description of an observed phenomenon. It doesn't explain why the phenomenon exists or what causes it. The explanation for a phenomenon is called a scientific theory . It is a misconception that theories turn into laws with enough research.

"In science, laws are a starting place," said Peter Coppinger, an associate professor of biology and biomedical engineering at the Rose-Hulman Institute of Technology in India. "From there, scientists can then ask the questions, 'Why and how?'" 

Difference between a scientific theory and a scientific law

Many people think that if scientists find evidence that supports a hypothesis, the hypothesis is upgraded to a theory, and if the theory is found to be correct, it is upgraded to a law. That is not how it works, though. Facts, theories and laws — as well as hypotheses — are separate elements of the scientific method . Though they may evolve, they aren't upgraded to something else.

" Hypotheses , theories and laws are rather like apples, oranges and kumquats: One cannot grow into another, no matter how much fertilizer and water are offered," according to the University of California, Berkeley . A hypothesis is a potential explanation of a narrow phenomenon; a scientific theory is an in-depth explanation that applies to a wide range of phenomena. A law is a statement about an observed phenomenon or a unifying concept, according to Kennesaw State University .

"There are four major concepts in science: facts, hypotheses, laws and theories," Coppinger told Live Science. 

Though scientific laws and theories are supported by a large body of empirical evidence that is accepted by the majority of scientists within that area of scientific study, and help to unify that body of data, they are not the same thing.

"Laws are descriptions — often mathematical descriptions — of natural phenomena for example, Newton's Law of Gravity or Mendel's Law of Independent Assortment. These laws simply describe the observation. Not how or why they work," Coppinger said.

Coppinger pointed out that the law of gravity was discovered by Isaac Newton in the 17th century. This law mathematically describes how two different bodies in the universe interact with each other. However, Newton's law doesn't explain what gravity is or how it works. It wasn't until three centuries later, when Albert Einstein developed the theory of Relativity , that scientists began to understand what gravity is and how it works. 

Mendelian Inheritance pea model.

"Newton's law is useful to scientists in that astrophysicists can use this centuries-old law to land robots on Mars. But it doesn't explain how gravity works, or what it is. Similarly, Mendel's Law of Independent Assortment describes how different traits are passed from parent to offspring, not how or why it happens," Coppinger said. Gregor Mendel discovered that two different genetic traits would appear independently of each other in different offspring. "Yet, Mendel knew nothing of DNA or chromosomes . It wasn't until a century later that scientists discovered DNA and chromosomes — the biochemical explanation of Mendel's laws. It was only then that scientists, such as T.H. Morgan, working with fruit flies, explained the Law of Independent Assortment using the theory of chromosomal inheritance. Still today, this is the universally accepted explanation (theory) for Mendel's Law," Coppinger said.

The difference between scientific laws and scientific facts is a bit harder to define, though the definition is important. Facts are simple, one-off observations that have been shown to be true. Laws are generalized observations about a relationship between two or more things in the natural world based on a variety of facts and empirical evidence, often framed as a mathematical statement, according to NASA . 

For example, "Apples fall down from this apple tree" is considered a fact because it is a simple statement that can be proven. "The strength of gravity between any two objects (like an apple and the Earth) depends on the masses of the objects and the distance between them" is a law because it describes the behavior of two objects in a certain circumstance. If the circumstance changes, then the implications of the law would change. For example, if the apple and the Earth shrank to a subatomic size, they would behave differently.

Equation showing Newton's universal law of gravitation.

Many scientific laws can be boiled down to a mathematical equation. For example, Newton's Law of Universal Gravitation states: 

F g = G (m 1 ∙ m 2 ) / d 2

Fg is the force of gravity; G is the universal gravitational constant, which can be measured; m1 and m2 are the masses of the two objects, and d is the distance between them, according to The Ohio State University .

Scientific laws are also often governed by the mathematics of probability. "With large numbers, probability always works. The house always wins," said Sylvia Wassertheil-Smoller, a professor at Albert Einstein College of Medicine in New York. "We can calculate the probability of an event and we can determine how certain we are of our estimate, but there is always a trade-off between precision and certainty. This is known as the confidence interval. For example, we can be 95% certain that what we are trying to estimate lies within a certain range or we can be more certain, say 99% certain, that it lies within a wider range. Just like in life in general, we must accept that there is a trade-off."

Just because an idea becomes a law doesn't mean that it can't be changed through scientific research in the future. The use of the word "law" by laymen and scientists differs. When most people talk about a law, they mean something that is absolute. A scientific law is much more flexible. It can have exceptions, be proven wrong or evolve over time, according to the University of California, Berkeley.

"A good scientist is one who always asks the question, 'How can I show myself wrong?'" Coppinger said. "In regards to the Law of Gravity or the Law of Independent Assortment, continual testing and observations have 'tweaked' these laws. Exceptions have been found. For example, Newton's Law of Gravity breaks down when looking at the quantum (subatomic) level. Mendel's Law of Independent Assortment breaks down when traits are "linked" on the same chromosome."

  • The law of conservation of energy, which says that the total energy in an isolated system remains constant. In other words, energy cannot be created or destroyed, according to Britannica .
  • The laws of thermodynamics , which deal with the relationships between heat and other forms of energy
  • Newton's universal law of gravitation, which says that any two objects exert a gravitational force upon each other, according to the University of Winnipeg
  • Hubble's law of cosmic expansion, which defines a relationship between a galaxy's distance and how fast it's moving away from us, according to astrophysicist Neta A. Bahcall
  • The Archimedes Principle , which states that the buoyant force on an object submerged in a fluid is equal to the weight of the fluid displaced by that object.
  • This resource from the New South Wales Education Standards Authority has an in-depth explanation of scientific theories and laws.
  • Find out why a theory can’t evolve into a law in this article from Indiana Public Media .
  • Watch a video about the difference between a scientific law and a scientific theory from TEDEd.

University of California, Berkeley, "​​Misconceptions about science." https://undsci.berkeley.edu/teaching/misconceptions.php

NASA IMAGE Education Center, "Teacher's Guide: Theories, Hypothesis, Laws, Facts & Beliefs." https://www.nasa.gov/pdf/371711main_SMII_Problem23.pdf  

The Ohio State University, "Lecture 18: The Apple and the Moon: Newtonian Gravity." https://www.astronomy.ohio-state.edu/pogge.1/Ast161/Unit4/gravity.html  

Encyclopedia Britannica, "Conservation of energy." November 16, 2021. https://www.britannica.com/science/conservation-of-energy  

University of Winnipeg, "Newton's Law of Gravitation." 1997. https://theory.uwinnipeg.ca/physics/circ/node7.html  

Neta A. Bahcall, "Hubble's Law and the expanding universe," Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Volume 112, March 2015, https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1424299112  

Sign up for the Live Science daily newsletter now

Get the world’s most fascinating discoveries delivered straight to your inbox.

Alina Bradford

Why do babies rub their eyes when they're tired?

Why do people dissociate during traumatic events?

Space photo of the week: James Webb telescope reveals surprising starburst in ancient galaxy

Most Popular

By Anna Gora December 27, 2023

By Anna Gora December 26, 2023

By Anna Gora December 25, 2023

By Emily Cooke December 23, 2023

By Victoria Atkinson December 22, 2023

By Anna Gora December 16, 2023

By Anna Gora December 15, 2023

By Anna Gora November 09, 2023

By Donavyn Coffey November 06, 2023

By Anna Gora October 31, 2023

By Anna Gora October 26, 2023

  • 2 Polar vortex is 'spinning backwards' above Arctic after major reversal event
  • 3 9,000-year-old rock art discovered among dinosaur footprints in Brazil
  • 4 Where does the solar system end?
  • 5 Secretive Delta IV Heavy rocket launch postponed indefinitely
  • 2 The 7 most powerful supercomputers in the world right now
  • 3 Fiber-optic data transfer speeds hit a rapid 301 Tbps — 1.2 million times faster than your home broadband connection
  • 4 Powerful X-class solar flare slams Earth, triggering radio blackout over the Pacific Ocean
  • 5 Polar vortex is 'spinning backwards' above Arctic after major reversal event

Back Home

  • Science Notes Posts
  • Contact Science Notes
  • Todd Helmenstine Biography
  • Anne Helmenstine Biography
  • Free Printable Periodic Tables (PDF and PNG)
  • Periodic Table Wallpapers
  • Interactive Periodic Table
  • Periodic Table Posters
  • How to Grow Crystals
  • Chemistry Projects
  • Fire and Flames Projects
  • Holiday Science
  • Chemistry Problems With Answers
  • Physics Problems
  • Unit Conversion Example Problems
  • Chemistry Worksheets
  • Biology Worksheets
  • Periodic Table Worksheets
  • Physical Science Worksheets
  • Science Lab Worksheets
  • My Amazon Books

Scientific Law Definition and Examples

Scientific Law vs Scientific Theory

A scientific law is a statement or mathematical equation that describes or predicts a natural phenomenon. It does not explain why or how a phenomenon occurs. Another name for a scientific law is a law of nature or law of science . All scientific laws are based on empirical evidence and the scientific method. In science, an assertion can be disproven, but never proven, so it’s possible for a scientific law to be revised or disproven by future experiments. In contrast, a mathematical theorem or identity is proven to be true.

Examples of Scientific Laws

There are laws in all scientific disciplines, although primarily they are physical laws. Here are some examples:

  • Beer’s law
  • Dalton’s law of partial pressures
  • Ideal gas law
  • Kepler’s laws of planetary motion
  • Law of conservation of mass
  • Law of conservation of energy
  • Law of conservation of momentum
  • Law of reflection
  • Laws of thermodynamics
  • Newton’s law of universal gravitation
  • Newton’s laws of motion

Difference Between a Scientific Law and Scientific Theory

Both scientific laws and scientific theories are based in the scientific method and are falsifiable. However, the two terms have very different meanings. A law describes what happens, but does not explain it. A theory explains how or why something works.

For example, Newton’s law of universal gravitation describes what happens when two masses are a given distance apart. The law can be written as a mathematical equation [F = G(m 1 m 2 /r 2 )] and used to make predictions and calculations. However, the law does not explain how gravity works or why two masses are attracted to one another. Scientists didn’t really have an explanation for gravity until Einstein’s theory of general relativity, which continues to be revised as we understand more about the nature of spacetime.

As another example, Hubble’s law of Cosmic Expansion (velocity = Hubble constant x distance) describes the movement of galaxies away from each other. It does explain why this occurs. The Big Bang Theory is one of the theories that explains why galaxies move apart, but the theory does not offer a formula for calculating this motion.

Can a Hypothesis or Theory Become a Law?

A hypothesis , theory, and law are all parts of scientific inquiry, but one never becomes another . They are different things. A hypothesis never becomes a theory, no matter how many experiments support it, because a hypothesis is simply a prediction about how one variable responds when another is changed. A theory takes into account the results of many experiments, testing different hypotheses. A theory explains how something works. Like a theory, a law draws on the results of repeated observations and experiments. But, a law states in words or mathematical equations what happens. Laws don’t explain why.

  • Barrow, John (1991). Theories of Everything: The Quest for Ultimate Explanations . ISBN 0-449-90738-4.
  • Feynman, Richard (1994). The Character of Physical Law (Modern Library ed.). New York: Modern Library. ISBN 978-0-679-60127-2.
  • Gould, Stephen Jay (1981). “ Evolution as Fact and Theory “. Discover . 2 (5): 34–37.
  • McComas, William F. (2013). The Language of Science Education: An Expanded Glossary of Key Terms and Concepts in Science Teaching and Learning. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-6209-497-0.

Related Posts

Have a language expert improve your writing

Run a free plagiarism check in 10 minutes, generate accurate citations for free.

  • Knowledge Base

Methodology

  • How to Write a Strong Hypothesis | Steps & Examples

How to Write a Strong Hypothesis | Steps & Examples

Published on May 6, 2022 by Shona McCombes . Revised on November 20, 2023.

A hypothesis is a statement that can be tested by scientific research. If you want to test a relationship between two or more variables, you need to write hypotheses before you start your experiment or data collection .

Example: Hypothesis

Daily apple consumption leads to fewer doctor’s visits.

Table of contents

What is a hypothesis, developing a hypothesis (with example), hypothesis examples, other interesting articles, frequently asked questions about writing hypotheses.

A hypothesis states your predictions about what your research will find. It is a tentative answer to your research question that has not yet been tested. For some research projects, you might have to write several hypotheses that address different aspects of your research question.

A hypothesis is not just a guess – it should be based on existing theories and knowledge. It also has to be testable, which means you can support or refute it through scientific research methods (such as experiments, observations and statistical analysis of data).

Variables in hypotheses

Hypotheses propose a relationship between two or more types of variables .

  • An independent variable is something the researcher changes or controls.
  • A dependent variable is something the researcher observes and measures.

If there are any control variables , extraneous variables , or confounding variables , be sure to jot those down as you go to minimize the chances that research bias  will affect your results.

In this example, the independent variable is exposure to the sun – the assumed cause . The dependent variable is the level of happiness – the assumed effect .

Here's why students love Scribbr's proofreading services

Discover proofreading & editing

Step 1. Ask a question

Writing a hypothesis begins with a research question that you want to answer. The question should be focused, specific, and researchable within the constraints of your project.

Step 2. Do some preliminary research

Your initial answer to the question should be based on what is already known about the topic. Look for theories and previous studies to help you form educated assumptions about what your research will find.

At this stage, you might construct a conceptual framework to ensure that you’re embarking on a relevant topic . This can also help you identify which variables you will study and what you think the relationships are between them. Sometimes, you’ll have to operationalize more complex constructs.

Step 3. Formulate your hypothesis

Now you should have some idea of what you expect to find. Write your initial answer to the question in a clear, concise sentence.

4. Refine your hypothesis

You need to make sure your hypothesis is specific and testable. There are various ways of phrasing a hypothesis, but all the terms you use should have clear definitions, and the hypothesis should contain:

  • The relevant variables
  • The specific group being studied
  • The predicted outcome of the experiment or analysis

5. Phrase your hypothesis in three ways

To identify the variables, you can write a simple prediction in  if…then form. The first part of the sentence states the independent variable and the second part states the dependent variable.

In academic research, hypotheses are more commonly phrased in terms of correlations or effects, where you directly state the predicted relationship between variables.

If you are comparing two groups, the hypothesis can state what difference you expect to find between them.

6. Write a null hypothesis

If your research involves statistical hypothesis testing , you will also have to write a null hypothesis . The null hypothesis is the default position that there is no association between the variables. The null hypothesis is written as H 0 , while the alternative hypothesis is H 1 or H a .

  • H 0 : The number of lectures attended by first-year students has no effect on their final exam scores.
  • H 1 : The number of lectures attended by first-year students has a positive effect on their final exam scores.

If you want to know more about the research process , methodology , research bias , or statistics , make sure to check out some of our other articles with explanations and examples.

  • Sampling methods
  • Simple random sampling
  • Stratified sampling
  • Cluster sampling
  • Likert scales
  • Reproducibility

 Statistics

  • Null hypothesis
  • Statistical power
  • Probability distribution
  • Effect size
  • Poisson distribution

Research bias

  • Optimism bias
  • Cognitive bias
  • Implicit bias
  • Hawthorne effect
  • Anchoring bias
  • Explicit bias

Prevent plagiarism. Run a free check.

A hypothesis is not just a guess — it should be based on existing theories and knowledge. It also has to be testable, which means you can support or refute it through scientific research methods (such as experiments, observations and statistical analysis of data).

Null and alternative hypotheses are used in statistical hypothesis testing . The null hypothesis of a test always predicts no effect or no relationship between variables, while the alternative hypothesis states your research prediction of an effect or relationship.

Hypothesis testing is a formal procedure for investigating our ideas about the world using statistics. It is used by scientists to test specific predictions, called hypotheses , by calculating how likely it is that a pattern or relationship between variables could have arisen by chance.

Cite this Scribbr article

If you want to cite this source, you can copy and paste the citation or click the “Cite this Scribbr article” button to automatically add the citation to our free Citation Generator.

McCombes, S. (2023, November 20). How to Write a Strong Hypothesis | Steps & Examples. Scribbr. Retrieved April 2, 2024, from https://www.scribbr.com/methodology/hypothesis/

Is this article helpful?

Shona McCombes

Shona McCombes

Other students also liked, construct validity | definition, types, & examples, what is a conceptual framework | tips & examples, operationalization | a guide with examples, pros & cons, unlimited academic ai-proofreading.

✔ Document error-free in 5minutes ✔ Unlimited document corrections ✔ Specialized in correcting academic texts

  • More from M-W
  • To save this word, you'll need to log in. Log In

Definition of hypothesis

Did you know.

The Difference Between Hypothesis and Theory

A hypothesis is an assumption, an idea that is proposed for the sake of argument so that it can be tested to see if it might be true.

In the scientific method, the hypothesis is constructed before any applicable research has been done, apart from a basic background review. You ask a question, read up on what has been studied before, and then form a hypothesis.

A hypothesis is usually tentative; it's an assumption or suggestion made strictly for the objective of being tested.

A theory , in contrast, is a principle that has been formed as an attempt to explain things that have already been substantiated by data. It is used in the names of a number of principles accepted in the scientific community, such as the Big Bang Theory . Because of the rigors of experimentation and control, it is understood to be more likely to be true than a hypothesis is.

In non-scientific use, however, hypothesis and theory are often used interchangeably to mean simply an idea, speculation, or hunch, with theory being the more common choice.

Since this casual use does away with the distinctions upheld by the scientific community, hypothesis and theory are prone to being wrongly interpreted even when they are encountered in scientific contexts—or at least, contexts that allude to scientific study without making the critical distinction that scientists employ when weighing hypotheses and theories.

The most common occurrence is when theory is interpreted—and sometimes even gleefully seized upon—to mean something having less truth value than other scientific principles. (The word law applies to principles so firmly established that they are almost never questioned, such as the law of gravity.)

This mistake is one of projection: since we use theory in general to mean something lightly speculated, then it's implied that scientists must be talking about the same level of uncertainty when they use theory to refer to their well-tested and reasoned principles.

The distinction has come to the forefront particularly on occasions when the content of science curricula in schools has been challenged—notably, when a school board in Georgia put stickers on textbooks stating that evolution was "a theory, not a fact, regarding the origin of living things." As Kenneth R. Miller, a cell biologist at Brown University, has said , a theory "doesn’t mean a hunch or a guess. A theory is a system of explanations that ties together a whole bunch of facts. It not only explains those facts, but predicts what you ought to find from other observations and experiments.”

While theories are never completely infallible, they form the basis of scientific reasoning because, as Miller said "to the best of our ability, we’ve tested them, and they’ve held up."

  • proposition
  • supposition

hypothesis , theory , law mean a formula derived by inference from scientific data that explains a principle operating in nature.

hypothesis implies insufficient evidence to provide more than a tentative explanation.

theory implies a greater range of evidence and greater likelihood of truth.

law implies a statement of order and relation in nature that has been found to be invariable under the same conditions.

Examples of hypothesis in a Sentence

These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word 'hypothesis.' Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.

Word History

Greek, from hypotithenai to put under, suppose, from hypo- + tithenai to put — more at do

1641, in the meaning defined at sense 1a

Phrases Containing hypothesis

  • counter - hypothesis
  • nebular hypothesis
  • null hypothesis
  • planetesimal hypothesis
  • Whorfian hypothesis

Articles Related to hypothesis

hypothesis

This is the Difference Between a...

This is the Difference Between a Hypothesis and a Theory

In scientific reasoning, they're two completely different things

Dictionary Entries Near hypothesis

hypothermia

hypothesize

Cite this Entry

“Hypothesis.” Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary , Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/hypothesis. Accessed 2 Apr. 2024.

Kids Definition

Kids definition of hypothesis, medical definition, medical definition of hypothesis, more from merriam-webster on hypothesis.

Nglish: Translation of hypothesis for Spanish Speakers

Britannica English: Translation of hypothesis for Arabic Speakers

Britannica.com: Encyclopedia article about hypothesis

Subscribe to America's largest dictionary and get thousands more definitions and advanced search—ad free!

Play Quordle: Guess all four words in a limited number of tries.  Each of your guesses must be a real 5-letter word.

Can you solve 4 words at once?

Word of the day.

See Definitions and Examples »

Get Word of the Day daily email!

Popular in Grammar & Usage

The tangled history of 'it's' and 'its', more commonly misspelled words, why does english have so many silent letters, your vs. you're: how to use them correctly, every letter is silent, sometimes: a-z list of examples, popular in wordplay, the words of the week - mar. 29, 10 scrabble words without any vowels, 12 more bird names that sound like insults (and sometimes are), 8 uncommon words related to love, 9 superb owl words, games & quizzes.

Play Blossom: Solve today's spelling word game by finding as many words as you can using just 7 letters. Longer words score more points.

"Arrest me!": J.K. Rowling posts anti-trans rant, responding to Scottish hate crime law

Rowling stated that she "looked forward to being arrested" if her post violated "the terms of the new act", by gabriella ferrigine.

J.K. Rowling has taken on Scotland's new legislation against hate speech in a lengthy anti-transgender  Twitter thread posted Monday. 

Per ABC, Scotland's new Hate Crime and Public Order Act makes it unlawful to incite hatred via threatening or abusive language on the basis age, disability, religion, sexual orientation and transgender identity. The "Harry Potter" series creator known for criticizing transgender individuals posted a thread about the new law by sharing information about several transgender women, including convicted criminals, trans-activists  and other public figures. "April Fools!" Rowling wrote . "Only kidding. Obviously, the people mentioned in the above tweets aren't women at all, but men, every last one of them.

"In passing the Scottish Hate Crime Act," Rowling claimed, "Scottish lawmakers seem to have placed higher value on the feelings of men performing their idea of femaleness, however misogynistically or opportunistically, than on the rights and freedoms of actual women and girls. . . . For several years now, Scottish women have been pressured by their government and members of the police force to deny the evidence of their eyes and ears, repudiate biological facts and embrace a neo-religious concept of gender that is unprovable and untestable . . . Freedom of speech and belief are at an end in Scotland if the accurate description of biological sex is deemed criminal."

Rowling concluded she's currently not in Scotland, "But if what I've written here qualifies as an offence under the terms of the new act, I look forward to being arrested when I return to the birthplace of the Scottish Enlightenment," she said. She added the hashtag #ArrestMe

hypothesis legal term

  • Skip to main content
  • Keyboard shortcuts for audio player

In Florida, there's détente in the battle between Disney and Gov. Ron DeSantis

hypothesis legal term

The Walt Disney Company and Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis have called off their lawsuit stemming from a yearlong legal dispute. It involves the district that's home to Disney's central Florida resort. Walt Disney World Resort via Get hide caption

The Walt Disney Company and Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis have called off their lawsuit stemming from a yearlong legal dispute. It involves the district that's home to Disney's central Florida resort.

MIAMI — The Walt Disney Company and a board appointed by Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis say they've reached a settlement that resolves a yearlong legal dispute.

It involves the Central Florida Tourism Oversight District, which encompasses the 40-square-mile property that's home to the Walt Disney World resort. DeSantis and Republican lawmakers created a new board for the district after they approved a law revoking Disney's self-governing status.

The settlement resolves lawsuits over a last-minute agreement Disney signed with its old board last year before it was dissolved by DeSantis and the Florida Legislature. That agreement would have taken power away from the new board and reserved for Disney all decisions concerning development at the theme parks. Under the settlement, that deal is now "null and void."

Disney sues Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis, claiming 'government retaliation'

Disney sues Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis, claiming 'government retaliation'

A federal judge dismisses Disney's lawsuit against Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis

A federal judge dismisses Disney's lawsuit against Florida Gov. Ron DeSantis

At a meeting Wednesday, the Central Florida Tourism Oversight District board said it will now work with Disney to update the district's 2020 comprehensive plan.

But a little later in the day, at a news conference in Orlando, DeSantis took aim at critics in the media and elsewhere who predicted that Disney would win its lawsuits and take back its self-governing status.

"The reality is here we are a year later and not one of them has succeeded," DeSantis said. "Every action we have taken has been upheld in full. And the state's better off for it."

It's the apparent end of a political battle that began in 2022 when DeSantis signed the Parental Rights in Education Act . The law, dubbed "Don't Say Gay" by critics, restricts how sexual orientation and gender identity are discussed in the schools. Disney's former CEO Bob Chapek spoke out against the law and said he'd work to overturn it. That angered DeSantis, who then worked with Republican lawmakers to pass a measure revoking Disney's self-governing status.

DeSantis appointed a new board to oversee the district. Disney challenged the move in federal court but lost. It's appealing that lawsuit. But Wednesday, Disney and the DeSantis-appointed board announced they had settled all the lawsuits pending in state court and are ready to move forward together.

"This agreement opens a new chapter of constructive engagement with the new leadership of the district and serves the interests of all parties by enabling significant continued investment and the creation of thousands of direct and indirect jobs and economic opportunity in the State," Walt Disney World Resort President Jeff Vahle said.

DeSantis wants to end Disney World's special status in Florida

DeSantis wants to end Disney World's special status in Florida

Disney workers walk out over the company's response to so-called 'Don't Say Gay' bill

Disney workers walk out over the company's response to so-called 'Don't Say Gay' bill

Another factor in the settlement appears to be two appointments also announced Wednesday. DeSantis named a new member to the district's board, Craig Mateer. Mateer formerly owned a tourism-related company in Orlando. At DeSantis' recommendation, the board appointed Stephanie Kopelousos as the new district administrator. Kopelousos had served as a former Clay County manager and was legislative and intergovernmental affairs director for DeSantis.

With the settlement, Disney is indicating that the current structure, operating under a board appointed by Florida's governor, is one it can work with. Disney CEO Bob Iger has announced plans to spend at least $30 billion to upgrade its theme parks over the next decade, including some $17 billion in Orlando.

Rick Foglesong, a retired professor and author of Married to the Mouse , which chronicles Disney's relationship with Florida, says the settlement is a win for both Disney and DeSantis. "I think they both needed to escape from the imbroglio in which they found themselves, that it wasn't working for either one of them."

Foglesong says the settlement clears the way for the expansion plans to go forward. Disney, he says, "needed to continue to invest here without appearing weak, as if they were caving to DeSantis. They need to keep tourists coming back. They need to reinvest in the parks."

In recent months, DeSantis has also indicated that he was also ready to move on from the fight. In campaign speeches in his run for the Republican presidential nomination, DeSantis often brought up his fight with Disney. Once that candidacy ended, he began moving to put the issue behind him. In a state where tourism accounts for nearly 10% of jobs, fighting with the operator of one of the state's most popular destinations may not have been seen as a winning long-term strategy.

  • Florida Governor Ron DeSantis
  • Share full article

Advertisement

Supported by

U.S.-Funded Broadcaster Leaves Hong Kong, Citing Security Law

Radio Free Asia, which ran a small operation in Hong Kong, said its staff was at risk because of the law’s sweeping definition of “external interference.”

Journalists crowd together, their cameras pointed in the same direction, behind a fence set up outside a building.

By David Pierson

Reporting from Hong Kong

The United States-funded news service Radio Free Asia said on Friday that it has closed its office in Hong Kong because of concerns about the city’s recently enacted national security law that targets so-called foreign interference.

Hong Kong’s new national security law, which was passed with unusual speed earlier this month, raised “serious questions about our ability to operate in safety,” the broadcaster’s president and chief executive, Bay Fang, said in a statement . Radio Free Asia said that it had relocated some employees from Hong Kong to Taiwan, the United States or elsewhere and laid others off.

The authorities in China have long accused Radio Free Asia, also known as R.F.A., of being a front for the U.S. government. In its statement, the news organization noted that officials in Hong Kong had also recently referred to R.F.A. as a “foreign force” in the context of how it covered the discussion over the new security law.

Hong Kong enacted the security law on March 23 , giving the city’s authorities more power to investigate such offenses as “external interference” and the theft of state secrets. The city’s officials, including its security chief, Chris Tang, have insisted that freedoms would be protected and the law would target only national security threats. The government declined a request to comment on Radio Free Asia’s departure, pointing instead to national security laws in other countries to justify legislation in Hong Kong.

“To single out Hong Kong and suggest that journalists would only experience concerns when operating here but not in other countries would be grossly biased, if not outrageous,” a government spokesman said in an emailed statement.

But advocates of press freedom say the laws significantly raise the risks for journalists operating in the city. Its vague definition of external interference can be broadly applied to regular journalistic work, the activists say .

Hong Kong’s status as one of Asia’s most vibrant capitals of free and independent media has eroded precipitously since Beijing imposed a sweeping crackdown on the city in response to antigovernment protests that erupted there in 2019.

In 2020, China directly imposed a national security law on the city that effectively silenced dissent there. Newsrooms were raided and editors arrested, forcing the closure of Apple Daily, a popular pro-democracy newspaper, as well as smaller, independent outlets such as Stand News and Citizen News.

The founder of Apple Daily, Jimmy Lai, is currently on trial on national security charges and is accused of masterminding the 2019 demonstrations. Two senior editors for Stand News are also on trial, accused of publishing what the authorities have called seditious material, which includes profiles of pro-democracy activists.

The government also imposed an overhaul of Radio Television Hong Kong, a public broadcaster that once was known for reporting critically on officials; programs were canceled and staff members replaced.

This year, as Hong Kong moved swiftly to pass its own security laws, the Hong Kong Journalists Association warned of a chilling effect. Leaks from government sources regarding personnel changes, financial budgets, police investigations and other matters in the public interest could be subject to national security laws, the group warned.

Officials say those concerns are misplaced and that there are sufficient safeguards in the laws to protect regular reporting.

In the past months, the Hong Kong government has taken a far more adversarial stance against foreign media. Officials have lashed out about a guest essay published in The New York Times and an editorial by The Washington Post as well as news articles by the BBC and Bloomberg about the national security legislation, describing the reports as scaremongering. (In 2020, The Times announced it would relocate its Hong Kong-based digital news operation to Seoul after the first security law was imposed.)

Cédric Alviani, the Asia-Pacific bureau director of Reporters Without Borders, said Hong Kong’s national security laws were placing pressure on local journalists to censor themselves to avoid crossing the government’s “blurry red lines.”

“What we’re seeing is the Chinese system of repression against the right to information and independent journalism is being applied more and more in Hong Kong,” Mr. Alviani said.

Radio Free Asia said its audience for content in Cantonese, the main language spoken in the city, grew sharply after the closures of Apple Daily and Stand News in 2021. Even so, it had already been suspending some of its Cantonese reports and programming because of concerns over China’s national security law.

The news outlet ran a small operation in Hong Kong; Ms. Fang, the president, said that it would retain its media license there and would cover Hong Kong remotely.

Radio Free Asia denies that it serves as a proxy for Washington. Though it is funded by the U.S. government’s Agency for Global Media, it says it maintains a legislative firewall that bars journalistic interference from U.S. officials.

Olivia Wang contributed research.

David Pierson covers Chinese foreign policy and China’s economic and cultural engagement with the world. He has been a journalist for more than two decades. More about David Pierson

  • International

live news

Israel-Hamas war

live news

2024 campaign and primaries

April 1, 2024 - Israel-Hamas war

By Jessie Yeung , Antoinette Radford, Maureen Chowdhury , Elise Hammond and Aditi Sangal , CNN

Netanyahu says he will temporarily shut down Al Jazeera news network in Israel

From CNN's Hande Atay Alam and Michael Conte

Israeli Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu speaks to the media following talks at the Chancellery in Berlin, Germany on March 16, 2023.

Israel's parliament approved a law on Monday that would allow the government to temporarily shut down the Al Jazeera news network in Israel.

The law gives the prime minister and the communications minister the authority to order the closure of foreign networks operating temporarily in Israel that are deemed a threat to national security.

Israel's Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu said he intends "to act immediately in accordance with the new law to stop the channel's activity," according to a post on X.

CNN reached out to the Qatar-based Al Jazeera for comment.

Separately, the United States said it will “continue to make clear” to Israel that it supports “the work that the free press does,” including Al Jazeera, according to State Department spokesperson Matthew Miller.

“We think the work that the independent free press does is important everywhere in the world, and much of what we know about what has happened in Gaza is because of reporters who are there doing their jobs, including reporters from Al Jazeera,” Miller said Monday.

Iran accuses Israel of killing Iranian military commander in airstrike on consulate in Damascus, Syria

From CNN's Hande Atay Alam, Adam Pourahmadi, Allegra Goodwin and Lauren Kent

Emergency and security personnel gather at the site of strikes, which hit a building next to the Iranian embassy, in Damascus, Syria, on Monday.

A top commander in Iran’s Revolutionary Guard has been killed in an airstrike on the country’s consulate building in Damascus, Syria, according to Iranian officials and state-affiliated media, which blamed Israel for the attack.

Iranian Quds Force commander Mohammed Reza Zahedi was among those killed in the incident on Monday, according to Iran's foreign ministry.

Speaking to reporters in Damascus, Iranian ambassador Hossein Akbari alleged that the building “was targeted with six missiles from Israeli F-35 warplanes.”

“Between five and seven people were killed in the attack. I was in my office in the embassy at the time and witnessed the destruction myself,” Akbari said.

Akbari added that Iranian diplomatic staff and military advisers were killed in the attack, and their names will be announced later. In a separate interview later on Monday, he said two Syrian policemen were among the people injured.

CNN cannot independently verify the claims or casualty figures. 

Syrian state media Syrian Arab News Agency also reported that “an Israeli act of aggression targeted on Monday afternoon a building in Mezzeh neighborhood in Damascus,” causing “massive destruction.”

Asked for comment on the incident by CNN, the Israel Defense Forces said it does not comment on foreign reports. Footage of the aftermath of the blast, published by Iranian state media Press TV, showed damage to the building, fire and smoke at the scene.

The foreign ministers of Iran and Syria also accused Israel of authoring the attack, with Iranian Foreign Minister Hossein Amir-Abdollahian calling it a “violation of all international obligations and conventions” and demanding a “serious response by the international community. Syrian Foreign Minister Faisal Mekdad described the alleged attack a “gross violation of international regulations, especially the 1961 Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations,” according to a readout of his call with Amir-Abdollahian.

Zahedi, the slain commander, was previously the commander of IRGC’s ground forces, the commander of IRGC’s air force, and the deputy commander of the IRGC’s operations.

This post was updated with more details on the casualties in Damascus.

UN is planning a mission to Al-Shifa Hospital following Israel's withdrawal

From CNN’s Eve Brennan in London and Richard Roth at the UN

The United Nations is planning a mission to Al-Shifa Hospital as soon as it is "allowed to help people receive medical attention and to assess the facility," the Office for the Coordination of Humanitarian Affairs (OCHA) said Monday.

The announcement comes after Israel ended its 14-day siege on Gaza’s largest hospital on Monday.

At least 300 bodies have been uncovered there so far, according to Gaza’s Civil Defense, and one witness described the destructive aftermath as like a scene from a "horror movie." 

The United Nations also said a WHO team visited the Al-Aqsa Hospital in central Gaza on Sunday when a tent camp inside the compound was hit by an Israeli airstrike.

On Sunday, Martin Griffiths, the UN's under-secretary-general for Humanitarian Affairs, called for attempts to sideline the largest humanitarian organization in Gaza — the United Nations Relief and Works Agency for Palestine Refugees in the Near East (UNRWA) — to stop.

He called UNRWA "the backbone of the humanitarian operation in Gaza" and added in his post on X that "any effort to distribute aid without them is simply doomed to fail." He added, "No other agency has the same reach, experience or community trust needed to do the job."

Al-Shifa hospital aftermath shows need for long-term Israeli plan for Gaza, State Department says

From CNN’s Michael Conte 

People inspect the damage at Al-Shifa hospital in Gaza on April 1.

Media reports of the aftermath of Israel’s operation inside Al-Shifa hospital in Gaza demonstrate “the need for Israel to have a sustainable long-term strategy” for the aftermath of the war, the United States State Department said Monday.

“They need to have a long-term sustainable strategy that is not just a security strategy, but also a political strategy if they really want to secure the future of Israel against the terrorist threat that has to date emanated from Gaza,” said State Department spokesperson Matthew Miller at a press briefing Monday.

Miller elaborated that the US still has not seen such a plan from Israel.

Witnesses and Palestinian officials say the Israeli operation left buildings largely destroyed and bodies strewn across the hospital complex. The Israel Defense Forces (IDF) confirmed its withdrawal Monday, saying its troops had killed Hamas militants, and seized weaponry and intelligence documents.

Miller also said that while the US “generally” does not want to see Israel operating in hospitals inside Gaza, “it is concerning that after Israel had conducted an operation earlier in this campaign to clear Al-Shifa that Al-Shifa again was apparently infiltrated by Hamas fighters.”

“It would be great if Hamas would stop hiding behind civilians and stop hiding inside civilian infrastructure,” he added.

US and Israeli officials are holding high-stakes virtual meeting today on Rafah, White House confirms

From CNN's Sam Fossum

The White House confirmed that senior US and Israeli officials are meeting virtually today as the Biden administration works to dissuade the Israeli government from a large military incursion into Gaza's densely populated city of Rafah. 

"We’ve been very clear about our concerns about a military operation into Rafah," White House press secretary Karine Jean-Pierre told reporters Monday, adding that there will be a readout of the meeting. "If they’re going to move forward with a military operation we have to have this conversation. We have to understand how they’re going to move forward."

The officials are also going to discuss "alternative ways of going after Hamas," she said. "I think it’s important that it happen as quickly as it did even though it’s virtual. And we’ll certainly have more to share."

It is taking place after a previously scheduled meeting was called off by the Israeli government after the US declined to block a UN Security Council resolution calling for a ceasefire in Gaza. 

Meanwhile tomorrow: President Joe Biden is expected to host a significantly scaled down iftar dinner at the White House on Tuesday to commemorate Ramadan, three sources familiar with the plans tell CNN. Several people who were invited to the dinner have declined, sources said, citing frustration with the administration’s support of Israel as the humanitarian crisis in Gaza continues. 

Vice President Kamala Harris, national security adviser Jake Sullivan, senior White House aides, and less than dozen invited guests are expected to attend the small gathering, a senior administration official said. Officials are hoping that the dinner will provide an opportunity for the guests to directly speak with the president and share their concerns about the Israel-Hamas conflict, according to a senior administration official. 

CNN's Khalil Abdallah, Camila DeChalus, and Betsy Klein contributed reporting to this post.

IDF says those detained in Al-Shifa hospital are being "treated in accordance with international law"

From CNN’s Hande Atay Alam in Atlanta

The Israel Defense Forces (IDF) told CNN on Monday that those detained in Al-Shifa hospital during the military raid are being "treated in accordance with international law."

When asked to respond to Al-Shifa medical staff complaints that staff were forced to strip naked, and that one staff representative was left "half naked for three hours before allowed to talk," the IDF responded: "It is often necessary for terror suspects to hand over their clothes such that their clothes can be searched and to ensure that they are not concealing explosive vests or other weaponry." The IDF said detainees were given back their clothes "when possible to do so."

The IDF claimed they were only detaining people they said were involved in terrorist activity, and releasing others who were not found to be involved. 

Israel's claims come as the military withdraws from Gaza’s largest hospital,  Al-Shifa , after a  14-day siege  that witnesses and Palestinian officials say has left buildings largely destroyed and bodies strewn across the complex. The IDF said Monday that its troops had killed Hamas militants, and seized weaponry and intelligence documents and that troops had done their "utmost" to keep civilians unharmed. 

But Gaza's Civil Defense reported earlier that at least 300 bodies have been found so far at Al-Shifa Hospital in Gaza City. The organization added that it was difficult to determine the exact number of people killed as Israeli forces had buried bodies inside and around the Al-Shifa complex and bulldozed nearby roads.

In photos: Aftermath of Israeli troop withdrawal from Al-Shifa hospital reveals trail of destruction

From CNN Digital's Photo team

Israel has withdrawn from Gaza's largest hospital, Al-Shifa, after a 14-day siege that left buildings largely destroyed and hundreds of people dead.

This is what the devastation looks like in images:

A view of destroyed houses and buildings at the area around Al-Shifa Hospital on April 1.

Satellite images show significant destruction at Al-Shifa hospital after IDF troops withdraw

From CNN's Paul P. Murphy and Allegra Goodwin

A satellite image taken on Monday shows the damage to the area around the Al-Shifa Hospital complex in Gaza City.

The Al-Shifa Hospital complex suffered significant building destruction and bulldozing during the 14 day siege by the Israel Defense Forces, according to new satellite images from Maxar Technologies.

The images, taken on April 1, show that much of the area around the hospital complex in central Gaza City has been leveled. 

Inside the complex, most of the buildings have sustained damage: some have been completely destroyed, others are missing entire facades and roofs. 

The grounds of the entire hospital complex is now covered in a layer of bulldozed dirt. 

The Gaza Civil Defense said that at least 300 bodies have been found at the complex, so far. 

"Injured and dead bodies fill the hospital grounds," Gaza Civil Defense captain Mahmoud Bassal told CNN on Monday, adding, "There are bodies buried in the hospital yards."

Israel Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu on Sunday claimed more than 200 militants had been killed in the hospital. The IDF has repeatedly claimed the Al-Shifa complex was being used by armed militants. 

Pediatrician who returned from Gaza says it’s a "massacre of human and civilian life"

From CNN’s Zeena Saifi and Zahid Mahmood

Dr. Tanya Haj-Hassan, a pediatric intensive care doctor with Doctors Without Borders, who has just returned from Gaza, told CNN on Monday that they are seeing a "massacre of human and civilian life" in the enclave.

Speaking to CNN from Amman, Jordan, Haj-Hassan said there have been many killings of civilians young and old.  

"We saw in the emergency department entire families being killed, maimed, dismembered, burned," she said.  

Haj-Hassan recalled a story about a young boy whose entire family had been killed. She said the boy's sister initially survived but was so badly burned and maimed that he was not able to recognize her.  

"He kept calling her name, he himself had half of his face blown off and is undergoing reconstructive surgery as we speak," she said. "She (the sister) died two days later." Haj-Hassan continued to say that the war has been documented in real time with videos from social media and was "ashamed to be a part of society that is allowing it to happen."

"This is a demise of our collective humanity," Haj-Hassan said. "I hope that that anybody with an awake conscience watching this hears these words and translates them into action," she added.

Please enable JavaScript for a better experience.

  • International edition
  • Australia edition
  • Europe edition

Victoria McCloud, a senior civil judge, is concerned that a successful appeal might reverse her birth certificate.

Transgender judge seeks leave to intervene in UK court case over legal definition of ‘woman’

Victoria McCloud wants leave to join litigation in supreme court appeal brought by For Women Scotland

The UK’s first transgender judge is seeking leave to join the litigation in a crucial supreme court case that could significantly affect legal protections for transgender women, the Guardian has learned.

Victoria McCloud, a senior civil judge who became the youngest person appointed as master of the high court in 2010, will make an application to intervene in the supreme court appeal brought by the campaign group For Women Scotland about the legal definition of “woman”. Interveners can put a case without being among the main parties to the litigation.

For Women Scotland is challenging whether Scottish government legislation aimed at improving gender balance on public boards should include transgender women.

The Gender Representation on Public Boards (Scotland) Act 2018 has been the subject of a long-running court action by the group, which most recently resulted in a ruling by Lady Haldane at the court of session that it was lawful to extend the definition of “woman” to transgender women with a gender recognition certificate.

McCloud, who transitioned in the late 1990s and subsequently changed her legal sex under the 2004 Gender Recognition Act, is supported in her application by the Good Law Project.

She is concerned about the effect of a successful appeal – which would affect the whole of the UK – on her legal recognition.

McCloud cannot speak directly to the media because of judicial constraints. A friend of hers said: “This would mean in practice that women like her [with a gender recognition certificate] would lose rights to equal pay with men and experience restricted rights to services or moves to exclude her from spaces such as women’s lavatories.”

The Guardian understands that if the For Women Scotland appeal succeeds, McCloud and her family have made provision to emigrate to an EU state where she would remain legally recognised as a woman.

Last month McCloud, 54, announced that she was resigning from the bench in April after 14 years as a full-time judge, citing the toxic climate towards transgender individuals in the UK.

In her resignation letter to the lady chief justice, president and vice-president of the king’s bench division, she wrote: “I have reached the conclusion that in 2024 the national situation and present judicial framework is no longer such that it is possible in a dignified way to be both ‘trans’ and a salaried, fairly prominent judge in the UK.”

According to For Women Scotland, which won an earlier judicial review of the act, the conflicting Scottish rulings “show that a definition of ‘sex’ that is inclusive of a person’s ‘acquired gender’ on a gender recognition certificate leaves the Equality Act opaque and unworkable for many women. There needs to be clarity that sex is a biological term.”

It argues that Haldane’s inclusive definition of “sex” leaves service providers of single-sex spaces “confused and … at risk of legal action for unlawful discrimination”.

Describing the case as “truly historic”, the author and campaigner JK Rowling has donated £70,000 to For Women Scotland’s crowdfunder for the action, which currently sits at nearly £150,000.

The executive director of the Good Law Project, Jo Maugham, said: “So many of these cases – about and with profound effects on the lives of trans people – are decided without any trans people in the room. Sometimes this happens because trans people can’t afford representation – they have no billionaire funders.

“Sometimes because it is said that trans people are self-interested – as though decisions about, say, black people should be made by white people. But however it happens it is not what justice looks like.”

  • Transgender
  • UK supreme court

More on this story

hypothesis legal term

‘We actually don’t know much’: the scientists trying to close the knowledge gap in trans healthcare

hypothesis legal term

Children to stop getting puberty blockers at gender identity clinics, says NHS England

hypothesis legal term

Green party sacking of spokesperson over trans rights views was procedurally unfair, court rules

hypothesis legal term

Sunak refuses to apologise to Brianna Ghey’s father over PMQs trans jibe

hypothesis legal term

Minister defends Sunak’s transgender jibe amid calls for apology

hypothesis legal term

Brianna Ghey’s father demands apology from Sunak over transgender remark

hypothesis legal term

Whether driven by Sunak’s callousness or clumsiness, trans jibe is PM’s new normal

hypothesis legal term

Starmer condemns Sunak over trans rights jibe during PMQs visit by Brianna Ghey’s mother

Most viewed.

Library homepage

  • school Campus Bookshelves
  • menu_book Bookshelves
  • perm_media Learning Objects
  • login Login
  • how_to_reg Request Instructor Account
  • hub Instructor Commons
  • Download Page (PDF)
  • Download Full Book (PDF)
  • Periodic Table
  • Physics Constants
  • Scientific Calculator
  • Reference & Cite
  • Tools expand_more
  • Readability

selected template will load here

This action is not available.

Chemistry LibreTexts

1.1: Hypothesis, Theories, and Laws

  • Last updated
  • Save as PDF
  • Page ID 338933

  Learning Objectives

  • Describe the difference between hypothesis and theory as scientific terms.
  • Describe the difference between a theory and scientific law.

Although many have taken science classes throughout the course of their studies, people often have incorrect or misleading ideas about some of the most important and basic principles in science. Most students have heard of hypotheses, theories, and laws, but what do these terms really mean? Prior to reading this section, consider what you have learned about these terms before. What do these terms mean to you? What do you read that contradicts or supports what you thought?

What is a Fact?

A fact is a basic statement established by experiment or observation. All facts are true under the specific conditions of the observation.

What is a Hypothesis?

One of the most common terms used in science classes is a "hypothesis". The word can have many different definitions, depending on the context in which it is being used:

  • An educated guess: a scientific hypothesis provides a suggested solution based on evidence.
  • Prediction: if you have ever carried out a science experiment, you probably made this type of hypothesis when you predicted the outcome of your experiment.
  • Tentative or proposed explanation: hypotheses can be suggestions about why something is observed. In order for it to be scientific, however, a scientist must be able to test the explanation to see if it works and if it is able to correctly predict what will happen in a situation. For example, "if my hypothesis is correct, we should see ___ result when we perform ___ test."
A hypothesis is very tentative; it can be easily changed.

What is a Theory?

The United States National Academy of Sciences describes what a theory is as follows:

"Some scientific explanations are so well established that no new evidence is likely to alter them. The explanation becomes a scientific theory. In everyday language a theory means a hunch or speculation. Not so in science. In science, the word theory refers to a comprehensive explanation of an important feature of nature supported by facts gathered over time. Theories also allow scientists to make predictions about as yet unobserved phenomena."

"A scientific theory is a well-substantiated explanation of some aspect of the natural world, based on a body of facts that have been repeatedly confirmed through observation and experimentation. Such fact-supported theories are not "guesses" but reliable accounts of the real world. The theory of biological evolution is more than "just a theory." It is as factual an explanation of the universe as the atomic theory of matter (stating that everything is made of atoms) or the germ theory of disease (which states that many diseases are caused by germs). Our understanding of gravity is still a work in progress. But the phenomenon of gravity, like evolution, is an accepted fact.

Note some key features of theories that are important to understand from this description:

  • Theories are explanations of natural phenomena. They aren't predictions (although we may use theories to make predictions). They are explanations as to why we observe something.
  • Theories aren't likely to change. They have a large amount of support and are able to satisfactorily explain numerous observations. Theories can, indeed, be facts. Theories can change, but it is a long and difficult process. In order for a theory to change, there must be many observations or pieces of evidence that the theory cannot explain.
  • Theories are not guesses. The phrase "just a theory" has no room in science. To be a scientific theory carries a lot of weight; it is not just one person's idea about something
Theories aren't likely to change.

What is a Law?

Scientific laws are similar to scientific theories in that they are principles that can be used to predict the behavior of the natural world. Both scientific laws and scientific theories are typically well-supported by observations and/or experimental evidence. Usually scientific laws refer to rules for how nature will behave under certain conditions, frequently written as an equation. Scientific theories are more overarching explanations of how nature works and why it exhibits certain characteristics. As a comparison, theories explain why we observe what we do and laws describe what happens.

For example, around the year 1800, Jacques Charles and other scientists were working with gases to, among other reasons, improve the design of the hot air balloon. These scientists found, after many, many tests, that certain patterns existed in the observations on gas behavior. If the temperature of the gas is increased, the volume of the gas increased. This is known as a natural law. A law is a relationship that exists between variables in a group of data. Laws describe the patterns we see in large amounts of data, but do not describe why the patterns exist.

What is a Belief?

A belief is a statement that is not scientifically provable. Beliefs may or may not be incorrect; they just are outside the realm of science to explore.

Laws vs. Theories

A common misconception is that scientific theories are rudimentary ideas that will eventually graduate into scientific laws when enough data and evidence has accumulated. A theory does not change into a scientific law with the accumulation of new or better evidence. Remember, theories are explanations and laws are patterns we see in large amounts of data, frequently written as an equation. A theory will always remain a theory; a law will always remain a law.

Video \(\PageIndex{1}\): What’s the difference between a scientific law and theory?

  • A hypothesis is a tentative explanation that can be tested by further investigation.
  • A theory is a well-supported explanation of observations.
  • A scientific law is a statement that summarizes the relationship between variables.
  • An experiment is a controlled method of testing a hypothesis.

Contributions & Attributions

Marisa Alviar-Agnew  ( Sacramento City College )

Henry Agnew (UC Davis)

IMAGES

  1. 🏷️ Formulation of hypothesis in research. How to Write a Strong

    hypothesis legal term

  2. How to Write a Hypothesis

    hypothesis legal term

  3. Research Hypothesis: Definition, Types, Examples and Quick Tips

    hypothesis legal term

  4. 15 Hypothesis Examples (2024)

    hypothesis legal term

  5. SOLUTION: How to write research hypothesis

    hypothesis legal term

  6. How to Write a Strong Hypothesis in 6 Simple Steps

    hypothesis legal term

VIDEO

  1. Hypothesis Testing

  2. Part 1 HYPOTHESIS TESTING I Business Statistics I

  3. age and area hypothesis / term 57 / #botanyterms #biology #shorts

  4. Explain the meaning of the term hypothesis as used in inferential statistics

  5. P-Value, Confidence Interval and Significance explained

  6. HYPOTHESIS

COMMENTS

  1. PDF HYPOTHESIS: MEANING, TYPES AND FORMULATION

    An Open Access Journal from The Law Brigade (Publishing) Group 148 JOURNAL OF LEGAL STUDIES AND RESEARCH Volume 6 Issue 6 - ISSN 2455 2437 December 2020 www.thelawbrigade.com MEANING The word hypothesis is made up of two Greek roots which mean that it is some sort of 'sub- statements', for it is the presumptive statement of a proposition, which the investigation seeks

  2. HYPOTHESIS Definition & Meaning

    Definition & Citations: A supposition, assumption, or theory; a theory set up by the prosecution,on a criminal trial, or by the defense, as an explanation of the facts in evidence,and a ground for inferring guilt or innocence, as the case may be, or asindicating a probable or possible motive for the crime. This article contains general legal ...

  3. Hypothesis legal definition of Hypothesis

    During a criminal trial, a hypothesis is a theory set forth by either the prosecution or the defense for the purpose of explaining the facts in evidence. It also serves to set up a ground for an inference of guilt or innocence, or a showing of the most probable motive for a criminal offense. West's Encyclopedia of American Law, edition 2.

  4. Scientific Hypothesis, Theory, Law Definitions

    A hypothesis is an educated guess, based on observation. It's a prediction of cause and effect. Usually, a hypothesis can be supported or refuted through experimentation or more observation. A hypothesis can be disproven but not proven to be true. Example: If you see no difference in the cleaning ability of various laundry detergents, you might ...

  5. PDF Understanding Hypotheses, Predictions, Laws, and Theories

    statement that summarises an observed regularity or pattern in nature. So, by using the term tentative, or trial, law instead of descriptive hypothesis, we can avoid any need to use the term descriptive hypothesis. Table 1 The Status of Different Uses of the Term Hypothesis Use of the term hypothesis Suggested status Causal hypothesis Essential

  6. Definition of HYPOTHESIS • Law Dictionary • TheLaw.com

    Legal definition for HYPOTHESIS: A supposition, assumption, or theory; a theory set up by the prosecution, on a criminal trial, or by the defense, as an explanation of the facts in evidence, and a ground fo

  7. What's the Difference Between a Fact, a Hypothesis, a Theory, and a Law

    A hypothesis is a tentative explanation about an observation that can be tested. It's just a starting point for further investigation. Any one observation usually comes with an array of hypotheses. If you observe that a swan is white, your hypothesis could be that it's painted, or it was bleached by the sun, or its feathers just lack pigment.

  8. Hypothesis, Model, Theory, and Law

    A scientific theory or law represents a hypothesis (or group of related hypotheses) which has been confirmed through repeated testing, almost always conducted over a span of many years. Generally, a theory is an explanation for a set of related phenomena, like the theory of evolution or the big bang theory . The word "law" is often invoked in ...

  9. PDF Hypothesis Formation and Testing in Legal Argument

    Definitions. Hypothesis ≡ tentative assumption made in order to draw out and test its normative, logical or empirical consequences. Hypothetical ≡ an imagined situation that involves a hypothesis; used to help draw out those consequences. In Supreme Court oral arguments, hypotheticals perform an important function.

  10. The Legal Concept of Evidence

    ("Adducing evidence" is the legal term for presenting or producing evidence in court for the purpose of establishing proof.) ... 319; Simon 2004, 2011; Griffin 2013). A hypothesis constructed by the fact-finder may be shaped subconsciously by a prejudicial generalisation or background belief about the accused based on a certain feature, say ...

  11. 1.6: Hypothesis, Theories, and Laws

    What is a Hypothesis? One of the most common terms used in science classes is a "hypothesis". The word can have many different definitions, depending on the context in which it is being used: ... the volume of the gas increased. This is known as a natural law. A law is a relationship that exists between variables in a group of data. Laws ...

  12. Theories, Hypotheses, and Laws

    A scientific hypothesis is an inferred explanation of an observation or research finding; while more exploratory in nature than a theory, it is based on existing scientific knowledge. ... A scientific law is an expression of a mathematical or descriptive relationship observed in nature. Terms you should know . data pieces of information ...

  13. Hypothesis: Meaning, Significance and Types

    Hypothesis should be stated as far as possible in most simple terms so that the same is easily understandable by all concerned. But one must remember that simplicity of hypothesis has nothing to do with its significance. In No Conflict with the Laws of Nature: A good hypothesis does not conflict with any law of nature which is known to be true ...

  14. Theory vs. Hypothesis vs. Law

    A hypothesis is a possible explanation that can be tested. This simple definition needs some further explanation. It says it must have a possible explanation. The hypothesis should apply reasoning ...

  15. 1.3: Hypothesis, Theories, and Laws

    What is a Hypothesis? One of the most common terms used in science classes is a "hypothesis". The word can have many different definitions, depending on the context in which it is being used: ... This is known as a natural law. A law is a relationship that exists between variables in a group of data. Laws describe the patterns we see in large ...

  16. Hypothesis : Legal Research

    Hypothesis : Legal Research01:02- What is Hypothesis?02:42 - Sources of Hypothesis04:23 - Stages in formulation of Hypothesis06:00 - Problems in formulation ...

  17. What is a law in science?

    A law is a statement about an observed phenomenon or a unifying concept, according to Kennesaw State University. "There are four major concepts in science: facts, hypotheses, laws and theories ...

  18. Scientific Law Definition and Examples

    Examples of Scientific Laws. There are laws in all scientific disciplines, although primarily they are physical laws. Here are some examples: Beer's law. Dalton's law of partial pressures. Ideal gas law. Kepler's laws of planetary motion. Law of conservation of mass. Law of conservation of energy.

  19. How to Write a Strong Hypothesis

    5. Phrase your hypothesis in three ways. To identify the variables, you can write a simple prediction in if…then form. The first part of the sentence states the independent variable and the second part states the dependent variable. If a first-year student starts attending more lectures, then their exam scores will improve.

  20. Hypothesis Definition & Meaning

    hypothesis: [noun] an assumption or concession made for the sake of argument. an interpretation of a practical situation or condition taken as the ground for action.

  21. Scientific hypothesis

    hypothesis. science. scientific hypothesis, an idea that proposes a tentative explanation about a phenomenon or a narrow set of phenomena observed in the natural world. The two primary features of a scientific hypothesis are falsifiability and testability, which are reflected in an "If…then" statement summarizing the idea and in the ...

  22. Dark forest hypothesis

    The dark forest hypothesis is the conjecture that many alien civilizations exist throughout the universe, but they are both silent and hostile, maintaining their undetectability for fear of being destroyed by another hostile and undetected civilization. It is one of many possible explanations of the Fermi paradox, which contrasts the lack of contact with alien life with the potential for such ...

  23. "Arrest me!": J.K. Rowling posts anti-trans rant, responding to

    J.K. Rowling posts anti-trans rant, responding to Scottish hate crime law Rowling stated that she "looked forward to being arrested" if her post violated "the terms of the new act"

  24. Why abuse of the Insurrection Act worries legal experts and how they'd

    A bipartisan group of legal experts is sounding an alarm about presidential power this election season. They're pushing Congress to update a cluster of laws known as the Insurrection Act and limit ...

  25. 1.5: Hypothesis, Theories, and Laws

    What is a Hypothesis? One of the most common terms used in science classes is a "hypothesis". The word can have many different definitions, depending on the context in which it is being used: ... the volume of the gas increased. This is known as a natural law. A law is a relationship that exists between variables in a group of data. Laws ...

  26. Florida Governor Ron DeSantis and Disney end legal dispute

    The law, dubbed "Don't Say Gay" by critics, restricts how sexual orientation and gender identity are discussed in the schools. Disney's former CEO Bob Chapek spoke out against the law and said he ...

  27. Radio Free Asia Leaves Hong Kong, Citing Security Law

    Radio Free Asia, which ran a small operation in Hong Kong, said its staff was at risk because of the law's sweeping definition of "external interference." Share full article 27

  28. Netanyahu says he will temporarily shut down Al Jazeera news ...

    Israel's parliament approved a law on Monday that would allow the government to temporarily shut down the Al Jazeera news network in Israel.

  29. Transgender judge seeks leave to intervene in UK court case over legal

    It argues that Haldane's inclusive definition of "sex" leaves service providers of single-sex spaces "confused and … at risk of legal action for unlawful discrimination".

  30. 1.1: Hypothesis, Theories, and Laws

    What is a Hypothesis? One of the most common terms used in science classes is a "hypothesis". The word can have many different definitions, depending on the context in which it is being used: ... the volume of the gas increased. This is known as a natural law. A law is a relationship that exists between variables in a group of data. Laws ...