SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Pierre Duhem

Pierre Duhem (1861–1916) was a French physicist and historian and philosopher of science. As a physicist, he championed “energetics,” holding generalized thermodynamics as foundational for physical theory, that is, thinking that all of chemistry and physics, including mechanics, electricity, and magnetism, should be derivable from thermodynamic first principles. In philosophy of science, he is best known for his work on the relation between theory and experiment, arguing that hypotheses are not straightforwardly refuted by experiment and that there are no crucial experiments in science. In history of science, he produced massive groundbreaking work in medieval science and defended a thesis of continuity between medieval and early modern science.

1. Life and Works

2.1 against “newtonian method”: the duhem thesis, 2.2 against “cartesian method”: metaphysics and models, 2.3 later developments, 3. history of science, primary sources, secondary sources, other internet resources, related entries.

Pierre Maurice Marie Duhem was born on June 10, 1861, in Paris, in a modest neighborhood on the Rue des Jeûneurs, near the Grands Boulevards, just South of Montmartre. His father, Pierre-Joseph Duhem, was of Flemish origin, the oldest child of a large family who lived in the French northern industrial city of Roubaix, near the Belgian border. After the death of his parents, Pierre-Joseph was forced to discontinue his studies with the Jesuits in order to provide for the family. He worked in the textile industry as a sales representative, but never abandoned his love of learning; it is said that, late in life, he was seen everywhere with the work of a Latin author under his arm. Pierre Duhem’s mother, Marie-Alexandrine Fabre, descended on her mother’s side from the Hubault-Delormes, a bourgeois family who had settled in Paris during the seventeenth century. Her father’s family had originally come from the southern town of Cabesprine, near Carcasonne, and it was there, in a house they still maintained and to which Pierre returned most summers, that he died on September 14, 1916.

The Duhems made sure that Pierre was well educated. Starting at the age of seven he was given private lessons with a small group of students, on grammar, arithmetic, Latin, and catechism. A letter he wrote about the siege of Chateaudun he experienced in October 1870 attests to his being already a literate writer by the age of nine. The young Duhem was witness to some troubling times, with the Franco-Prussian War raging until the armistice in February 1871 and the Paris Commune in March. The Duhems had avoided the advance of the Prussians against Paris but were caught up in the siege of Chateaudun; they barely escaped to Bordeaux, returning to Paris after the armistice and just before the Paris Commune. That social experiment lasted only two months, though it set the stage for some wide-ranging transformations to French culture that were to have great consequences when they were later established permanently. Among the Commune’s decrees were the separation of church from state, the rendering of all church property into public property, and the exclusion of religion from schools. The Duhems did not approve of these measures and were particularly chagrined by some of the extreme actions taken by the most radical elements of the Commune, such as the desecration of churches and graveyards. For the Duhems, the Commune was a paradigm of anarchy and irreligion.

The Fall of 1872 brought two great tragedies to the Duhem family: a diphtheria epidemic killed Pierre’s younger sister Antoinette and his recently born brother Jean, leaving only Pierre and Antoinette’s twin sister Marie. Pierre continued his education (as demi-pensionnaire ) at a Catholic school, the Collège Stanislas in Paris, in 1872 and for the next ten years. The mature Duhem recalled his college days as most formative. In particular, he singled out his science teacher as an important influence:

Let us return to some twenty-five years back to the time when we received our first initiation as a physicist in the mathematics classes of the Collège Stanislas. The person who gave us this initiation, Jules Moutier, was an ingenious theorist; his critical sense, ever aware and extremely perspicacious, distinguished with sure accuracy the weak point of many a system that others accepted without dispute; proofs of his inquiring mind are not lacking, and physical chemistry owes him one of its most important laws. It was this teacher who planted in us our admiration for physical theory and the desire to contribute to its progress. … Being a disciple of Moutier, it was as a convinced partisan of mechanism that we approached the courses in physics pursued at the Ecole Normale. (1914, 417–18; 1954, 275–76.)

Duhem’s science teacher Jules Moutier went on to teach at the Ecole Polytechnique and to publish a number of texts, including La thermodynamique et ses principales applications (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1885). Duhem recognized in his theory of chemical dissociation and in his thermodynamics generally a first enunciation of the chemical theories that Josiah Willard Gibbs, an important later influence on Duhem, was to develop more fully.

In 1882 Duhem enrolled at the prestigious secular institution of higher education, the Ecole Normale Supérieure. When he entered the Ecole Normale he was first in his class in the Science Section, out of the approximately 30 students chosen from the best 800 or so graduates in France that year, and he remained first throughout his years there. The curriculum at the Ecole Normale usually lasted three years; Duhem was granted a fourth year and stayed on a fifth year as agrégé préparateur . He received a license in mathematics and another in physics at the end of academic year 1883–84. In his final year, Duhem was offered a position in Louis Pasteur’s laboratory as a chemist-bacteriologist, though he refused it because of his desire to work in theoretical physics.

One of the turning points in Duhem’s career occurred during academic year 1884–85, while he was only a third-year student. Duhem presented a thesis in physics for his doctorate. The thesis, on thermodynamic potential, Le potentiel thermodynamique et ses applications à la mécanique chimique et à l’étude des phénomènes électriques , was rejected by a panel composed of three scholars: the physicist Gabriel Lippmann and the mathematicians Charles Hermite and Emile Picard. The panel, chaired by Lippmann, seems to have made a political decision. The prestigious French scientific publisher, Hermann, published a version of the thesis the following year. Duhem defended another thesis in applied mathematics, on the theory of magnetization by induction, Sur l’aimantation par influence , and received his doctorate in October 1888; this time, the physicist Edmond Bouty, the mathematician Gaston Darboux, and the mathematician-physicist Henri Poincaré constituted the panel that accepted the dissertation. It would be difficult to understand fully these events without delving deeply into the social, cultural, and intellectual context of France at the end of the nineteenth century. At a time when French scientists were predominantly liberal and anti-clerical, Duhem was openly conservative and deeply religious; he was also stubborn and often contentious. The structure of French academia was surely also a factor in the affair. However, the specific motives generally cited in the case were Lipmann’s “jealousy” and the fact that Duhem’s thesis refuted the principle of maximum work: that chemical changes tend spontaneously to produce maximum heat. It was one of the cherished theses of Marcellin Berthelot, Lippmann’s friend and a significant power in the French scientific establishment. It was reported that Berthelot had said: “This young man will never teach in Paris.” Berthelot’s edict came true. Duhem spent his academic career in provincial universities far from Paris, the center of academic life in France. His teaching positions brought him from Lille, then briefly to Rennes, then to Bordeaux for the remainder of his life, but never to Paris.

Duhem assumed the position of Maitre de Conférences at the Faculté des Sciences at Lille in October 1887. There he met Adèle Chayet, whom he married in October 1890. Their daughter Hélène was born in September 1891. Tragically, Adèle died in childbirth the following summer; the newborn child also did not survive. Duhem never remarried. He left the upbringing of Hélène to his mother who lived with him after his father Pierre-Joseph died. The situation in Lille soured for Duhem. Never one to back off from a dispute, he fought with the Dean of his faculty over a minor issue: an assistant had failed to unlock the door of Duhem’s laboratory for his students during their licentiate examinations. The assistant complained about his mistreatment by Duhem to the Dean, who requested that the assistant write a letter of apology; Duhem rejected the apology and took issue with the Dean, who then brought the matter to the Rector, adding further complaints against Duhem. The minor issue having escalated to immense proportions, Duhem requested and received a change of positions at the end of academic year 1893. During these formative years, Duhem worked very hard on his science. He published six books: a two-volume work on hydrodynamics, elasticity, and acoustics, his lectures on electricity and magnetism, in three volumes, and an introduction to physical chemistry. Duhem was one of the first to appreciate the work of W. J. Gibbs, writing the earliest critical examination of Gibbs’ “On the Equilibrium of Heterogeneous Substances” in 1887 and later promoting the French translation of Gibbs’ works (Duhem 1907); for an English translation of Duhem’s 1887 essay on Gibbs and his Commentaries on the Principles of Thermodynamics, 1892–1894, see Duhem [CPT].

In October 1893, Duhem left Lille for Rennes. He lasted only one year, leaving for Bordeaux in October 1894. He was hoping for a position in Paris. The prodigious quantity and quality of his publications in many fields of science, the philosophy of science, and the history of science were not able to change his situation. Very late in life, he was approached about the newly created chair in the History of Science at the Collège de France, but he refused to be a candidate for it. The proud and stubborn Duhem told his daughter: “I am a theoretical physicist. Either I will teach theoretical physics at Paris or else I will not go there.”

Duhem’s curriculum vitae, written in 1913, on the occasion of his nomination as non-resident member of the Académie des Sciences (1917, 41–70), lists over 350 items, about 50 of which were books. From the mid-1880s to 1900, Duhem’s primary interests were scientific, ranging from thermodynamics and physics, but publishing on elasticity and energetics as late as 1911. In the 1890s, while still at Lille, he began writing essays on questions of methodology that would lead to the publication of his most influential books in the philosophy of science, translated into English as The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory and To Save the Phenomena . It was also in the mid-1890s that Duhem published his first essays in the history of science, starting on the path that would lead him in 1904 to a new understanding of the history of science and to his thesis of continuity between medieval and early modern science. This path would culminate in such important historical works as Études sur Léonard de Vinci and Le système du monde .

Duhem made a number of enduring contributions to thermodynamics and physical chemistry. Among these were the Duhem–Margules and Gibbs–Duhem equations, which deal with reversible processes in thermodynamics as quasi-static limiting processes and give a general proof of the Gibbs phase rule. These results were obtained in the context of a program of generalized thermodynamics called “energetics.” Indeed, Duhem’s entire scientific program was driven by the conviction that a generalized thermodynamics should be foundational for physical theory, thinking that all of chemistry and physics, including mechanics, electricity and magnetism, should be derivable from thermodynamic first principles. Duhem started from the concept of the thermodynamic potential (the topic of his failed thesis), deploying it in a manner similar to that of potentials in mechanics, so as to represent all physical and chemical changes. The program finds its mature statement in his Traité d’énergétique of 1911; it was well received by late-nineteenth-century energeticists, such as Wilhelm Ostwald and Georg Helm. So important was energetics for Duhem, that his work in the history and philosophy of science has been viewed as an attempt to defend its aims and methods (see Lowinger 1941). More recently, Niall Martin and others have argued for the importance of religious motives in Duhem’s work (see Martin 1991, Jaki 1991) and it has become clear in the course of Duhem’s writings that he expected the endpoint of science to harmonize with the teachings of the Catholic Church.

Whatever was Duhem’s initial motivation, his historical and philosophical work took on a life of its own. One cannot read Duhem’s numerous historical and philosophical tomes and think that his labor was only in the service of energetics and that the sole goal of his works was but a defense of its methods and its historical position. No doubt energetics might be a thread running through Duhem’s various works, and no doubt these works harmonize with the method of energetics as he conceives it, but energetics cannot be the whole story.

2. Philosophy of Science

Duhem’s early methodological views reflected late nineteenth-century positivism: Physical theory was no more than an aid to memory, summarizing and classifying facts by providing a symbolic representation of them; the facts of physical theory are different from common sense and metaphysics, especially from the mechanical theories fashionable at the time. Duhem’s position was immediately attacked by a Catholic engineer, Eugène Vicaire, on the grounds that separating physics from metaphysics implied that physics was the only real knowledge (another positivistic thesis), and thus conceded too much to skepticism. Vicaire raised an important point for turn-of-the-century Catholics because the Church was officially committed to neo-Thomism, with its generally rationalist apologetics (see Martin 1991, chap. 2). In his reply Duhem adopted a quasi-Thomist position: metaphysics is a real form of knowledge, more excellent than physics, but separated from it in that it has different objects and is governed by different methods. This immediate response fitted reasonably well into the framework of neo-Thomism, though it did not go as far as to reunite the disparate forms of knowledge into a hierarchical system of sciences including cosmology and metaphysics. Duhem’s mature position was somewhat different, containing three key ideas elaborated upon on various occasions: (1) the underdetermination of theory by fact, often referred to as the Duhem Thesis, (2) the rejection of metaphysics and models in physics, and (3) natural classification as the endpoint of physical theory.

Duhem’s work was important for members of the Vienna Circle, including Otto Neurath and Philipp Frank, as it had been for Ernst Mach (for a comparison between Duhem and Mach on thought experiments and conventionalism, see Buzzoni 2015). Despite Duhem’s conservative beliefs, his work was also taken up by participants in the Viennese political scene, such as Friedrich Adler, who had translated La théorie physique into German in 1908. The Duhem thesis surfaced fully in Anglo-American philosophy in the 1950s through the work of W. V. O. Quine. In Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” the second dogma is reductionism, the belief that “each meaningful statement is equivalent to some construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience” (1953, 20). Quine argues that reductionism is an ill-founded dogma. He asserts that although reductionism has ceased to figure in some empiricists’ thoughts, there remains a more subtle form of reductionism that each statement taken in isolation can admit confirmation or disconfirmation. Against this dogma Quine suggests that “our statements about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individually, but only as a corporate body” (1953, 41), and, in a footnote of the reprinted article in his collected essays, From a Logical Point of View , says that the doctrine was well argued by Pierre Duhem. Quine proceeds to detail an “empiricism without the dogmas” in which knowledge is to be likened to a field of force where “a conflict with experience at the periphery occasions readjustments in the interior of the field” (1953, 42), and “any statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system” (1953, 43). Because of Quine’s reference to Duhem, the thesis formed from the two sub-theses, that (i) since empirical statements are interconnected, they cannot be singly disconfirmed, and (ii), if we wish to hold a particular statement true we can always adjust another statement, has become known as the Duhem-Quine thesis.The antecedent of sub-thesis (i) is often referred to as “holism.” Quine attributes only sub-thesis (i) to Duhem; Duhem would have recognized sub-thesis (i) as an offspring of his, but would not have fully agreed with it as formulated by Quine.

Duhem does not claim that when there is some conflict with experience, we can always make enough adjustments elsewhere in the system. He makes a weaker claim, also limited in other ways, but which would be equivalent to: when there is some conflict with experience what is disconfirmed is necessarily ambiguous. Duhem’s formulation of his non-falsifiability thesis is that “if the predicted phenomenon is not produced, not only is the questioned proposition put into doubt, but also the whole theoretical scaffolding used by the physicist” (1914, 281; 1954, 185). He does not take the second Quinean step of holding any statement true come what may, but says “the only thing the experiment teaches us is that, among all the propositions used to predict the phenomenon and to verify that it has not been produced, there is at least one error; but where the error lies is just what the experiment does not tell us” (1914, 281; 1954, 185). He refers to two possible ways of proceeding when an experiment contradicts the consequences of a theory: a timid scientist might wish to safeguard certain fundamental hypotheses and attempt to complicate matters by invoking various cases of error and multiplying the corrections, while a bolder scientist can resolve to change some of the essential suppositions supporting the entire system (1914, 329; 1954, 216–17). The scientist has no guarantee of success: “If they both succeed in satisfying the requirements of the experiment, each is logically permitted to declare himself content with the work he has accomplished” (1914, 330; 1954, 217).

Moreover, Duhem does not argue directly for the non-falsifiability thesis. He seems to regard it as an obvious corollary of another thesis, which could be called the non-separability thesis, that the physicist can never submit an isolated hypothesis to experimental test: “To seek to separate each of the hypotheses of theoretical physics from the other assumptions upon which this science rests, in order to subject it in isolation to the control of observation, is to pursue a chimera” (1914, 303; 1954, 199–200).

The Duhemian thesis usually makes its appearance in the context of Duhem’s critique of the inductive method (or what he calls the Newtonian method), which rejects any hypothesis about imperceptible bodies and hidden movements and admits only general laws known by induction from observation. Duhem accuses this method of being unmanageable; he asserts that a science can only follow the Newtonian method when its means of knowing are those of common sense: “When science no longer observes facts directly but substitutes for them measurements, given by instruments, of magnitudes that mathematical theory alone defines, induction can no longer be practiced in the manner that the Newtonian method requires,” (1917, 153; [EHPS, 234]). He clearly indicates that some sciences can use the Newtonian method, derive their principles by induction from observation and disconfirm them as tests warrant. What Duhem thinks is wrong with inductivism is that it cannot be used by all sciences. For Duhem the non-falsifiability thesis is a consequence of the non-separability thesis, and the non-separability thesis is an empirical thesis depending upon factors that do not govern all sciences. This is supported as well by Duhem’s assertions, in La théorie physique , that he is imposing narrow limits on his inquiry, and is restricting his generalizations to physics; when he first announces the non-separability thesis, he announces it as a principle about what physicists do, whose consequences will be developed in the remainder of the book.

It is not generally known that Duhem in his lifetime confronted an extension of his thesis in the fashion of Quine and had previously rejected it. In the 1913 essay entitled “Examen logique de la théorie physique,” republished as part II of the overview of all his work, Duhem sketched the set of theses constituting the Duhem thesis and stated:

Separated from the various schools of Pragmatists on the subject of the value of physical theory, we do not take our stand, in any circumstance, among the number of their followers. The analysis we have given of experiments in physics shows fact to be completely interpenetrated by theoretical interpretation, to the point where it becomes impossible to express fact in isolation from theory, in such experiments. This analysis has found great favor on the side of many Pragmatists. They have extended it to the most diverse fields: to history, to exegesis, to theology. (1917, 156 [EHPS, 237])

Thus, already by 1913, the scope of Duhem’s thesis had been stretched beyond Duhem’s intentions. “The several authors we have just cited often draw from this analysis of the experimental method used in physics conclusions which go beyond the boundaries of physics; we shall not follow them that far, but shall stay always within the limits of physical science” (1914, 218n; 1954, 144n). While Duhem did not identify these authors, these “pragmatists,” as early as 1905, in a footnote of La théorie physique , he asserts that some of his friends and acquaintances and, in particular, Gaston Milhaud, Edouard Le Roy, and Joseph Wilbois had adopted his analysis of experimental method, as discussed in his earlier articles (1914, 217–218n; 1954, 144n). And these same thinkers, together with Duhem’s very good friend, Maurice Blondel, were referred to favorably as “French pragmatists” by William James in 1907 in his Lectures on Pragmatism : “If my lectures interest any reader in the general subject, he will doubtless wish to read farther. I therefore give him a few references. … Furthermore, see J. Milhaud, Le Rationnel , 1898, and the fine articles by Le Roy in the Revue de Metaphysique , vols. 7, 8, and 9. Also articles by Blondel and de Sailly in the Annales de Philosophie Chrétienne , 4eme Série, vols. 2 and 3. Papini announces a book on Pragmatism, in the French language, to be published very soon” (James, 1981, 3; a quick glance at Milhaud’s Le Rationnel reveals numerous references to Duhem). Thus the Duhem thesis in its extended form was favorably received in the Anglophone world during the first few decades of the twentieth century, well before Quine’s reference to it. Duhem’s reaction to the extension of his thesis was as follows:

We do not deny that this extension is legitimate to some extent. However different the problems may be, it is always the same human intellect that exerts itself to resolve them. In the same way, there is always something common in the several procedures reason employs. But if it is good to notice the analogies between our diverse scientific methods, it is on condition that we do not forget the differences separating them. And, when we compare the method of physics, so strangely specialized in the application of mathematical theory and by the use of measuring instruments, to other methods, there are surely more differences to describe than analogies to discover. (1917, 156 [EHPS, 237])

In the overview of all his scholarly works in the document supporting his candidacy for membership to the Académie des Sciences Duhem contrasted the methodology of energetics with the two leading methodologies at the time, what he called the method of the Cartesians and that of the Newtonians. We have discussed his critique of the Newtonians; we now turn to that of the Cartesians. The salient feature of energetics was that “the principles it embodies and from which it derives conclusions do not at all aspire to resolve the bodies we perceive or the motions we report into imperceptible bodies or hidden motions” (1917, 151 [EHPS, 232]). What energetics offered was a formal theory, with the character of logical system, which instead of reducing physical qualities in the manner of mechanistic theories, limited itself to marking by means of a numerical scale the various intensities of such qualities. Duhem’s critique of mechanistic theories (or the method of Cartesians and atomists) was that they are not autonomous:

The physicist who wishes to follow them can no longer use the methods proper to physics exclusively. … Here he enters the domain of cosmology. He no longer has the right to shut his ears to what metaphysics wishes to tell him about the real nature of matter; hence, as a consequence, through dependence on metaphysical cosmology, his physics suffers from all the uncertainties and vicissitudes of that doctrine. Theories constructed by the method of the Cartesians and atomists are also condemned to infinite multiplication and to perpetual reformulation. They do not appear to be in any state to assure consensus and continual progress to science. (1917, 152 [EHPS, 233–34])

For Duhem, the contemporary scientist who exemplified the method of the “Cartesians” was James Clerk Maxwell. Duhem issued three interconnected complaints against Maxwell’s work: (i) Maxwell’s theory is overly bold or not systematic enough; (ii) it is too dependent on models; and (iii) its concepts are not continuous with those of the past.

The justification Duhem gives for the accusation of extreme boldness is that:

When a physicist discovers facts unknown until then, when his experiments have allowed him to formulate new laws that the theory had not foreseen, he must first try with the greatest care to represent these laws, to the required degree of approximation, as consequences of admitted hypotheses. Only after having acquired the certainty that the magnitudes treated until now by the theory cannot serve as symbols for the observed quantities, that received hypotheses cannot flow from the established laws, is he authorized to enrich physics with a new magnitude, to complicate it with a new hypothesis (1902, 7).

According to Duhem, the founders of electrodynamics—Coulomb, Poisson, and Ampere—followed these principles, but Maxwell did not. Duhem cites with approbation Ampere’s attempt to represent the attraction or repulsion of currents in wires using Coulomb’s formula. He also praises the fact that Ampere abandoned the attempt only after experimental facts about the magneto-optical rotation, discovered by Faraday, showed clearly that Ampere could not succeed in the attempt. But, again, according to Duhem, Maxwell does not follow these principles. In fact, he goes so far as to accuse Maxwell of following the “inverse path”:

At the moment when Maxwell introduced a new magnitude in electrodynamics, the displacement currents, at the moment when he marked, as essential hypotheses, the mathematical form of the laws to which this magnitude should be submitted, no properly observed phenomenon required this extension of the theory of currents; that theory was sufficient for representing, if not all phenomena known until then, at least all those whose experimental study had achieved a sufficient degree of clearness. No logical necessity pressed Maxwell to imagine a new electrodynamics. (1902, 8.)

As a result, Maxwell reversed “with an incredible rashness” the natural order according to which physical theory evolves—he broke with the past before he needed to.

Duhem is well known for his attack on the use of models in physical science. At first, it seems that Duhem tries to link his attack on model building with his espousal of instrumentalism for the physical sciences. He accuses the English scientists of believing that “to understand physical phenomena is to compose a model” (1914, 103; 1954, 71–72) and of “confusing model with theory” (1913, 102; 1954, 71). He specifically blames Maxwell of these misunderstandings, indicating that in his 1855–56 essay Maxwell proposed only “to illustrate” the theory of dielectrics, whereas in his 1861–62 essay he proposed “to represent or to explain” the electrical and magnetic actions by a mechanical model. Duhem even seems scornful of Maxwell’s interchangeable use of the verbs “to represent” and “to explain.” He states, “for an English physicist, the two words have the same meaning” (1902, 9).

For Duhem there is a crucial difference between representing and explaining. He divides theories into two large categories, explanatory and purely representative theories, and argues that physical theories should not be considered as explanatory, but as purely representative or classificatory. The argument, as we have seen, is that, in order for physical theory to be explanatory, it would have to be subordinate to metaphysics and not autonomous. The reference to the two words having the same meaning for Maxwell and English scientists is thus a reference to what Duhem would consider a confusion about the aim of physical theory, one that arises in the identification of the model with the theory, in thinking that what is represented by the theory and/or model is real.

But Duhem broadens the critique of model building to include mathematical models along with mechanical models. He decides that, for an English scientist, theory is “for him neither an explanation nor a rational classification of physical laws, but a model of these laws, a model not built for the satisfying of reason but for the pleasure of the imagination” (1914, 117; 1954, 81). The complaint is clear: model building has no real place in physical theory (beyond a minor heuristic role); it can neither be grounded in realism, in the thought that physical theories are explanatory structures, nor in instrumentalism, in the thought that physical theories are classificatory or representative structures. In fact, model building is not even connected to the higher intellectual faculty of reason but to the lower faculty of imagination. So, ultimately, Duhem’s attack on model building is rooted in something more fundamental than his instrumentalist methodology for the physical sciences.

Duhem banishes model building from physical theory (as he previously banished Maxwell’s rashness) because model building breaks with historical continuity; in fact, model building is not only historically non-continuous, but present models are even often “non-continuous” among themselves. Some model builders even find pleasure in building two or more models of the same law. The fact that the English physicist can accept disparate models, breaking up the historical continuity of science and even its present unification, is what shocks Duhem; it is what reconfirms for him that English physics is not the work of reason, but the work of imagination.

A principle of historical continuity is invoked in the conclusion of Duhem’s primary work on Maxwell. Duhem evaluates there an interpretation of Maxwell’s work he attributes to Heaviside, Hertz, and Cohn, among others. He quotes Hertz as stating that: “what is essential in Maxwell’s theories is Maxwell’s equations.” He takes this to be Hertz’s way of salvaging what is valuable in Maxwell from the midst of logical errors and incoherence, which are not only difficult to correct, but which have frustrated many illustrious mathematicians. But Duhem cannot accept Hertz’s implied criterion of identity for physical theories. He asserts that he might accept such a criterion for algebra but “a physicist is not an algebraist”:

An equation does not simply bear on letters; such letters symbolize physical magnitudes which must be either measurable experimentally or formed from other measurable magnitudes. Therefore, if a physicist is given only an equation, he is not taught anything. To this equation must be joined rules by which the letters that the equation bears upon are made to correspond to the physical magnitudes they represent. And that which allows us to know these rules is the set of hypotheses and arguments by which one has arrived at the equations in question. [The set of rules] is the theory that the equations summarize in a symbolic form: in physics, an equation, detached from the theory that leads to it, has no meaning . (1902, 223.)

Duhem proceeds to detail two complete theories that can recover Maxwell’s equations within a logical and coherent structure, the theories of Boltzmann and Helmholtz. The only criterion he gives for choosing between these two theories, though without elaborating upon it or justifying it, is that Helmholtz’s theory is to be preferred over Boltzmann’s theory because it is a natural “extension of the doctrines of Poisson, Ampere, Weber, and Newmann; it leads logically from the principles posited at the start of the nineteenth century to the most seductive consequences of Maxwell’s theories, from the laws of Coulomb to the electromagnetic theory of light; [it does so] without losing any of the recent victories of electrical science; it reestablishes the continuity of tradition” (1902, 225).

Duhem does not attempt to justify his criterion of historical continuity in his study of Maxwell, perhaps because he previously broached the question. In an early methodological article, he asserts:

IF WE RESTRICT OURSELVES TO INVOKING CONSIDERATIONS OF PURE LOGIC, we cannot prevent a physicist from representing different sets of laws, or even a single group of laws, by several irreconcilable theories. We cannot condemn incoherence in the development of physical theory . (1893, 366 and elsewhere; [EHPS, 66])

Thus historical continuity as a consideration falls outside of pure logic and outside reasons of physics proper, but deals with the relation between physics and metaphysics, what Duhem calls “metaphysical cosmology.” Surprisingly, if one considers him as an instrumentalist, for Duhem, we must judge a physical theory in comparison to an ideal and perfect theory that provides the total and adequate metaphysical explanation of the nature of material things, that is, the natural classification of laws. (For more on Duhem on natural classification and conventionalism, see Dion 2013, Dion 2017, and Ivanova 2015.) For that reason, a coherent physical theory is more perfect than an incoherent set of incompatible theories. Elaborating upon this point and commenting upon the connection between cosmology—that is, metaphysics, natural classification, or the ideal form of physical theory—and physical theory itself, Duhem asserts:

It is not enough for cosmologists to know very accurately the doctrines of contemporary theoretical physics; they must also know past doctrines. In fact, current theory need not be analogous with cosmology, but with the ideal theory toward which current theory tends by a continual progress. Therefore, it is not up to philosophers to compare physics as it is now with their cosmology, by congealing science in some manner at a precise moment of its evolution, but rather to appreciate the development of theory and to surmise the goal toward which it is directed. Now, nothing can guide them safely in conjecturing the path that physics will follow if not the knowledge of the road it has already covered. (1914, 460; 1954, 303.)

Duhem supports this statement using an analogy with the trajectory of a ball. We cannot guess its end point with an instant glance at the ball, but we can prolong its trajectory if we followed the ball from the moment it was struck. So we cannot guess the end point of physical theory, the natural classification, by looking at any particular theory. We must appeal to the trajectory of physical theory, to its history, to enable us to tell whether any particular theory is likely to contribute toward the ultimate natural classification. Duhem’s doctrine of natural classification provides the grounds for various commentators to argue that Duhem is not an instrumentalist, that his philosophy of science considered as a whole looks more like convergent or motivational realism (see Maiocchi in Ariew and Barker 1990 and others).

As presented so far, Duhem is a philosopher who weaves together two large patchworks of theses: (i) instrumentalism or fictionalism, anti-atomism or anti-Cartesianism, anti-modelism, and autonomy of physics from metaphysics and (ii) anti-inductivism or critique of Newtonian method, the Duhem thesis, that is, non-falsifiability and non-separability. Both sets of theses are intended as empirical theses about the workings of science and both are important to understanding Duhem’s thought. The first set of theses effectively demarcates physical theory as an autonomous domain apart from other domains, that is, rejects any external method, and the second set then operates on the internal workings of physical theory. Having set apart physical theory, Duhem asserts that no internal method leads inexorably to the truth.

For Duhem, there are always at least two basic ways of proceeding in science. Some scientists prefer the clutter of concrete details and thus do not mind ad hoc explanations, complications, and corrected theories; others prefer abstract, simple, and uncomplicated theories, even if they are gotten at the price of conceptual novelty. As we have seen, Duhem discusses this dichotomy under the rubric of the English mind and the French mind—what he also calls “esprit de finesse” and “esprit de géométrie,” following Blaise Pascal. Despite the labels “English” and “French,” Duhem’s categories are analytic ones, not mere epithets to be used rhetorically against his adversaries. In fact, from the start, when he described the broad-shallow English mind, his archetype was Napoleon Bonaparte, a great genius of military details—not an Englishman. Duhem’s ideal of the narrow-deep French mind was Newton, the geometer of physics—not a Frenchman. Thus, when Duhem accused Faraday and Maxwell of having English minds, he did so by trying to establish something about how they conducted their science, not by referring to their ancestry.

In his last work, La science allemande , mostly a work of wartime propaganda, Duhem added a third kind of mind to his original two, namely, the German mind. If there are two basic types, the French mind and the English mind, then what could the German mind possibly be? Citing Pascal, Duhem tells us that truth requires both reason and argument— raison and raisonnement . Logic, or our ability to link propositions with one another, allows us to deduce one truth from another; but that ability, by itself, merely gets us back to first principles or axioms. We also need a faculty that allows us to intuit the truth of the first principles or axioms, that is, bon sens (good sense). Bon sens is to “esprit de finesse” what “pure logic” is to “esprit de géométrie.” Moreover, bon sens , our faculty of recognizing fundamental truth gets perfected by the practice of history, by our becoming more aware of the failures and successes of previous theories, by thinking about the trajectory of scientific theories, rather than by considering a single theory frozen in time. The dual scheme can now be expanded. We need logic, the ability to systematize, but we also need intuition, the recognition of truth. When one of these is allowed to dominate, we get a science which is all intuition, all “esprit de finesse,” but no logical coherence, namely, English science; or we get a science which is all logic, lacking bon sens, namely, German science. German science then is a degenerate kind of French science, the latter being predominantly “esprit de géométrie,” corrected by bon sens .

As a result, we can talk about a continuum of sciences; at one extreme on the theoretical side is German science, or logicism, and at the other extreme on the experimental side is English science, or crude modelism. In the middle is French science, which allegedly tempers the logical bent with historicism.

In a well-known chapter of Social Theory and Social Structure , the sociologist of science Robert Merton refers to Duhem’s critique of German science as one of the many polemics against national kinds affirming a universalistic standard: “Dispassionate scientists impugned ‘enemy’ contributions, charging nationalistic bias, log-rolling, intellectual dishonesty, incompetence, and lack of creative capacity. Yet this very deviation from the norm of universalism actually presupposed the legitimacy of the norm. For nationalistic bias is opprobrious only if judged in terms of the standard of universalism… Thus by the very process of condemning their violation, the mores are reaffirmed” (1968, 8).

At first glance Duhem’s polemics against German science might seem to arise from a universalistic standard. Duhem does talk at times of a perfect form of science, one without personal or national character: “Quite often the great masters possess a reason in which all the faculties are so harmoniously proportioned that their very perfect doctrines are exempt from all individual character, as from all national character. … In such works one no longer sees the genius of this or that people, but only the genius of Humanity” (1915, 105 [EHPS, 253]). Such perfection for Duhem is an equilibrium of disparate elements, not itself a single ideal type. Duhem might regret what he sees as an overabundance of esprit de géométrie in German science, and might wish that it be tempered by a bit more finesse, but there is no suggestion in Duhem that there is only one way to proceed in science.

Duhem specifically states that the

perfect form of science could not be obtained except by a very precise separation of the various methods concurring in the discovery of truth. Each of the many faculties that human reason puts into play when it wishes to know more and better would have to play its role, without anything being omitted, without any faculty being overlooked. This perfect equilibrium between the many organs of reason does not occur in any one man. In each of us one faculty is stronger and another weaker. In the conquest of truth the weaker will not contribute as much as it should and the stronger will take on more than its share. (1915, 104 [EHPS, 252]).

At bottom, despite his talk of ideal type and equilibrium, Duhem’s science is not universalistic. The strength of his analysis is that there is no single direction within science that each individual must follow. For that, one would need to ground physics in a particular metaphysics—which Duhem explicitly rejects with his instrumentalism—or rather, to be guided by what one projects metaphysics will look like over the long run. Unfortunately, Duhem took this last thought too rigidly and ultimately condemned all innovations as breaking with the past, either due to an excess of esprit de géométrie , as with non-Euclidean geometry and relativity, or an excess of esprit de finesse , as with electron theory. But his philosophy of science itself contained the seeds of scientific pluralism, which are the foundations of the Duhem thesis, that is, the thought that there are many legitimate and disparate ways of proceeding in science.

Duhem’s famous critique of crucial experiments follows a similar pattern. Duhem argues that crucial experiments resemble false dilemmas: hypotheses in physics do not come in pairs, so that crucial experiments cannot transform one of the two into a demonstrated truth. For example, the Newtonian emission theory predicts that light travels faster in water than in air; according to the wave theory, light travels slower in water than in air. Dominique François Arago proposed a crucial experiment comparing the respective velocities. Léon Foucault then devised an apparatus to measure the speed of light in various media and found a lower velocity in water than in air. Arago and Foucault concluded for the wave theory, thinking that the experiment refuted the emission theory. Discussing Foucault’s experiment, Duhem asks whether we dare assert that no other hypothesis is imaginable and suggests that instead of light being either a simple particle or wave, it might be something else, perhaps a disturbance propagated within a dielectric medium, as theorized by Maxwell (1914, 285–89; 1954, 188–90).

More than a century after Duhem argued for his non-falsifiability thesis, the set of issues connected with it are still elaborated upon, criticized, and defended in the large literature on the philosophy of science. Given holism, non-falsifiability follows logically and thus, when an experiment goes wrong, there is no set way to determine which hypothesis among many hypotheses is defective. Duhem proposed bon sens as a resolution to the problem, but that solution seemed unsatisfactory to many: it looked more psychological than epistemological and it sounded too vague. Thus scholars attempted to articulate further what Duhem might have meant as bon sens (see Ivanova 2010, Kidd 2011, Ivanova 2011, and Ivanova and Pasternote 2013). Others proposed their own resolutions to the problem, attempting to isolate defective hypotheses by extra-logical means, whether by inference to the best explanation, Bayesian devices, error-statistical methods, or though elaborate experimental practices; for an analysis of such solutions, see Dietrich and Honenberger 2020 or Ivanova 2021).

For most of the nineteenth century, scholars treated “medieval science” as an oxymoron. Since nothing from the Middle Ages was worthy of the name “science,” no history of medieval science could be written. For example, William Whewell referred to Greek philosophy as “the period of the first waking of science” and to the medieval era as “that of its mid-day slumber” (1857, I, Introduction). As a result, Whewell’s chapter on medieval science from the History of the Inductive Sciences , entitled “Of the Mysticism of the Middle Ages,” was just two-pages long.

With work such as Whewell’s being typical of Duhem’s intellectual context, when Duhem wrote L’évolution de la mécanique , in 1903, he dismissed the Middle Ages as scientifically sterile. Similarly, Duhem’s history of chemical combination, Le mixte et la combinaison chimique , published in book-form in 1902, had jumped from Aristotle’s concept of mixtio to modern concepts. It was only in 1904, while writing Les origines de la statique that Duhem came across an unusual reference to a then-unknown medieval thinker, Jordanus de Nemore. His pursuit of this reference, and the research to which it led, is widely acknowledged to have created the field of the history of medieval science. Where Duhem’s previous histories had been silent, Les origines de la statique contained a number of chapters on medieval science: one treated Jordanus de Nemore; another treated his followers; a third argued their influence on Leonardo de Vinci. In the second volume, Duhem greatly extended his historical scope. As expected, he covered seventeenth-century statics, but he also returned to the middle ages, spending four chapters on geostatics, including the work of Albert of Saxony in the fourteenth century. Les origines de la statique is thus a transition from Duhem’s early conventional histories to the later work for which he is best known, Etudes sur Léonard de Vinci , and Le Système du monde , in which his thesis of the continuity of late medieval and early modern science is fully displayed.

From 1906 to 1913, Duhem delved deeply into his favorite guide for the recovery of the past, the scientific notebooks of Leonardo de Vinci. He published a series of essays uncovering de Vinci’s medieval sources and their influences on the moderns. The third volume of Duhem’s Etudes sur Léonard de Vinci gained a new subtitle, Les précurseurs parisiens de Galilée, announcing Duhem’s bold new thesis that even the works of Galileo had a medieval heritage; reviewing his historical accomplishments, Duhem summarized them as follows:

When we see the science of Galileo triumph over the stubborn Peripatetic philosophy of somebody like Cremonini, we believe, since we are ill-informed about the history of human thought, that we are witness to the victory of modern, young science over medieval philosophy, so obstinate in its mechanical repetition. In truth, we are contemplating the well-paved triumph of the science born at Paris during the fourteenth century over the doctrines of Aristotle and Averroes, restored into repute by the Italian Renaissance. (1917, 162 [EHPS, 193])

Duhem presented Galilean dynamics as a continuous development out of medieval dynamics. He recovered the late medieval theory of impetus, tracing it from John Philoponus’ criticism of Aristotle to its mature statements in the fourteenth century works of John Buridan and Nicole Oresme: “The role that impetus played in Buridan’s dynamics is exactly the one that Galileo attributed to impeto or momento , Descartes to ‘quantity of motion,’ and Leibniz finally to vis viva . So exact is this correspondence that, in order to exhibit Galileo’s dynamics, Torricelli, in his Lezioni accademiche , often took up Buridan’s reasons and almost his exact words” (1917, 163–62 [EHPS, 194]). Duhem then sketched the extension of impetus theory from terrestrial dynamics to the motions of the heavens and earth:

Nicole Oresme attributed to the earth a natural impetus similar to the one Buridan attributed to the celestial orbs. In order to account for the vertical fall of weights, he allowed that one must compose this impetus by which the mobile rotates around the earth with the impetus engendered by weight. The principle he distinctly formulated was only obscurely indicated by Copernicus and merely repeated by Giordano Bruno. Galileo used geometry to derive the consequences of that principle, but without correcting the incorrect form of the law of inertia implied in it. (1917, 166 [EHPS, 196])

Duhem’s essays on Leonardo de Vinci concluded with a speculation about the means for the transmission of medieval ideas to modern science. Since the studies of Buridan and Oresme had remained in large part in manuscript, Duhem suggested that Albert of Saxony, whose works were printed and reprinted during the sixteenth century, was the likely link to Galileo. Duhem’s key to understanding the transmission of medieval science was Galileo’s use of the phrase Doctores Parisienses , a conventional label denoting Buridan and Oresme, among others. Based on evidence including references to certain unusual doctrines and the particular order in which the questions were arranged, Duhem conjectured that Galileo had consulted George Lokert’s compilation of Albert of Saxony, Themo Judaeus, and others, and the works of the Dominican Domingo de Soto (1906–13, III.582–83). Duhem’s conjecture has been revised and expanded upon: The means of transmission has been made clearer because of the labor of A. C. Crombie, Adriano Carugo, and William Wallace.

In the three years before his death in 1916, Duhem wrote Le Système du monde , but did not succeed in finishing it. He intended it as a twelve-volume work on the history of cosmological doctrines, ending with Copernicus. He completed nine volumes, the first five being published from 1914 to 1919, and the next four having to wait until the 1950s; a tenth, incomplete volume was also published then. These tomes impart an enormous amount of information about medieval astronomy, astrology, tidal theory, and geostatics, again presenting many sources for the first time in the modern era. They also trace developments in doctrines associated with such concepts as infinity, place, time, void, and the plurality or unity of the world. Duhem intended to write a 300-page summary of his results after he was done with the Le Système du monde ; he did not have the time to accomplish what would have surely been an amazing volume. (Duhem [LAS] is an attempt to construct such a single volume from the ten volumes of the Le Système du monde .)

Unlike his philosophical work, Duhem’s influential contemporaries did not receive his historical work with sympathy. As early as 1916, Antonio Favaro, the editor of Le Opere di Galileo Galilei , rejected the continuity of medieval and early modern science. The next generation of historians of science, Alexandre Koyré for example, acknowledged Duhem’s studies as the foundation for modern studies of medieval science, but subjected them to harsh criticism. Two themes divide Koyré’s historical work from that of Duhem. It presents histories of science in which metaphysics plays a primary role in explaining scientific change and it espouses a historiography that gives a central place to the concept of revolution. Medieval thought and early modern science are judged to be different in kind as well as in content.

At the beginning of an essay on void and infinite space, Koyré quotes a passage from Duhem that has become infamous: “If we were obliged to assign a date to the birth of modern science, we would undoubtedly choose 1277, when the Bishop of Paris solemnly proclaimed that a multiplicity of worlds could exist, and that the system of celestial spheres could, without contradiction, be endowed with straight line motion” (1906–13, II.411; see also 1913–59, VII. 4). Koyré calls the two theses from the condemnations of 1277 “absurdities,” noting that they arise in a theological context, and rejects Duhem’s date for the birth of modern science; he remarks that Duhem gives another date elsewhere, corresponding to Buridan’s impetus theory being extended to the heavens, but dismisses it also, saying that “it is as false as the first date” (1961, 37n). For Koyré, the introduction of Platonic metaphysics, the mathematization of nature, marks a break with the Aristotelian Middle Ages.

Koyré’s work influenced Thomas Kuhn and others who made “scientific revolutions” a central feature of their historical accounts. Still, the work of Kuhn and later historically oriented philosophers and sociologists of science did attempt to reintegrate the philosophical and historical studies that Duhem pursued together but that were separated for a good part of the twentieth century.

Duhem often first published his main works, such as Les théories électriques de J. Clerk Maxwell , L’évolution de la mécanique , Les origines de la statique , La théorie physique , son objet et sa structure , serially as articles in such journals as Annales de la de la Société scientifique de Bruxelles , Revue Générale des Sciences pures et appliquées , Revue des Questions Scientifiques , Revue de Philosophie , respectively.

  • Ariew, Roger, 1984, “The Duhem Thesis,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 35: 313–25.
  • Ariew, Roger and Peter Barker, 1986, “Duhem on Maxwell: a Case-Study in the Interrelations of History of Science and Philosophy of Science,” Philosophy of Science Association , 1: 145–56.
  • Ariew, Roger and Peter Barker (eds.), 1990, Pierre Duhem: Historian and Philosopher of Science , Synthese , 83 (2) and (3).
  • Biard, Joel, 2004, “Le rôle des condamnations de 1277 dans le développement de la physique selon Pierre Duhem,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 15–36
  • Brenner, Anastasios, 1990, Duhem, Science, Réalité et Apparence , Paris: Vrin.
  • –––, 2004, “Genèse, évolution et continuité du développement scientifique selon Pierre Duhem,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 37–58.
  • Brenner, Anastasios (ed.), 1992, Pierre Duhem , Revue Internationale de Philosophie , 46.
  • Brenner, Anastasios, Paul Needham, David Stump, and Robert Deltete, 2011, “New perspectives on Pierre Duhem’s The aim and structure of physical theory ,” (Book Symposium), Metascience , 20: 1–25.
  • Brouzeng, Paul, 1979, “L’histoire des sciences dans l’élaboration et la diffusion de la connaissance scientifique chez Pierre Duhem,” Actes du 104e Congrès national des sociétés savantes de Bordeaux , Paris, pp. 159–167.
  • –––, 1987, Duhem, Science et Providence , Paris: Belin.
  • Buzzoni, Marco, 2018, “ Pierre Duhem and Ernst Mach on Thought Experiments,” HOPOS , 8: 1–27.
  • Darling, Karen M., 2002, “The Complete Duhemian Underdetermination Argument: Scientific Language and Practice,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 33: 511–533.
  • –––, 2003, “Motivational Realism: The Natural Classification for Pierre Duhem,” Philosophy of Science , 70 (5): 1125–1136.
  • Dietrich, Michael, and Phillip Honenberger, 2020, “Duhem’s problem revisited: Logical vs epistemic formulations and solutions,” Synthese , 197: 337–54.
  • Dion, Sonia Maria, 2013, “Pierre Duhem and the inconsistency between instrumentalism and natural classification,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 44: 12–19.
  • –––, 2018, “Natural classification and Pierre Duhem’s historical work: Which relationships?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 69: 34–39.
  • Goddu, André, 1991, “Natural Classification: Pierre Duhem’s Continuity Thesis and the Resolution of Positivism, ” Historia philosophiae medii aevi , 1 (2): 329–348.
  • Hadamard, Jaques, 1927, “L’oeuvre de Duhem dans son aspect mathématique,” Mémoires de la Société des Sciences Physiques et naturelles de Bordeaux , 1: 635–665.
  • Harding, Sandra G., ed., 1976, Can Theories be Refuted? Essays on the Duhem-Quine Thesis , Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Ivanova, Milena, 2010, “Pierre Duhem’s good sense as a guide to theory choice,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 41: 58–64.
  • –––, 2011, “‘Good Sense’ in context: A response to Kidd,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 42: 610–12.
  • –––, 2015, “Conventionalism about what? Where Duhem and Poincaré part ways,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 54: 80–9.
  • –––, 2021, Duhem and Holism (Series: Cambridge Elements in the Philosophy of Science), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ivanova, Milena, and Cedric Paternote, 2013, “Theory Choice, Good Sense and Social Consensus,” Erkenntnis , 78: 1109–1132.
  • Jaki, Stanley L., 1984, Uneasy Genius, the Life and Work of Pierre Duhem , The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • –––, 1988, The Physicist as Artist: the landscapes of Pierre Duhem , Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press.
  • –––, 1991, Scientist and Catholic: an essay on Pierre Duhem , Front Royal, VA: Christendom Press; pp. 147–278 consist of English translation of selected texts from Duhem.
  • –––, 1992, Reluctant Heroine the Life and Work of Hélène Duhem , Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press.
  • James, William, 1981, Pragmatism , Indianapolis IN: Hackett.
  • Jordan, Emile, 1917, “Duhem, Pierre, Mémoires,” Société des Sciences Physiques et Naturelles de Bordeaux , 7 (1), 3–40.
  • Kidd, Ian James, 2011, “Pierre Duhem’s epistemic aims and the intellectual virtue of humility: A reply to Ivanova,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 42: 185–9.
  • Koyré, Alexandre, 1961, “Le vide et l’espace infini au XIVe siècle,” Etudes de l’histoire de la pensée philosophique , Paris: Gallimard. The essay was originally published in 1949.
  • Kragh, Helge, 2008, “Pierre Duhem, Entropy, and Christian Faith,” Physics in Perspective , 10: 379–95.
  • Lejbowicz, Max, 2004, “Pierre Duhem et l’histoire des sciences arabes,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 59–84.
  • Lowinger, Armand, 1941, The Methodology of Pierre Duhem , New York: Columbia.
  • Maiocchi, Roberto, 1985, Chimica e Filosofia, Scienza, epistemologia, storia e religione nell’Opera di Pierre Duhem , Firenze: La Nuova Italia.
  • Manville, Octave, 1928, L’oeuvre scientifique de Pierre Duhem , Paris: Blanchard.
  • Martin, R. N. D., 1976, “The Genesis of a Mediaeval Historian: Pierre Duhem and the Origins of Statics,” Annals of Science , 33: 119–129.
  • –––, 1982, “Saving Duhem and Galileo,” History of Science , 25: 302–319.
  • –––, 1991, Pierre Duhem: Philosophy and History in the Work of a Believing Physicist , La Salle, IL: Open Court.
  • –––, 1991, “The Trouble with Authority: the Galileo Affair and one of its Historians,” Modern Theology , 7: 269–80.
  • Mazauric, Simone, 2004, “Duhem et les lumières,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 85–104.
  • Merton, Robert, 1968, “Science and Democratic Social Structure,” Social Theory and Social Structure , New York: Free Press.
  • Miller, Donald G., 1970, “Pierre Duhem,” in Charles Gillispie, ed., Dictionary of Scientific Biography , New York: Scribner and American Council of Learned Societies, vol. 3, pp. 225–233.
  • Needham, Paul, 1996a, “Aristotelian Chemistry: A Prelude to Duhemian Metaphysics,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science , 26: 251–269.
  • –––, 1996b, “Substitution: Duhem’s Explication of a Chemical Paradigm,” Perspectives on Science , 4: 408–33.
  • –––, 1998, “Duhem’s Physicalism,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 29: 33–62.
  • –––, 2000, “Duhem and Quine,” Dialectica , 54: 109–132.
  • –––, 2002, “Duhem’s Theory of Mixture in the Light of the Stoic Challenge to the Aristotelian Conception,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 33: 685–708.
  • –––, 2008, “Resisting Chemical Atomism: Duhem’s Argument,” Philosophy of Science , 75: 921–931.
  • Nye, Mary Jo, 1986, Science in the provinces: scientific communities and provincial leadership in France, 1860–1930 , Berkeley: University of California Press,
  • Patapievici, Horia-Roman, 2015, “The ‘Pierre Duhem thesis’: A reappraisal of Duhem’s discovery of the physics of the middle ages,” Logos & Episteme: An International Journal of Epistemology , 6: 201–218.
  • Paul, Harry W., 1979, The Edge of Contingency, French Catholic Reaction to Scientific Change from Darwin to Duhem , Gainesville: University Presses of Florida.
  • Pierre-Duhem, Helene, 1936, Un Savant Français, Pierre Duhem , Paris: Plon.
  • Quine, W. V. O., 1953, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” From a Logical Point of View , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. First version of the paper, without any reference to Duhem, in The Philosophical Review , 60 (1951): 20–53.
  • Stoffel, Jean-François, 1995, “L’histoire des théories physiques dans l’oeuvre de Pierre Duhem (avec une bibliographie exhaustive de la littérature consacrée à Duhem),” Sciences et techniques en perspective , Nantes, pp. 49–85.
  • –––, 1996, Pierre Duhem et ses doctorants: bibliographie de la littérature primaire et secondaire , Turnhout: Brepols.
  • –––, 2002, Le phénoménalisme problématique de Pierre Duhem , Brussels: Académie royale de Belgique.
  • Whewell, William, 1857, History of the Inductive Sciences , third edition (new impression with index), London: Cass, 1967.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Electronic text of Duhem’s La théorie physique, son objet, sa structure (1906)]
  • Electronic links to several of the articles in the 1911 Catholic Encyclopedia by Duhem: “History of Physics,” “Pierre de Maricourt,” “Jordanus de Nemore,” “Nicole Oresme,” “Albert of Saxony,” “Thierry of Freburg,” and “Jean de Sax.” Also included are links to Duhem’s “Physics of a Believer,” and a few other excerpts.

Albert of Saxony | analytic/synthetic distinction | atomism: 17th to 20th century | Bacon, Roger | Buridan, John [Jean] | condemnation of 1277 | Einstein, Albert: philosophy of science | fictionalism | Galileo Galilei | James, William | Kuhn, Thomas | logic: inductive | Mach, Ernst | Pascal, Blaise | physics: experiment in | Poincaré, Henri | Quine, Willard Van Orman | scientific progress | statistical physics: philosophy of statistical mechanics | thought experiments | underdetermination, of scientific theories | Vienna Circle | Whewell, William

Copyright © 2022 by Roger Ariew < rariew @ usf . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

  • Browse by author
  • Browse by year
  • Departments
  • History of Thought
  • Advanced search

Through a detailed analysis of Duhem's writings some light is cast on the relations between holism, underdetermination and theory-ladenness of experimentation. The latter, which results from the need to interpret theoretically what is actually observed during an experiment, plays a key role in Duhem's analysis of the relation between observation and theory. I will argue that the theory-ladenness of experimentation on one hand provides a general argument for the holistic character of theory testing, and on the other renders problematic the thesis that theories are underdetermined by empirical evidence. A tension is found between Duhem's claim that the aim of theory is to save the phenomena and his analysis of the interpretative role of theory in experiments. I suggest how to overcome this difficulty by showing in what sense we can say that theory saves theory-laden phenomena. After stressing the differences between the Duhemian and the Quinean variants of holism, I argue that Quine fails to take into account the importance of the theory- ladenness of experimentation and the implications of Duhem's thought: Quine shares with the Logical Empiricists the belief that it is possible to detach from theories their empirical content. His acceptance of holism has simply the effect of restricting the attribution of empirical content only to conjunctions of many theoretical statements. I analyse and criticise the two notions of empirical content that Quine has developed. Furthermore I argue that there is no general theory-free expression of the experiential implications of a theory, for theories are logically connected to observable events only within local contexts defined theoretically and brought about by the activities of experimenters. Finally I suggest that, in the light of these considerations, the implications resulting from the possibility of rival incommensurable traditions of research should be discussed, rather than Quine's dilemma concerning empirically equivalent systems of the world.

Actions (login required)

-

Downloads per month over past year

View more statistics

Duhem, Quine and Kuhn, and Incommensurability

  • First Online: 01 January 2014

Cite this chapter

duhem quine thesis examples

  • Joseph Agassi 2  

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Philosophy ((BRIEFSPHILOSOPH))

1814 Accesses

There are many versions of the Duhem-Quine thesis or problem. What Duhem said was, no verification of hypotheses is possible, and not even refutation, since the refuting evidence is not proven. Popper agreed and said, evidence refutes a theory to the contrary as long as it is endorsed. Duhem argued against the realist reading of theories as it is metaphysical. Quine and Popper disagreed with this. Kuhn renamed the thesis incommensurability, but he rejected both the realist view of scientific theories and the opposite view of them. It is not clear whether he offered any alternative view.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Bibliography

Adam, A.M. 1992. Einstein, Michelson, and crucial experiment revisited. Methodology and Science 25: 117–218.

Google Scholar  

Agassi, Joseph. 2003. Comparability and incommensurability. In The Kuhn controversy, Social Epistemology ed. Stefano Gattei, 17, 2-3: 93–94.

Ariev, Roger. 1984. The Duhem thesis. British Journal of the Philosphy of Science 35: 313–325.

Article   Google Scholar  

Cross, Rodney. 1982. The Duhem-Quine thesis, Lakatos and the appraisal of theories in macroeconomics. Economic Journal 92: 320–340.

Duhem, Pierre. 1906, 1954. The aim and structure of physical theory.

Gillis, Don. 1998. Philosophy of science: The central issues.

Grünbaum, A. 1960. The Duhemian argument. Philosphy Science 27: 75–87.

Harding, Sandra G, ed. 1976. Can theories be refuted? Essays on the Duhem-Quine Thesis .

Hesse, M.B. 1969. Duhem, Quine and a new empiricism. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 3: 191–209.

Mirowski, Philip and Esther-Mirjam Sent. 2002. In Science bought and sold: Essays in the economics of science, ed.

Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1879. Note on the theory of the economy of research. In Mirowski and Sent, 2002, 183–190.

Quine, W.V. 1953. From a logical point of view.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Tel Aviv University, 69978, Tel Aviv, Israel

Joseph Agassi

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Agassi .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Agassi, J. (2014). Duhem, Quine and Kuhn, and Incommensurability. In: Popper and His Popular Critics. SpringerBriefs in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06587-8_6

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06587-8_6

Published : 15 May 2014

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-319-06586-1

Online ISBN : 978-3-319-06587-8

eBook Packages : Humanities, Social Sciences and Law Philosophy and Religion (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Duhem and Quine

Profile image of Paul Needham

The rejection of the idea that the so-called Duhem-Quine thesis in fact expresses a thesis upheld by either Duhem or Quine invites a more detailed comparison of their views. It is suggested that the arguments of each have a certain impact on the positions maintained by the other. In particular, Quine&#39;s development of his notion of ontological commitment is enlisted in the interpretation of Duhem&#39;s position. It is argued that this counts against the instrumentalist construal usually put on what Duhem says about approximation and historical continuity.

Related Papers

Emiliano TRIZIO

Through a detailed analysis of Duhem&#39;s writings some light is cast on the relations between holism, underdetermination and theory-ladenness of experimentation. The latter, which results from the need to interpret theoretically what is actually observed during an experiment, plays a key role in Duhem&#39;s analysis of the relation between observation and theory. I will argue that the theory-ladenness of experimentation on one hand provides a general argument for the holistic character of theory testing, and on the other renders problematic the thesis that theories are underdetermined by empirical evidence. A tension is found between Duhem&#39;s claim that the aim of theory is to save the phenomena and his analysis of the interpretative role of theory in experiments. I suggest how to overcome this difficulty by showing in what sense we can say that theory saves theory-laden phenomena. After stressing the differences between the Duhemian and the Quinean variants of holism, I argue ...

duhem quine thesis examples

Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science

Stefano Bordoni

Pierre Duhem can be looked upon as one of the heirs of a tradition of historical and philosophical researches that flourished in the second half of the nineteenth century. This tradition opposed the naïve historiography and epistemology of the positivist school. Beside the positivists of different leanings such as Littré, Laffitte, Wyrouboff, and Berthelot, we find Cournot, Naville, and Tannery, who developed sophisticated histories and philosophies of science focusing on the real scientific practice and its history. They unfolded elements of continuity and discontinuity in the history of science, and enlightened the complex relationship among experimental, mathematical, logical and philosophical components in scientific practice. In Pierre Duhem we find a systematic and vivid interpretation of these meta-theoretical issues, and a meaningful development of a cultural tradition that re-emerged in the second half of the twentieth century.

Daniel Durante Pereira Alves

Much of the ontology made in the analytic tradition of philosophy nowadays is founded on some of Quine's proposals. His naturalism and the binding between existence and quantification are respectively two of his very influential metaphilo-sophical and methodological theses. Nevertheless, many of his specific claims are quite controversial and contemporaneously have few followers. Some of them are: (a) his rejection of higher-order logic; (b) his resistance in accepting the intensional-ity of ontological commitments; (c) his rejection of first-order modal logic; and (d) his rejection of the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements. I intend to argue that these controversial negative claims are just interconnected consequences of those much more accepted and apparently less harmful metaphilosophical and methodological theses, and that the glue linking all these consequences to its causes is the notion of extensionality.

Greg Frost-Arnold

Quine’s philosophical views did not emerge fully formed in the 1930s; rather, they changed over the seven decades he was philosophically active. This chapter investigates two episodes in Quine’s ontological development: his engagement with Pythagoreanism (§2, with primary material in the Appendix), and his conversion from nominalism to Platonism about mathematics (§4). These two topics might seem completely distinct. However, although they could conceivably be treated separately, I will treat them together by considering the role clarity plays in both these episodes. Quine’s changing views about the theoretical virtue of clarity, and which particular things are clear and which are not, help explain his ontological development. In particular, §4 offers a new hypothesis about the causes of Quine’s conversion from nominalism to realism in which his views about clarity play an essential role. That said, Quine’s later views about clarity, and its significance for theory choice, are compl...

Ricardo Aragao

In recent academic debates, a lot has been said about metaontology. Usually, the main point of disagreement in these debates is the relationship between ontology and the logical existential quantifier. It has been well-known, since the famous 'On What There Is' (1948), that the dominant view regarding the meaning of the existential quantifier of formal logic is ontological, which means that the ontological notion of existence is completely captured by it. This association between ontological existence and the logical existential quantifier is explicitly defended by Quine with his criterion of ontological commitment. However, the most curious aspect about Quine's criterion that is commonly put aside, on purpose or not, is that it is a clear and extreme attempt to reduce ontological and metaphysical debates to the field of logic and semantics, more specifically, to the theory of reference. His criterion, as it was proposed, can be seen as a tool with which he defends the idea that the correct and only approach to answer the main ontological question " What is there? " is through logical analysis. If this interpretation is correct, the criterion of ontological commitment, although toughly defended by metaphysicians nowadays, is much closer to a deflationist point of view than is usually assumed. This is due to the fact that, as I intend to show, the relation between ontological existence and the logical existential quantifier, especially as proposed by Quine, is reductionist, superficial and completely anti-intuitive.

Benjamin Le Roux , Marcin Krasnodębski

Les origines de la statique, published in 1905 by physicist and historian of physical theories Pierre Duhem, offers not only a radically new interpretation of the history of statics but also represents a milestone in the methodology of history of science thanks to a particular form of historical reasoning as deployed by the author to justify his hypotheses. This article uses a quantitative analysis of the references contained in the book's footnotes in order to study the way Duhem validated his assertions. We highlight in particular his relentless will to return to the original texts. This method is one of the reasons why Duhem's book (and more generally the Duhemian methodology) had such a lasting impact on French epistemology.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy

Andrei Marasoiu

Guido Imaguire

My aim in this paper is to defend Quine’s so-called “Ostrich Nominalism”. This pejorative designation was introduced by Armstrong (1978), who accused Quine of not taking predicates with “ontological seriousness” and not offering any explanation of predication. However, I think Quine is entirely correct in this. In particular, I will show how to counter the Platonist One Over Many argument for the existence of universals. In doing this, I will go beyond merely offering an exegesis of Quine’s views on ontology: I will also try to fill in some gaps in his original argumentation.

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

Sonia Maria Dion

RELATED PAPERS

EasyChair Preprints

Kingsley Okoye

International Journal of Communications, Network and System Sciences

Ali M Allam

Journal of International Relations and Development

Gilles Carbonnier

Victor Estrada

International Journal of Elementary Education

Ni Luh Putu Era Adnyayanti

Molecular Cell

Julio Cesar Valdez Morales

Marco Barchi

Anna Motylska-Kuźma

Gastrointestinal Endoscopy

Md Asif Ansari

Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences

Paul Dolman

Free Radical Biology and Medicine

Waleska Kerllen Martins

European Journal of Pharmaceutical Sciences

Andrzej Woźnica

International Journal of Business and Management

Kamran Shafiq

Le Centre pour la Communication Scientifique Directe - HAL - SHS

Edwin Matutano

Medicine & Science in Sports & Exercise

Maniliz Segarra

Journal of Applied Sciences

Sifanele Machacha

Hyperfine Interactions

Lajos Nyikos

Robyn Dolson

The Journal of the National Collegiate Honors Council

Rebecca Bott

Clinical Nutrition

Shreenika Weliange

Blucher Engineering Proceedings

Marcelo Diniz

Varia Humanika

Eko Raharjo

Nanasaheb Shinde

Olubukola (Bukky) Tokede

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis Essay

Introduction.

Scientific proposition necessitates more than one insinuation to the situation in order to be analyzed practically. Through segregation, it may not be feasible to experiment any scientific hypothesis as stipulated by the problem raised by Duhem–Quine (Duhem-Quine thesis).

The thesis presented by Duhem-Quine may also refer to the auxiliary hypotheses or assumptions. In essence, predictions cannot be made easily through this thesis (Curd & Cover 1998, p. 10). However, a number of typical postulations in the surroundings would be a boost to obtaining predictions from the correct hypotheses.

For instance, it is feasible to derive any prediction once there is perfect scientific information in the preceding hypothesis and if the actual test works as premeditated. In fact, when studying the planet, astronomic and physical theories take into account facts and proofs of the notion that the world is in a continuous motion.

The malfunctioning of both the background assumptions and the hypothesis may perhaps lead to the falsification, as well as examination of the experimental scientists. According to the thesis presented by Duhem-Quine, the separation of a solitary hypothesis from the entire package of hypotheses is not achievable.

Besides, researchers are faced with a single solution to the predicament. Thus, failure of the empirical tests increases the likelihood of scientists to think otherwise. Actually, researchers would think that the examined theory is wrong even if the assumptions at the background are believed to be accurate.

Thus, chapter three of the Philosophy of Science basically offers simple and analytical techniques that are coherent in heightening and developing physical sciences. All these are developed in divergent sections, which include the portion that talks about the formation of a corporal principle.

The other portion concentrates on the subject matter and aims of the corporal principle. Thus, the Quine-Duhem states that it is not possible to examine any scientific theory through isolation owing to an experiential examination of the hypothesis that needs more than one contextual assumption.

Basically, Duhem’s point necessarily leads to the incommensurability thesis. There are several justifications to support this claim. According to Duham-Quine’s Philosophy of Science , the indeterminacy of translation is incompatible with the rendition manuals for any language.

In fact, the manuals can be arranged in a system where there is no impartially exact choice. A powerful variety of empiricisms required for affirmatively necessary or confident basis of credence through inductive verification was ruthlessly criticized by Duham and Popper.

The declaration is intrinsically covered by Martin Curd and Christopher Pincock in the Philosophy of Science. Quine stated that there are scientific theories that are irreconcilable yet they are practically correspondent. Specifically, the theory states that there is a connection between propositions that express pertinent proof and suggestions that comprise the theory.

The logic behind this theory is that recurring annotations of white swans do not prevent the likelihood of the survival of black swans. In essence, the peak point in the distortion is the fundamental testing.

According to Quine (1986), the testing can be carried out if two contradictory suppositions predict diverse results in some solid situations.

When the condition arises through tentative management or opportune combination of intrinsic occurrences, the outcome amid the competitors may be one or another. The hypothesis raised doubts regarding the reason for distortion, hence the influential character of critical testing.

When investigating the subject, Quine states that the results of any testing are not envisaged on the foundation of a single thesis only since supplementary theses are involved. The outcomes are often challenging and are not primarily regarded as threatened, when the thesis of concern is examined.

Nonetheless, if the results of the testing are not envisaged, it is rationally probable that the thesis under examination is correct and the inaccuracy reclines in one or more of the supplementary examinations (Gillies 1993, p. 7).

The Duhem-Quine problem examines the representation and classification of experimental regulations. The objective of all impartial hypotheses is the depiction of investigational regulations. The terms “truth” and “certainty” possess a single implication with regard to such a thesis.

The terms articulate concordance amid the termination of the thesis and the regulations recognized by the observer. Furthermore a rule of physics is only the synopsis of perpetuity of trials that have been conducted or shall be conducted in future (Quine 1954, p. 3).

Fundamentally, Duhem’s argument regarding experimental laws essentially leads to the incommensurability theory. According to this author, a sound thesis offers an acceptable depiction of tentative laws. He stated that the conformity to the experiment is the only criteria of reality for a physical thesis.

The author acknowledged four consecutive operations in the expansion of such a thesis. They include the description and gauging of physical magnitudes. In this, he identified the easiest characteristics of physical procedures and articulated the choosing of hypothesis.

He also accounted for the interconnection devised in prior stages and articulated the arithmetical progression of the thesis. This level is guided simply by the constraints of arithmetical reason devoid of physical realism. Finally, he articulated the evaluation of the thesis with experimentation.

The Duhem-Quine theory is critically concerned with falsification. The philosophy offers the methodology that develops the uncertainty of repudiation. Inherently, the author states that when a physicist opposes a certain principle, he or she contributes some uncertainty to a specific hypothetical point.

In this view, he hypothetically creates the justification for these doubts. From the proposal under arraignment, scientists will develop the forecasting of an investigational detail. Consequently, he or she will take into consideration circumstances under which the investigational detail should be developed.

When the anticipated detail is not developed, the proposal which acted as the foundation of the estimation will be condemned. He explored the Bayesian turn in identifying the outstanding characteristics of distortion when accounting for the research program in view of various challenges.

As a result, Quine observed that the Bayesian outline is not hinged on the valuation of impartial prospects in the first instance. The Bayesians begin with the likelihoods that are allocated to philosophies by experts (Lakatos 1978, p. 12).

In this case, there are disagreements among different Bayesians. Basically, the disagreements concern how the likelihoods are assigned. It does not matter if biased belief is applied or is subjected to individuals’ behavior.

Consequently, the author introduces the Bayes’s Theorem as formulated below.

P(h!e) = P(e!h)P(h) where P(h), and P(e) > 0

In this condition, he was concerned with the integrity of the theory h in comparison with experiential confirmation e. This means that the ensuing probability regarding the entirety of the evidence can be articulated.

When written in the above form, the theorem states that the probability of the hypothesis’ provisional confirmation is equivalent to the prospect of the proof’s provision in the theory reproduced by the prospect of the theory in the absence of the confirmation factor. The result is then alienated by the possibility of the confirmation (Curd & Cover 1998, p. 3).

The paper reviewed Duhem-Quine thesis expansion as presented by Gillies. In this paper, the fundamental modification by Quine and the traditional formulation of the postulation by Duhem have been observed.

In fact, when predictions fail, the reasoning is that the concurrence of numerous hypotheses in a rational presumption disqualifies the unambiguous acknowledgment of error. Hence, it undercuts the attractive reasoning in critical research as a way of deciding amid rival theories.

Duhem-Quine thesis has not blocked the development of science since neither Quine, nor Duhem predicted such a result. Interestingly, the thesis has aggravated lively discussions and the reconsideration of boundaries of common sense and the drawbacks in naive observations as offered by evidence collision.

In general, Duhem never argued about the probability of conducting experiment to disprove theories. However, the scholar emphasized that the disclaimers plunged upon schemes of theories while the examination of experience was no longer instantaneous and straight.

The series of circumstances transpiring from scientific decision-making rule out any simple or solitary solution to the falsification ambiguity. There is an understandable background that is suitable to warrant safety in the experimental outcomes.

Based on other instances, scientific problem is less specific. Consequently, different works will possibly offer solutions to the thesis. Duhem-Quine thesis is moreover posed in a modus that is uncooperative. Yet, the reliability on science anchors on instantaneous negations or confirmations.

Duhem gives us a more convincing standpoint regarding his discharge of prompt rationality. Thus, the understanding of Duhem-Quine problem stipulates that scientists should not rush into conclusions when choosing between systems theory.

Curd, M & Cover, J 1998, Philosophy of science: the central issues , Norton and Company, London.

Gillies, D 1993, Philosophy of science in the twentieth centur y: four central themes, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford.

Lakatos, I 1978, “Why did copernicus’s research programme supersede ptolemy’s?” Philosophical Papers , vol. 1 no. 3, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Quine, O 1986, Reply to Jules Vuillemin the philosophy of W. V. Quine , Library of Living Philosophers, Open Court, La Salle.

  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2022, April 12). Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-duhem-quine-thesis-essay/

"Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis." IvyPanda , 12 Apr. 2022, ivypanda.com/essays/the-duhem-quine-thesis-essay/.

IvyPanda . (2022) 'Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis'. 12 April.

IvyPanda . 2022. "Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis." April 12, 2022. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-duhem-quine-thesis-essay/.

1. IvyPanda . "Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis." April 12, 2022. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-duhem-quine-thesis-essay/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis." April 12, 2022. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-duhem-quine-thesis-essay/.

  • Document Falsification Crime and Response to It
  • Qualitative Research: Observation, Case Studies and Interviews
  • Sickle Cell Anemia: Diagnosis and Treatment
  • Popper on Corroboration
  • Aligning Philosophies of Science with Research Approaches
  • Inductivist Method of Science
  • Objectivity of Science
  • The Philosophical Revolution of Early Seventeenth Century
  • Than Christopoulos
  • May 30, 2023
  • 19 min read

The Duhem-Quine Thesis and the Critique of Falsificationism: Rethinking Theory Evaluation

Many Christians face accusations of making their worldview unfalsifiable by providing responses to objections that opponents perceive as post-hoc rationalizations. Is this truly the decisive blow to Christianity that some people claim it to be? Or is it possible that such accusations stem from a misunderstanding of how effective theory comparison works? To explore this question, we will delve into a concept known as the Duhem-Thesis, which sheds light on how Christianity possesses explanatory flexibility to accommodate data that might initially appear to challenge it. Through this investigation, we aim to unravel the role of reason in understanding how Christianity can reconcile seemingly contradictory information.

Introduction

The Duhem-Quine thesis, also known as the Duhem-Quine problem or the underdetermination of theory by evidence, is a concept in the philosophy of science that addresses the relationship between theories and evidence. It is named after the French physicist Pierre Duhem and the American philosopher Willard Van Orman Quine, who made significant contributions to our understanding of the complex nature of scientific theories and the challenges involved in testing them.both of whom made significant contributions to this idea.

One of Duhem's most influential works, "La Théorie physique, son objet et sa structure" (The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory), published in 1906, laid the foundation for what would later become known as the Duhem-Quine thesis. In this work, Duhem explored the fundamental aspects of scientific theories and their interconnectedness, focusing on the holistic nature of theory evaluation.

Duhem argued that scientific theories are not isolated entities but are composed of a network of interconnected hypotheses, auxiliary assumptions, and background knowledge. He emphasized that when testing a hypothesis or evaluating a theory, it is crucial to consider the entire theoretical framework rather than isolating individual components. This perspective challenged the traditional notion of straightforward hypothesis testing and called for a more comprehensive evaluation of scientific theories.

Duhem's work paved the way for subsequent developments in the philosophy of science, leading to the formulation of the Duhem-Quine thesis. This thesis, named after both Duhem and the American philosopher Willard Van Orman Quine, further expanded on Duhem's ideas and highlighted the underdetermination of theory by evidence.

While Duhem's original work focused primarily on the physical sciences, his ideas have had far-reaching implications for philosophy and the evaluation of scientific, historical and stretching even to philosophical theories more broadly. His emphasis on the holistic nature of theories and the interconnectedness of hypotheses and assumptions has influenced various fields, including the philosophy of religion.

Therefore, when discussing the Duhem-Quine thesis, it is important to recognize the seminal contribution of Pierre Duhem through his influential work "La Théorie physique, son objet et sa structure." Duhem's insights into the complex structure of scientific theories and his recognition of the interdependencies within them laid the groundwork for a deeper understanding of the challenges inherent in theory evaluation and the development of the Duhem-Quine thesis as a significant concept in the philosophy of science.

So What Exactly Is The Point?

The thesis suggests that it is impossible to test a single scientific hypothesis in isolation because any experiment or observation is influenced by a network of assumptions and auxiliary hypotheses. According to Duhem and Quine, when a hypothesis is tested and produces a result that conflicts with predictions, it is difficult to determine which part of the network of beliefs and assumptions is responsible for the discrepancy. This means that it is challenging to pinpoint whether a particular hypothesis or auxiliary assumption is false based solely on empirical evidence.

Keep this in mind when we return to apply this to the debate about God’s existence…

The Duhem-Quine thesis challenges the traditional notion of straightforward hypothesis testing and highlights the holistic nature of scientific theories. It suggests that theories are not confirmed or refuted in isolation, but rather as part of a larger web of beliefs and assumptions. Therefore, if empirical evidence contradicts a theory, scientists have the flexibility to revise or modify any component of the theory, including auxiliary hypotheses, background assumptions, or even the entire theoretical framework.

This thesis has important implications for the philosophy of science, as it emphasizes the role of scientific communities in evaluating and revising theories based on evidence. It also highlights the inherent uncertainty and subjectivity involved in scientific inquiry, as scientists must make judgments and decisions about which parts of the theoretical network to modify when faced with conflicting evidence.

It's worth noting that while the Duhem-Quine thesis challenges the idea of conclusive hypothesis testing, it does not imply that all theories are equally valid or that science is arbitrary. Rather, it underscores the complexity of theory confirmation and the need for critical evaluation and ongoing refinement in scientific practice.

The Duhem-Quine thesis, which challenges the traditional view of falsificationism (The claim that the main activity of a researcher is to invalidate a theory by observation or experiment as a definitive method for theory evaluation.) By highlighting the holistic nature of scientific theories and the interconnectedness of hypotheses and auxiliary assumptions, the Duhem-Quine thesis sheds light on the limitations of falsificationism. Because of this falsificationism is an outdated and inadequate approach to theory evaluation, as it oversimplifies the complexity of scientific inquiry and fails to account for the subjective and context-dependent aspects of theory assessment.

Falsificationism

We will be arguing that falsificationism is therefore false and this is why when Christians face accusations of making their worldview unfalsifiable by providing responses to objections that opponents perceive as post-hoc rationalizations is not the blow people may think it is. Falsificationism, popularized by Karl Popper, has long been regarded as a cornerstone of scientific methodology. It posits that scientific theories should be evaluated based on their ability to be falsified through empirical evidence (Popper, K. R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge.). However, the Duhem-Quine thesis challenges this notion by highlighting the inherent complexity and interdependence of scientific hypotheses and auxiliary assumptions. As noted by philosopher Peter Lipton, "The Duhem-Quine thesis poses a significant challenge to the simplistic idea that theories can be tested and falsified in isolation" (Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge.).The reasons why can be broken up into 4 main parts.

The Holistic Nature of Scientific Theories:

Scientific theories consist of a network of interconnected hypotheses, auxiliary assumptions, and background knowledge. The Duhem-Quine thesis argues that when a hypothesis is tested and conflicts with predictions, it is difficult to isolate which specific component of the theoretical network is responsible for the discrepancy. As philosopher Paul Hoyningen-Huene explains, "The Duhem-Quine thesis emphasizes the holistic character of scientific theories and the fact that a single hypothesis cannot be tested in isolation" (Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2006). Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn's Philosophy of Science. University of Chicago Press.). This holistic perspective suggests that the failure of a prediction does not necessarily imply that the specific hypothesis being tested is false. Instead, it calls for a critical examination of the entire theoretical framework and auxiliary assumptions.

Underdetermination of Theory by Evidence:

The underdetermination of theory by evidence, a key aspect of the Duhem-Quine thesis, further undermines the validity of falsificationism. Since evidence alone cannot unequivocally identify the cause of a discrepancy between theory and observation, scientists are faced with multiple plausible explanations. As philosopher Imre Lakatos points out, "The Duhem-Quine thesis reveals that a single falsifying observation cannot definitively refute a theory, as there are always alternative hypotheses and auxiliary assumptions that can be modified to accommodate the conflicting evidence" (Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (pp. 91-196). Cambridge University Press.). Consequently, the falsification of a specific hypothesis does not necessarily lead to the rejection of an entire theory. Rather, it prompts scientists to consider alternative explanations and revise auxiliary assumptions, rendering falsificationism an incomplete and limited methodology.

Context-Dependent Theory Evaluation:

Falsificationism assumes that theories can be evaluated independently of the wider scientific context. However, the Duhem-Quine thesis emphasizes the subjectivity and context-dependency of theory evaluation. The choice of which hypotheses or auxiliary assumptions to modify or discard when faced with conflicting evidence is influenced by various subjective factors, such as scientific judgment, theoretical preferences, axiology, and societal norms. As philosopher Bas C. van Fraassen argues, "The Duhem-Quine thesis highlights the subjective nature of theory evaluation and the fact that scientists make judgments about which components of the theoretical network to revise based on a range of subjective factors" (van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford University Press.). This subjectivity calls into question the objectivity and universality of falsificationism as a theory evaluation tool.

Refinement and Evolution of Scientific Theories:

The Duhem-Quine thesis encourages a more nuanced approach to theory evaluation, one that recognizes the frequentative and evolutionary nature of scientific inquiry. Instead of viewing the failure to falsify a hypothesis as a definitive rejection of a theory, the thesis suggests that scientific theories are subject to continual refinement and revision. As physicist and philosopher Nancy Cartwright argues, "The Duhem-Quine thesis promotes the idea that scientific theories are not static entities but rather dynamic frameworks that can be refined and modified in response to empirical evidence and theoretical advancements" (Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge University Press.). Scientists have the flexibility to modify auxiliary assumptions, reformulate hypotheses, or even reconstruct the entire theoretical framework in light of new evidence and theoretical insights.

Counter Examples to Falsificationism:

With this in place let's consider a few examples that demonstrate why this view of theory comparison should be preferred over falsificationism.

Several historical examples provide concrete illustrations of the limitations of falsificationism.

The phenomenon of black-body radiation

One example is the phenomenon of black-body radiation, which posed a challenge to classical physics. Rather than abandoning the entire theory, physicists developed new auxiliary assumptions and theoretical frameworks, leading to the formulation of quantum mechanics (Planck, M. (1914). The Theory of Heat Radiation. P. Blakiston's Son & Co.)

In the late 19th century, physicists were attempting to understand the radiation emitted by an idealized object known as a black body. According to classical physics, the energy emitted by a black body should increase without bound as the frequency of radiation increases, which is known as the ultraviolet catastrophe (Planck, 1914). However, experimental observations contradicted this prediction and showed that the energy distribution followed a different pattern.

To address this discrepancy, Max Planck introduced a new auxiliary assumption in 1900 that revolutionized our understanding of black-body radiation. Planck proposed that energy could only be emitted or absorbed in discrete packets, or quanta, rather than continuously (Planck, 1914). This assumption, now known as Planck's quantum hypothesis, provided a successful explanation for the observed energy distribution and laid the foundation for the development of quantum mechanics.

The significance of this example lies in the fact that rather than rejecting the entire classical physics framework, physicists introduced a new auxiliary assumption that led to a paradigm shift in our understanding of the fundamental nature of energy and matter. This example demonstrates the flexibility of scientific theories to adapt and incorporate new insights, even when faced with conflicting evidence.

To delve deeper into the topic, a scholarly paper by Planck himself, titled "The Theory of Heat Radiation," provides an in-depth exploration of the development of his quantum hypothesis and its implications for our understanding of black-body radiation (Planck, 1914). This seminal work discusses the experimental evidence, the challenges posed by classical physics, and the formulation of the quantum hypothesis as a solution.

By examining the historical context and the specific scientific advancements related to black-body radiation, we gain a deeper appreciation of how the Duhem-Quine thesis challenges the simplistic view of falsificationism. Rather than outright falsifying classical physics, the observed discrepancies prompted the development of new auxiliary assumptions and theoretical frameworks, leading to a more comprehensive understanding of the physical phenomena involved.

Newton’s gravitational theory

Consider the case of Newton’s gravitational theory. Due to gravitational attraction, in 1821 Alexis Bouvard predicted that the orbit of the Uranus, known at the time as the planet that was farther away from the Sun in the solar system, would be such-and-such, but observations consistently showed that the actual trajectory deviated from this prediction. No serious scientist thought that a well confirmed theory such as Newton’s should be immediately rejected because of a failed prediction. Rather, many revised some of the auxiliary assumptions, including the one about Uranus actually being the planet farthest away from the Sun. Two scientists working independently, Adams and Leverrier, posited that there must be another planet whose position and mass was affecting Uranus’ trajectory. They calculated where this planet was supposed to be, and how massive it would be. Eventually, the planet Neptune was discovered by direct observation.

The solar neutrino problem

The solar neutrino problem also illustrates this point. Neutrinos are near massless microparticles which are only subject to weak forces –they only interact with protons—and can go through almost any massive object. Our sun emits a vast number of neutrinos from its core, and the analysis of this flux of neutrinos is the main way of studying the inner workings of the sun. In the 60s, given what they knew at the time regarding the sun and neutrinos, scientists predicted a given number of neutrinos coming from the sun, but experiments showed only about a third of this number. This discrepancy was known as the solar neutrino problem. The tested hypothesis was the Standard Solar Model, and the auxiliary hypotheses included knowledge concerning the nature of neutrinos, the instruments that measured the solar neutrino flux (which include washing-up liquid), and assumptions concerning the whole experimental set up. Scientists didn’t just reject the Standard Solar Model in the face of this discrepancy (after all, the Standard Solar Model was well confirmed by many other situations and experiments) but analyzed some of these other assumptions. They hypothesized that perhaps neutrinos were more complex than they initially thought, and that there may be more kinds of neutrinos, some of which were undetectable by the measuring devices used in the initial experiment. This hypothesis was confirmed in 1985.

Did Adams, Leverrier, and the scientists involved in the solar neutrino problem proceed in an unscientific manner by not dropping their theories immediately? Surely they didn’t! So, there must be something wrong with Popper’s falsifiability criterion. It is true that if a theory consistently fails to be confirmed then that would be a good indication that it should be abandoned, but that would take us away from Popper’s criterion. After all, how many disconfirmations would one need in order to reject a theory? That would of course depend on each particular situation, but we see now that, contrary to Popper’s suggestion, falsifiability by itself is not enough to reject or accept a theory.

Dark Matter

There are also modern examples that illustrate the application of the Duhem-Quine thesis in contemporary scientific inquiry. One such example is found in the field of cosmology, specifically in the study of dark matter.

Dark matter is a hypothetical form of matter that does not interact with light or other electromagnetic radiation, making it invisible to direct detection. Its existence is inferred from its gravitational effects on visible matter and the large-scale structure of the universe. Various hypotheses and theories have been proposed to explain the nature of dark matter, including the existence of new particles beyond the Standard Model of particle physics.

In the quest to detect and understand dark matter, scientists rely on a combination of theoretical models, astrophysical observations, and experimental data. However, due to the elusive nature of dark matter, the complexity of astrophysical systems, and the limitations of observational techniques, the identification and characterization of dark matter remains a challenging endeavor.

The Duhem-Quine thesis is relevant in this context because the evaluation of competing dark matter hypotheses and theories is not solely based on isolated empirical tests. Instead, it involves a network of interdependent assumptions, such as the nature of particle interactions, the distribution of dark matter, and the behavior of gravity on large scales. When a specific dark matter hypothesis is confronted with observational data, it is difficult to pinpoint which assumptions within the broader theoretical framework are responsible for any discrepancies. Consequently, alternative explanations or modifications to auxiliary assumptions are considered to account for the observed phenomena.

For example, in recent years, there have been intriguing discrepancies between the predictions of dark matter simulations and observations of certain galactic structures. These observations, such as the unexpected distribution of dark matter in dwarf galaxies or the "too big to fail" problem, have raised questions about the standard dark matter paradigm. Scientists have proposed alternative explanations, including modifications to the properties of dark matter or the incorporation of additional astrophysical processes, to address these inconsistencies.

The ongoing research on dark matter and the attempts to reconcile theoretical predictions with observational data exemplify the holistic and interconnected nature of scientific theories as highlighted by the Duhem-Quine thesis. It underscores the need for critical evaluation, revision of auxiliary assumptions, and refinement of theoretical frameworks in light of empirical evidence and emerging insights.

While the specific application of the Duhem-Quine thesis in the context of dark matter is complex and subject to ongoing debate, it serves as a modern illustration of the challenges and considerations involved in theory evaluation within a complex scientific domain.

How Does This All Tie In?

Now you may be wondering why this matters at all with regards to the debate on God’s existence and whether or not Christianity is true.

The Duhem-Quine thesis and its implications for theory evaluation, particularly its emphasis on holism and the underdetermination of theory by evidence, can be applied to the debate about the truth of Christianity. While it is important to note that matters of faith and religious belief extend beyond the realm of scientific inquiry, the Duhem-Quine thesis offers a framework that allows for a nuanced understanding of the complexity and flexibility of Christian theism in response to challenges and criticisms.

Problem of Evil:

One aspect of the Duhem-Quine thesis is its recognition of the holistic nature of scientific theories. Similarly, in the context of Christianity, the belief system encompasses a comprehensive worldview that includes theological doctrines, moral teachings, and explanations for the nature of God, humanity, and the world. When confronted with the problem of evil, which questions how the existence of a benevolent and all-powerful God can be reconciled with the presence of suffering and injustice in the world, the Duhem-Quine framework allows Christians to approach the issue holistically.

By considering the problem of evil within the broader theological framework of Christianity, believers can explore various interconnected aspects, such as free will, the consequences of human choices, the role of suffering in spiritual growth, and the ultimate redemption and restoration of creation. This holistic perspective enables Christians to address the problem of evil not as a standalone challenge to the truth of Christianity but as an integral part of a comprehensive theological narrative that encompasses the entire human experience.

Furthermore, the Duhem-Quine thesis encourages Christians to engage in critical reflection and revision of auxiliary assumptions within their theological framework. This can involve theological debates and discussions that seek to refine and develop responses to the problem of evil, drawing on diverse philosophical, ethical, and theological perspectives. The flexibility provided by the Duhem-Quine framework allows Christians to explore and consider different explanations and solutions, acknowledging the complexity and interconnectedness of their belief system.

Historical Debates:

The history of Christianity is replete with debates and disagreements about its truth claims, ranging from theological doctrines to historical events such as the life, death, and resurrection of Jesus Christ. These debates have involved the critical evaluation of various pieces of evidence, interpretation of historical texts, and philosophical arguments.

Applying the Duhem-Quine thesis to historical debates about the truth of Christianity allows for an understanding of the interconnectedness of different historical and theological claims. Rather than evaluating isolated pieces of evidence or events in isolation, the Duhem-Quine framework prompts scholars and theologians to consider the larger historical and theological context.

For example, the debate surrounding the historical evidence for the resurrection of Jesus Christ requires considering a network of interconnected beliefs, such as the reliability of the Gospel accounts, the theological significance of the resurrection, and the coherence of the overall Christian worldview. The Duhem-Quine framework encourages scholars to engage in a holistic evaluation that takes into account multiple lines of evidence, historical context, and theological implications, allowing for a more nuanced understanding of the debate.

Scientific Insights:

Beyond philosophical and historical debates, scientific discoveries and insights can also be viewed through the lens of the Duhem-Quine thesis within the context of Christian theism. As scientific knowledge advances, new findings may raise questions or appear to challenge certain interpretations or beliefs. However, the Duhem-Quine framework encourages Christians to approach these scientific challenges with a holistic perspective.

For instance, the theory of evolution is often discussed in relation to Christianity, particularly in the context of the creation account in the book of Genesis. The Duhem-Quine thesis invites Christians to evaluate the relationship between scientific theories and their theological understanding in a comprehensive manner. This involves considering the theological richness of creation accounts, the symbolism and metaphorical nature of biblical texts, and the compatibility of evolutionary theory with theological concepts such as divine providence.

By adopting a holistic approach, Christians can engage in a nuanced evaluation that recognizes the limits and strengths of scientific knowledge while exploring how scientific insights can enrich their understanding of the world and their faith. This allows for a fruitful dialogue between science and Christian theology, where both domains contribute to a deeper comprehension of the complexities of existence.

In conclusion, the application of the Duhem-Quine thesis to the debate about the truth of Christianity provides a comprehensive framework that acknowledges the complexity and interconnectedness of belief systems. It allows for a more nuanced evaluation, critical reflection, and flexibility in addressing challenges, historical debates, and scientific advancements within the context of Christian theism. This holistic and reflective approach does not render religious beliefs unfalsifiable or post hoc rationalizations but provides a robust framework for evaluating their plausibility and coherence in a thoughtful and intellectually rigorous manner.

Moreover, the Duhem-Quine thesis highlights the flexibility and explanatory power of Christian theism in response to historical challenges. By recognizing the interconnectedness of beliefs within the broader Christian worldview, proponents of Christian theism have the ability to revise auxiliary assumptions, reinterpret historical events, or incorporate new evidence while maintaining the core tenets of their faith. This flexibility allows for a dynamic engagement with historical debates and the incorporation of emerging insights and scholarship.

It is important to note that the application of the Duhem-Quine thesis to the debate about the truth of Christianity does not claim to provide a conclusive proof or disproof of religious claims. Instead, it offers a framework that acknowledges the complexity and interconnectedness of belief systems, allowing for a more nuanced evaluation, critical reflection, and flexibility in addressing challenges and historical debates within the context of Christian theism.

The argument that Christianity, or any religious belief, is "unfalsifiable" based on the Duhem-Quine thesis, confirmational holism, and Bayesianism is a misunderstanding of the nature of theory evaluation and the flexibility of these frameworks. While it is true that religious beliefs, by their nature, may not lend themselves to direct empirical testing in the same way as scientific hypotheses, it does not render them unfalsifiable or dismiss them as post hoc rationalizations.

Holistic Evaluation and Coherence:

Confirmational holism, as emphasized by the Duhem-Quine thesis, recognizes the interconnectedness and interdependence of beliefs and assumptions within a theoretical framework. In the case of Christianity, the evaluation of its truth claims involves examining the coherence and consistency of its various doctrines, theological concepts, and historical narratives. This holistic evaluation is not a post hoc rationalization but a rigorous assessment of the internal consistency and logical coherence of the belief system.

By considering the broader theological context, Christians can critically evaluate how different elements fit together, ensuring that their beliefs are mutually reinforcing and logically sound. In this process, potential conflicts or inconsistencies can be identified and addressed, leading to a more robust and coherent understanding of their faith.

Bayesianism and Reasoned Evaluation:

Bayesianism, a framework for probabilistic reasoning, provides a valuable tool for theory evaluation, including religious beliefs. Bayesianism recognizes that beliefs are updated based on the available evidence and the assessment of the likelihood of various hypotheses. In the context of Christianity, Bayesian reasoning allows believers to weigh the evidence, consider arguments from philosophy, history, theology, and personal experiences, and make reasoned judgments about the plausibility and coherence of their faith.

Contrary to the notion of post hoc rationalizations, Bayesianism encourages a proactive and critical evaluation of evidence, ensuring that beliefs are not held dogmatically but are open to revision in light of new information. It enables believers to assess the cumulative impact of various pieces of evidence and arguments, and make rational decisions about the credibility and coherence of their beliefs.

Exploratory Flexibility and Open Inquiry:

The flexibility inherent in the Duhem-Quine thesis and these frameworks allows for open inquiry and exploration of alternative explanations and interpretations. Rather than being a weakness, this flexibility is a strength that aligns with the practices of science itself.

In scientific inquiry, hypotheses are often refined, modified, or even replaced in response to new evidence and theoretical advancements. Similarly, within the realm of religious belief, Christians have the freedom to engage in critical reflection, refine their understanding of theological concepts, and explore different approaches to address philosophical and historical objections.

This flexibility does not undermine the credibility of Christian theism but fosters a dynamic engagement with intellectual challenges and encourages continuous growth and refinement of theological perspectives.

It is important to note that the evaluation of religious beliefs is multifaceted and extends beyond the boundaries of empirical testing. The frameworks of the Duhem-Quine thesis, confirmational holism, and Bayesianism provide a comprehensive approach that acknowledges the complexity of belief systems, encourages critical evaluation, coherence, and reasoned judgment, and allows for the flexibility necessary to respond to challenges and engage in open inquiry. This holistic and reflective approach does not render religious beliefs unfalsifiable or post hoc rationalizations but provides a robust framework for evaluating their plausibility and coherence in a thoughtful and intellectually rigorous manner.

So we just covered a lot of things here and you may have trouble tying it all together. Here is the basic idea. To recap, when atheists argue that Christianity is "unfalsifiable" or that responses to objections are merely "post hoc rationalizations," they overlook the nuances of theory evaluation and the frameworks we employ in scientific and philosophical discourse. The Duhem-Quine thesis, confirmational holism, and Bayesianism offer valuable insights into how we assess the credibility of beliefs, including religious ones.

First, holistic evaluation and coherence are key. Christians engage in a rigorous assessment of the internal consistency and logical coherence of their faith. It's not about post hoc rationalization, but about critically examining the interconnectedness of beliefs within a broader theological framework.

Second, Bayesianism and reasoned evaluation play a crucial role. Christians weigh the available evidence, consider arguments from philosophy, history, theology, science and personal experiences, and make reasoned judgments about the plausibility and coherence of their faith. This is a proactive and intellectually rigorous process, not mere post hoc rationalization in an attempt to dishonestly avoid disconfirmation.

Finally, exploratory flexibility and open inquiry are vital. Just as scientific hypotheses like the ones we covered earlier are refined and modified based on new evidence, Christians have the freedom to engage in critical reflection, refine their understanding, and explore alternative explanations. This flexibility fosters growth and refinement, rather than being an admission of unfalsifiability.

Conclusion:

In conclusion, the charges of "unfalsifiability" and "post hoc rationalization" leveled against Christianity by atheists are misplaced. By employing the Duhem-Quine thesis, confirmational holism, and Bayesianism, Christians engage in a thoughtful and intellectually robust evaluation of their beliefs. They assess coherence, employ reasoned judgment, and embrace exploratory flexibility. This comprehensive approach allows for a more nuanced understanding of the faith and counters the misconceptions surrounding its evaluation.

In light of the Duhem-Quine thesis, falsificationism appears outdated and inadequate as a comprehensive theory evaluation methodology. The holistic nature of scientific theories, the underdetermination of theory by evidence, the subjectivity of theory evaluation, and the refinement and evolution of theories all challenge the notion that falsification alone can provide conclusive assessments of scientific theories. Embracing a more nuanced and holistic approach to theory evaluation allows for a deeper understanding of the complex dynamics within scientific inquiry and promotes the progress of scientific knowledge.

The inclusion of the counterexamples to falsificationism further strengthens the argument that falsification alone is insufficient for comprehensive theory evaluation and that we ought to follow the light of reason that the Duhem-Quine thesis, confirmational holism, and Bayesianism provide.

"The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" by Thomas S. Kuhn

`"Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge" by Karl Popper

"W. V. Quine: From a Logical Point of View" by W. V. Quine

"The Duhem Thesis and the Quine Thesis" by Pierre Duhem

"Confirmation, Empirical Progress, and Truth Approximation: Essays in Debate with Theo Kuipers" edited by Roberto Festa, Peer D. H. Grunwald, and Franz W.

"Holism, Entrenchment, and the Future of Empirical Theory" by Paul Hoyningen-Huene

"The Quine-Duhem Thesis: A Critical Appraisal" by Frederick Grinnell

"Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science" by Peter Godfrey-Smith

"Underdetermination: An Introduction" by Paul Hoyningen-Huene

"Inference to the Best Explanation" by Peter Lipton

Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge University Press.

Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2006). Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn's Philosophy of Science. University of Chicago Press.

Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013). Systematicity: The Nature of Science. Oxford University Press.

Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In I.

Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (pp. 91-196). Cambridge University Press.

Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge.

Planck, M. (1914). The Theory of Heat Radiation. P. Blakiston's Son & Co.

Popper, K. R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge.

van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford University Press.

Recent Posts

An Introduction to the Contingency Argument

Than Christopoulos Exploring Reality An Introduction to the Contingency Argument What is the Contingency Argument? I find that the contingency argument tends to be the most misunderstood of the argume

Slides From Our Gospel Authorship Stream

IMAGES

  1. The Quine-Duhem Thesis by Shade' Lovett on Prezi

    duhem quine thesis examples

  2. PPT

    duhem quine thesis examples

  3. Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis

    duhem quine thesis examples

  4. underdetermination thesis Duhem-Quine thesis jdnorton/papers/Science

    duhem quine thesis examples

  5. The Discussion of the Character of Empirical Observations according to

    duhem quine thesis examples

  6. PPT

    duhem quine thesis examples

VIDEO

  1. Day 8 Epistemology THV: Duhem-Quine Thesis

  2. Gibbs Duhem Margules Equation

  3. Gibb's Duhem equation in thermodynamics in tamil

  4. Gibbs Duhem Equation

  5. Sébastien Duhem

  6. H. Duhem Euphonium Etude in F Major

COMMENTS

  1. Duhem-Quine thesis

    In philosophy of science, the Duhem-Quine thesis, ... but the nature of the controversy was a clear example of how different bundles of (usually implicit) auxiliary assumptions could support mutually inconsistent hypotheses concerning a single theory. In terms of either version of the Duhem-Quine thesis it therefore is necessary to study ...

  2. PDF Chapter 5 The Quine-Duhem Thesis and Implications for Scientific Method

    1, in which we discussed such collections of beliefs by an analogy with jigsaw puzzles. Quine. tended to speak of such collections of beliefs as "webs of beliefs," suggesting an analogy with a spider's web. In a spider's web, changes in the outer regions of a web affect the more central. regions in only minor ways.

  3. Underdetermination of Scientific Theory

    From this and similar examples, Duhem drew the quite general conclusion that our response to the experimental or observational falsification of a theory is always underdetermined in this way. ... "The Duhem Thesis and the Quine Thesis,", in Philosophy of Science in the Twentieth Century, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 98-116.

  4. Popper, Basic Statements and the Quine-Duhem Thesis

    These are (1) the class of basic statements that are consistent with the theory, or which the theory 'permits'; and (2) the class of basic statements that the theory 'prohibits' or rules out. The latter class—which, in Popperian terms, is by far the more important of the two—is the theory's potential falsifiers, since the truth of ...

  5. PDF The Duhem Thesis and the Quine Thesis

    The Duhem Thesis and the Quine Thesis. In current writing on the philosophy of science, reference is often made to what is called 'tile Duhem-Quine thesis'. Really, however, this is some* thing of a misnomer; for, as we shall see, the Duhem thesis differs in many important respects from the Quine thesis. In this chapter I will expound the two ...

  6. PDF THE DUHEM-QUINE THESIS

    THE DUHEM-QUINE THESIS 4.1. THE COMPREHENSIVE INSTRUMENTALISM OF W. V. QUINE As we noted in the preceding chapter, W. V. Quine rejects every construction of the nature of Carnap's concept of an obser­ vational language (either strict .or extended) as sUbstantively incor,rect since-in his opinion-it is based on the false assump­

  7. Underdetermination Thesis, Duhem-Quine Thesis

    UNDERDETERMINATION THESIS, DUHEM-QUINE THESIS Underdetermination is a relation between evidence and theory. More accurately, it is a relation between the propositions that express the (relevant) evidence and the propositions that constitute the theory. The claim that evidence underdetermines theory may mean two things: first, that the evidence cannot prove the truth of the theory, and second ...

  8. PDF The Duhem Thesis, the Quine Thesis and The Problem of Meaning Holism in

    2.2 A comparison between the Duhem Thesis and the Quine Thesis_____ 48 3. QUINE ON ... that will be adopted throughout the thesis. I also discuss some examples that will be often referred to in subsequent chapters when dealing with Quine's philosophy of science. The thesis that no hypothesis in physics can be tested in isolation (also ...

  9. The Q uine- D uhem Thesis and Implications for Scientific Method

    The Quine-Duhem thesis, and issues surrounding the topic of scientific method, illustrate some of the ways that issues in science and the philosophy of science are intertwined, and intertwined in complex ways. In many ways, Rene Descartes' view of the proper way to conduct science was similar to that of Aristotle. There is no question that the ...

  10. Duhem-Quine Thesis

    The Duhem-Quine problem is named after Pierre Duhem (1861-1916) and Willard Van Orman Quine (1908-2000). The problem concerns a "gap" between theory and observation. Though the problem can be given various formulations, in general the issue is that a singular theoretical claim has no direct observational consequences, and thus cannot ...

  11. The complete Duhemian underdetermination argument: scientific language

    The Duhem-Quine thesis has received a significant amount of attention in recent years in scientific and logical theory circles, as a progressive alternative to the hypothetico-deductive method. The thesis's main attraction to contemporary practitioners of science is that it allows methodologically rigorous ways of resolving inconsistencies ...

  12. Pierre Duhem

    For example, the Newtonian emission theory predicts that light travels faster in water than in air; according to the wave theory, light travels slower in water than in air. ... Essays on the Duhem-Quine Thesis, Dordrecht: D. Reidel. Ivanova, Milena, 2010, "Pierre Duhem's good sense as a guide to theory choice," Studies in History and ...

  13. The Duhem thesis, the Quine thesis and the problem of meaning holism in

    Through a detailed analysis of Duhem's writings some light is cast on the relations between holism, underdetermination and theory-ladenness of experimentation. The latter, which results from the need to interpret theoretically what is actually observed during an experiment, plays a key role in Duhem's analysis of the relation between observation and theory.

  14. Duhem, Quine and Kuhn, and Incommensurability

    Duhem argued against the realist reading of theories as it is metaphysical. Quine and Popper disagreed with this. Kuhn renamed the thesis incommensurability, but he rejected both the realist view of scientific theories and the opposite view of them. It is not clear whether he offered any alternative view. Download chapter PDF.

  15. [PDF] The Duhem thesis, the Quine thesis and the problem of meaning

    Through a detailed analysis of Duhem's writings some light is cast on the relations between holism, underdetermination and theory-ladenness of experimentation. The latter, which results from the need to interpret theoretically what is actually observed during an experiment, plays a key role in Duhem's analysis of the relation between observation and theory. I will argue that the theory ...

  16. Philosophy of science

    Underdetermination. The complexities of the notion of falsification, originally diagnosed by Duhem, had considerable impact on contemporary philosophy of science through the work of the American philosopher W.V.O. Quine (1908-2000). Quine proposed a general thesis of the underdetermination of theory by evidence, arguing that it is always possible to preserve any hypothesis in the face of any ...

  17. (PDF) Duhem and Quine

    Download Free PDF. View PDF. Duhem and Quine PAUL NEEDHAM* Abstract The rejection of the idea that the so-called Duhem-Quine thesis in fact expresses a thesis upheld by either Duhem or Quine invites a more detailed comparison of their views. It is suggested that the arguments of each have a certain impact on the positions maintained by the other.

  18. PDF The Duhem-Quine thesis and experimental economics. A ...

    pure mathematics and logic" (Quine, 1980, p. 42). Below, the individual positions of Duhem and Quine are elaborated on separately (alternative expositions of the theses can be found in Vuillemin, 1986 and Gilles, 1993, Chapter 5). 2.1. The Duhem thesis Duhem's primary contention is non-separability. This is the assertion that theoretical statements

  19. PDF Duhem, Quine and the other dogma

    A quantum-mechanical example is looked at in x5. In x6 I consider how Quine relates meaning, essence and analyticity, in x7 how Duhem relates the cleavage between physics and mathematics to the impossibility of crucial experiments, and whether holism really does have conflicting implications for Duhem and for Quine. 2 Essences, accidents and ...

  20. Quine-Duhem Thesis

    The Quine-Duhem thesis is a form of the thesis of the underdetermination of theory by empirical evidence. The basic problem is that individual theoretical claims are unable to be confirmed or falsified on their own, in isolation from surrounding hypotheses. For this reason, the acceptance or rejection of a theoretical claim is underdetermined ...

  21. Confirmation holism

    Confirmation holism. In philosophy of science, confirmation holism, also called epistemological holism, is the view that no individual statement can be confirmed or disconfirmed by an empirical test, but rather that only a set of statements (a whole theory) can be so. It is attributed to Willard Van Orman Quine who motivated his holism through ...

  22. Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis

    Quine, O 1986, Reply to Jules Vuillemin the philosophy of W. V. Quine, Library of Living Philosophers, Open Court, La Salle. This essay, "Duhem-Quine Thesis Analysis" is published exclusively on IvyPanda's free essay examples database. You can use it for research and reference purposes to write your own paper.

  23. The Duhem-Quine Thesis and the Critique of Falsificationism: Rethinking

    The Duhem-Quine thesis, which challenges the traditional view of falsificationism (The claim that the main activity of a researcher is to invalidate a theory by observation or experiment as a definitive method for theory evaluation.) ... For example, the debate surrounding the historical evidence for the resurrection of Jesus Christ requires ...