Teleological Arguments

Overview of Teleological Arguments

  • Originates from the Greek word ‘telos’ which means ‘end’ or ‘purpose’.
  • Posits that the order and complexity found in the Universe signifies an intelligent design, credited to a divine being.
  • Also known as arguments from design .
  • Counts as a type of a posteriori argument because it is based on experiences and observations of the natural world.

Types of Teleological Arguments

Classical Design Arguments

  • Typically associated with philosophers like William Paley and St Thomas Aquinas .
  • Paley famously equated the intricacy seen in nature (e.g., the eye) to a watch, arguing that a watch necessitates a watchmaker, similarly to how complexity in nature implies a designer.
  • Aquinas’ Fifth Way maintains that everything acts towards an end and any order in this respect reflects an intelligent being.

Modern Design Arguments

  • This refers to arguments primarily influenced by scientific discoveries .
  • For instance, the Anthropic Principle suggests the initial conditions of the Universe are ‘fine-tuned’ for life, implying a divine tuner.
  • The Intelligent Design Theory posits that certain biological structures are too intricate to have arisen simply by evolutionary processes, suggesting a designer’s presence.

Critiques of Teleological Arguments

  • Key criticisms include those advanced by David Hume .
  • Hume questioned the analogy between human artefacts and the Universe; just because human artefacts have designers, this does not necessarily mean the Universe does too.
  • Hume also challenged the idea of assuming the designer’s nature based on the design. For example, why assume a single, benevolent God and not multiple flawed deities?
  • Some critics highlight the issue of evil and suffering in the world, challenging the notion of a benevolent designer.
  • Darwinian evolution is often cited as a naturalistic explanation for the appearance of design.
  • Modern critics cite Occam’s Razor , arguing that the hypothesis of God as a designer is an unnecessary complication when natural explanations, like evolution, suffice.

Responses to Criticisms

  • The argument from design does not claim to prove God’s existence conclusively but only suggests that God’s existence is probable based on the intricate design observed.
  • The presence of evil and suffering does not negate a designer; instead, they could indicate a non-benevolent designer or a designer with a higher purpose beyond our understanding.
  • Even with naturalistic explanations for apparent design, some argue these processes themselves imply a designer who established these natural laws.

First Cause Argument and Teleological Arguments

  • Teleological arguments are often combined with Cosmological arguments , specifically the First Cause Argument.
  • Both arguments propose a deity as the best explanation for observed phenomena – design and existence, respectively.
  • This combination can provide a stronger argument for the existence of God, but it also invites criticisms grounded in both arguments.

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Teleological Arguments for God’s Existence

Some phenomena within nature exhibit such exquisiteness of structure, function or interconnectedness that many people have found it natural to see a deliberative and directive mind behind those phenomena. The mind in question is typically taken to be supernatural. Philosophically inclined thinkers have both historically and at present labored to shape the relevant intuition into a more formal, logically rigorous inference. The resultant theistic arguments, in their various logical forms, share a focus on plan, purpose, intention, and design, and are thus classified as teleological arguments (or, frequently, as arguments from or to design).

Although enjoying some prominent defenders over the centuries, such arguments have also attracted serious criticisms from major historical and contemporary thinkers. Critics and advocates include not only philosophers but also scientists and thinkers from other disciplines as well. In the following discussion, major variant forms of teleological arguments will be distinguished and explored, traditional philosophical and other criticisms will be discussed, and the most prominent contemporary turns (cosmic fine tuning arguments, many-worlds theories, and the Intelligent Design debate) will be tracked. Discussion will conclude with a brief look at one historically important non-inferential approach to the issue.

1. Introduction

2.1 analogical design arguments: schema 1, 2.2 deductive design arguments: schema 2, 2.3 inferences to the best explanation/abductive design arguments: schema 3.

  • 3.1 Explaining Away

3.2 Indirect Causation, Design and Evidences

4.1.1 no explanation needed, 4.1.2 rival explanations.

  • 4.2 Biological: The “Intelligent Design” Movement

5. The Persistence of Design Thinking

6. conclusion, other internet resources, related entries.

It is not uncommon for humans to find themselves with the intuition that random, unplanned, unexplained accident just couldn’t produce the order, beauty, elegance, and seeming purpose that we experience in the natural world around us. As Hume’s interlocutor Cleanthes put it, we seem to see “the image of mind reflected on us from innumerable objects” in nature (Hume 1779 [1998], 35). And many people find themselves convinced that no explanation for that mind-resonance which fails to acknowledge a causal role for intelligence, intent and purpose in nature can be seriously plausible.

Cosmological arguments often begin with the bare fact that there are contingently existing things and end with conclusions concerning the existence of a cause with the power to account for the existence of those contingent things. Others reason from the premise that the universe has not always existed to a cause that brought it into being. Teleological arguments (or arguments from design ) by contrast begin with a much more specialized catalogue of properties and end with a conclusion concerning the existence of a designer with the intellectual properties (knowledge, purpose, understanding, foresight, wisdom, intention) necessary to design the things exhibiting the special properties in question. In broad outline, then, teleological arguments focus upon finding and identifying various traces of the operation of a mind in nature’s temporal and physical structures, behaviors and paths. Order of some significant type is usually the starting point of design arguments.

Design-type arguments are largely unproblematic when based upon things nature clearly could not or would not produce (e.g., most human artifacts), or when the intelligent agency is itself ‘natural’ (human, alien, etc.). Identifying designed traces of ‘lost’ human civilizations or even non-human civilizations (via SETI) could in principle be uncontroversial. Objections to design inferences typically arise only when the posited designer is something more exotic or perhaps supernatural.

But despite the variety of spirited critical attacks they have elicited, design arguments have historically had and continue to have widespread intuitive appeal—indeed, it is sometimes claimed that design arguments are the most persuasive of all purely philosophical theistic arguments. Note that while design arguments have traditionally been employed to support theism over metaphysical naturalism, some might also be relevant for panentheism, panpsychism, and other views involving irreducible teleology.

2. Design Inference Patterns

The historical arguments of interest are precisely the potentially problematic ones—inferences beginning with some empirical features of nature and concluding with the existence of a designer. A standard but separable second step—the natural theology step—involves identifying the designer as God, often via particular properties and powers required by the designing in question. Although the argument wielded its greatest intellectual influence during the 18th and early 19th centuries, it goes back at least to the Greeks and in extremely clipped form comprises one of Aquinas’s Five Ways. It was given a fuller and quite nice early statement by Hume’s Cleanthes (1779 [1998], 15).

The question remains, however, about the formal structure of such arguments. What sort of logic is being employed? As it turns out, that question does not have just a single answer. Several distinct answers are canvassed in the following sections.

Design arguments are routinely classed as analogical arguments—various parallels between human artifacts and certain natural entities being taken as supporting parallel conclusions concerning operative causation in each case. The standardly ascribed schema is roughly thus:

Schema 1 : Entity e within nature (or the cosmos, or nature itself) is like specified human artifact a (e.g., a machine) in relevant respects R . a has R precisely because it is a product of deliberate design by intelligent human agency. Like effects typically have like causes (or like explanations, like existence requirements, etc.) Therefore It is (highly) probable that e has R precisely because it too is a product of deliberate design by intelligent, relevantly human- like agency.

2.1.1 Humean objections

This general argument form was criticized quite vigorously by Hume, at several key steps. Against (1), Hume argued that the analogy is not very good—that nature and the various things in it are not very like human artifacts and exhibit substantial differences from them—e.g., living vs. not, self-sustaining vs. not. Indeed, whereas advocates of design arguments frequently cited similarities between the cosmos on the one hand and human machines on the other, Hume suggested that the cosmos much more closely resembled a living organism than a machine. (Contemporary cosmology strengthens Hume’s point, given the radical changes that have taken place since the Big Bang. The universe looks less stable and “machine-like” than when the design argument was at the height of its popularity.) But if the alleged resemblance is in relevant respects distant, then the inference in question will be logically fragile. And while (2) may be true in specific cases of human artifacts a , that fact is only made relevant to natural phenomena e via (3), which underpins the transfer of the key attribution. Against (3), Hume argued that any number of alternative possible explanations could be given of allegedly designed entities in nature—chance, for instance. Thus, even were (1) true and even were there important resemblances, the argument might confer little probabilistic force onto the conclusion.

More generally, Hume also argued that even if something like the stated conclusion (4) were established, that left the arguer far from anything like a traditional conception of God. For instance, natural evils or apparently suboptimal designs might suggest e.g., an amateur designer or a committee of designers. And if phenomena instrumental to the production of natural evils (e.g., disease microorganisms) exhibited various of the R s, then they would presumably have to be laid at the designer’s door, further eroding the designer’s resemblance to the wholly good deity of tradition. And even the most impressive empirical data could properly establish only finite (although perhaps enormous) power and wisdom, rather than the infinite power and wisdom usually associated with divinity. But even were one to concede some substance to the design argument’s conclusion, that would, Hume suggested, merely set up a regress. The designing agent would itself demand explanation, requiring ultimately a sequence of prior analogous intelligences producing intelligences. And even were the existence of a designer of material things established, that did not yet automatically establish the existence of a creator of the matter so shaped. And since analogical arguments are a type of induction (see the entry on analogy and analogical reasoning ), the conclusion even if established would be established only to some, perhaps insignificant, degree of probability. Furthermore, we could not ground any induction concerning the cosmos itself upon a requisite fund of experiences of other cosmoi found to be both deliberately designed and very like ours in relevant respects—for the simple reason that this universe is our only sample. And finally the fraction of this one cosmos (both spatially and temporally) available to our inspection is extraordinarily small—not a promising basis for a cosmically general conclusion. Hume concluded that while the argument might constitute some limited grounds for thinking that “ the cause or causes of order in the universe probably bear some remote analogy to human intelligence ” (1779 [1998], 88) Hume’s emphasis)—and that is not a trivial implication—it established nothing else whatever.

Historically, not everyone agreed that Hume had fatally damaged the argument. It is simply not true that explanatory inferences cannot properly extend beyond merely what is required for known effects. As a very general example, based on the few observations which humans had made during a cosmically brief period in a spatially tiny part of the cosmos, Newton theorized that all bits of matter at all times and in all places attracted all other bits of matter. There was nothing logically suspect here. Indeed, simplicity and uniformity considerations—which have considerable well-earned scientific clout—push in the direction of such generalizations.

But Hume certainly identified important places within the argument to probe. Whether his suggestions are correct concerning the uncertain character of any designer inferred will depend upon the specific R s and upon what can or cannot be definitively said concerning requirements for their production.

2.1.2 R Concerns: Round 1

Key questions, then, include: what are the relevant R s typically cited? do those R s genuinely signal purpose and design? how does one show that either way? are there viable alternative accounts of the R s requiring no reference to minds? how does one show that either way? The specific R s in question are obviously central to design argument efforts. Although the underlying general category is, again, some special type of orderliness, the specifics have ranged rather widely historically. Among the more straightforwardly empirical are inter alia uniformity, contrivance, adjustment of means to ends, particularly exquisite complexity, particular types of functionality, delicacy, integration of natural laws, improbability, and the fitness (fine-tuning) of the inorganic realm for supporting life. Several problematic proposals that are empirically further removed and have axiological overtones have also been advanced, including the intelligibility of nature, the directionality of evolutionary processes, aesthetic characteristics (beauty, elegance, and the like), apparent purpose and value (including the aptness of our world for the existence of moral value and practice) and just the sheer niftiness of many of the things we find in nature.

But some advocates of design arguments had been reaching for a deeper intuition. The intuition they were attempting to capture involved properties that constituted some degree of evidence for design, not just because such properties happened to be often or even only produced by designing agents. Advocates were convinced that the appropriate R s in question were in their own right directly reflective of and redolent of cognition, that this directly suggested mind , that we could see nearly directly that they were the general sort of thing that a mind might or even would generate, and that consequently they did not depend for their evidential force upon previously established known instances of design. When we see a text version of the Gettysburg Address, that text says mind to us in a way totally unrelated to any induction or analogy from past encounters with written texts. It was that type of testimony to mind, to design, that some historical advocates of design arguments believed that they found in some R s observed in nature—a testimony having no dependency on induction or analogy. Beauty, purpose and in general value especially when conjoined with delicate complexity were popular underlying intuitive marks. Intricate, dynamic, stable, functioning order of the sort we encounter in nature was frequently placed in this category. Such order was taken to be suggestive of minds in that it seemed nearly self-evidently the sort of thing minds were prone to produce. It was a property whose mind-resonating character we could unhesitatingly attribute to intent.

Despite Hume’s earlier demurs that things in nature are not really very like artifacts such as machines, most people who are most familiar with nature’s dazzling intricacies freely admit that nature abounds with things that look designed—that are intention- shaped . For instance, Francis Crick (no fan of design) issued a warning to his fellow biologists:

Biologists must constantly keep in mind that what they see was not designed, but rather evolved. (Crick 1988, 138).

Along with this perception of mind-suggestiveness went a further principle—that the mind-suggestive or design- like characteristics in question were too palpable to have been generated by non-intentional means.

That allows specification of a second design inference pattern:

Schema 2 : Some things in nature (or nature itself, the cosmos) are design-like (exhibit a cognition-resonating, intention-shaped character R ) Design-like properties ( R ) are not producible by (unguided) natural means—i.e., any phenomenon exhibiting such R s must be a product of intentional design. Therefore Some things in nature (or nature itself, the cosmos) are products of intentional design, which in turn requires agency of some type.

Notice that explicit reference to human artifacts has dropped out of the argument, and that the argument is no longer comparative but has become essentially deductive. Some arguments were historically intended as arguments of that type. William Paley famously sees no design-like properties in a stone, but finding a watch on the ground would be another matter. Unlike the stone, it could not always have been there. Why not? [ 1 ]

For this reason, and for no other, namely, that when we come to inspect the watch, we perceive—what we could not discover in the stone—that its several parts are framed and put together for a purpose … [The requisite] mechanism being observed … the inference we think is inevitable, that the watch must have had a maker. ... Every observation which was made in our first chapter concerning the watch may be repeated with strict propriety concerning the eye, concerning animals, concerning plants, concerning, indeed, all the organized parts of the works of nature. … [T]he eye … would be alone sufficient to support the conclusion which we draw from it, as to the necessity of an intelligent Creator. …

Although Paley’s argument is routinely construed as analogical, it contains an informal statement of the above variant argument type. Paley goes on for two chapters discussing the watch, discussing the properties in it which evince design, and destroying potential objections to concluding design in the watch. It is only then that entities in nature—e.g., the eye—come onto the horizon. Paley isn’t trying to persuade his readers that the watch is designed and has a designer. He is teasing out the bases and procedures from and by which we should and should not reason about design and designers. Thus Paley’s use of the term ‘inference’ in connection with the watch’s designer. [ 2 ]

Once having acquired the relevant principles, then in Chapter 3 of Natural Theology —“Application of the Argument”—Paley applies the same argument (vs. presenting us with the other half of the analogical argument) to things in nature. The cases of human artifacts and nature represent two separate inference instances:

up to the limit, the reasoning is as clear and certain in the one case as in the other. (Paley 1802 [1963], 14)

But the instances are instances of the same inferential move:

there is precisely the same proof that the eye was made for vision as there is that the telescope was made for assisting it. (Paley 1802 [1963], 13)

The watch does play an obvious and crucial role—but as a paradigmatic instance of design inferences rather than as the analogical foundation for an inferential comparison.

Schema 2, not being analogically structured, would not be vulnerable to the ills of analogy, [ 3 ] and not being inductive would claim more than mere probability for its conclusion. That is not accidental. Indeed, it has been argued that Paley was aware of Hume’s earlier attacks on analogical design arguments, and deliberately structured his argument to avoid the relevant pitfalls (Gillispie 1990, 214–229).

2.2.1 Assessing the Schema 2 argument

First, how are we to assess the premises required by this schema? Premise (5), at least, is not particularly controversial even now. Crick’s earlier warning to biologists would have been pointless were there no temptation toward design attributions, and even as implacable a contemporary opponent of design arguments as Richard Dawkins characterized biology as:

the study of complicated things that give the appearance of having been designed for a purpose. (Dawkins 1987, 1)

Day-to-day contemporary biology is rife with terms like ‘design’, ‘machine’, ‘purpose’, and allied terms. As historian of science Timothy Lenoir has remarked:

Teleological thinking has been steadfastly resisted by modern biology. And yet, in nearly every area of research biologists are hard pressed to find language that does not impute purposiveness to living forms. (Lenoir 1982, ix)

Whether or not particular biological phenomena are designed, they are frequently enough design- like to make design language not only fit living systems extraordinarily well, but to undergird the generation of fruitful theoretical conceptions. [ 4 ] Advocates of design arguments claim that the reason why theorizing as if organisms are designed meets with such success is that organisms are in fact designed. Those opposed would say that all teleological concepts in biology must, in one way or another, be reduced to natural selection.

However, principle (6) (that the relevant design-like properties are not producible by unguided natural means) will be more problematic in evolutionary biology. What might be the rational justification for (6)? There are two broad possibilities.

1. Empirical: induction . Induction essentially involves establishing that some principle holds within the realm of our experience (the sample cases), and then generalizing the principle to encompass relevant areas beyond that realm (the test cases). The attempt to establish the universality of a connection between having relevant R s and being a product of mind on the basis of an observed consistent connection between having relevant R s and being a product of mind within all (most) of the cases where both R was exhibited and we knew whether or not the phenomenon in question was a product of mind, would constitute an inductive generalization.

This approach would suffer from a variety of weaknesses. The R -exhibiting things concerning which we knew whether they were designed would be almost without exception human artifacts, whereas the phenomena to which the generalization was being extended would be things in nature. And, of course, the generalization in question could establish at best a probability, and a fairly modest one at that.

2. Conceptual . It might be held that (6) is known in the same conceptual, nearly a priori way in which we know that textbooks are not producible by natural processes unaided by mind. And our conviction here is not based on any mere induction from prior experiences of texts. Texts carry with them essential marks of mind, and indeed in understanding a text we see at least partway into the mind(s) involved. Various alien artifacts (if any)—of which we have had no prior experience whatever—could fall into this category as well. Similarly, it has been held that we sometimes immediately recognize that order of the requisite sort just is a sign of mind and intent.

Alternatively, it could be argued that although there is a genuine conceptual link between appropriate R s and mind, design, intent, etc., that typically our recognition of that link is triggered by specific experiences with artifacts. On this view, once the truth of (6) became manifest to us through those experiences, the appropriateness of its more general application would be clear. That might explain why so many advocates of design arguments seem to believe that they must only display a few cases and raise their eyebrows to gain assent to design.

Either way, principle (6), or something like it, would be something with which relevant design inferences would begin. Further investigation of (6) requires taking a closer look at the R s which (6) involves.

2.2.2 R Concerns: Round 2

One thing complicating general assessments of design arguments is that the evidential force of specific R s is affected by the context of their occurrence. Specifically, properties which seem to constitute marks of design in known artifacts often seem to have significantly less evidential import outside that context. For instance, we typically construe enormous complexity in something known to be a manufactured artifact as a deliberately intended and produced characteristic. But mere complexity in contexts not taken to involve artifacts (the precise arrangement of pine needles on a forest floor, for instance) does not seem to have that same force. In the case of natural objects, it is less clear that such complexity—as well as the other traditional empirical R s—bespeaks intention, plan, and purpose.

Furthermore, even within those two contexts—artifact and nature—the various R s exhibit varying degrees of evidential force. For instance, even in an artifact, mere complexity of whatever degree speaks less clearly of intent than does an engraved sentence. As most critics of design arguments point out, the examples found in nature are not of the “engraved sentence” sort.

2.2.3 Gaps and Their Discontents

Evidential ambiguity would virtually disappear if it became clear that there is no plausible means of producing some R independent of deliberate intent. Part of the persuasiveness of (6) historically came from absence of any known plausible non-intentional alternative causal account of the traditional R s. Such cases are often linked to alleged gaps in nature—phenomena for which, it is claimed, there can be no purely natural explanation, there being a gap between nature’s production capabilities and the phenomenon in question. (For example, nature’s unaided capabilities fall short of producing a radio.) Design cases resting upon nature’s alleged inability to produce some relevant ‘natural’ phenomenon are generally assumed to explicitly or implicitly appeal to supernatural agency, and are typically described as “God-of-the-gaps” arguments—a description usually intended to be pejorative.

The position that there are causal gaps in nature is not inherently irrational—and would seem to be a legitimate empirical question. But although gaps would profoundly strengthen design arguments, they have their suite of difficulties. Gaps are usually easy to spot in cases of artifactuality (take the radio example, again), but although they may be present in nature, establishing their existence there can usually be done (by science, at least) only indirectly—via probability considerations, purported limitations on nature’s abilities, etc.

Several possible snags lurk. Gaps in nature would, again, suggest supernatural agency, and some take science to operate under an obligatory exclusion of such. This prohibition—commonly known as methodological naturalism —is often claimed (mistakenly, some argue) to be definitive of genuine science. [ 5 ] While such “established” limitations on science have been overturned in the past, the spotty track record of alleged gaps provides at least a cautionary note. Purported gaps have been closed by new scientific theories postulating means of natural production of phenomena previously thought to be beyond nature’s capabilities. The most obvious example of that is, of course, Darwin’s evolutionary theory and its descendants.

Some philosophers of science claim that in a wide variety of scientific cases we employ an “inference to the best explanation” (IBE). [ 6 ] The basic idea is that if one among a number of competing candidate explanations is overall superior to others in significant respects—enhanced likelihood, explanatory power and scope, causal adequacy, plausibility, evidential support, fit with already-accepted theories, predictiveness, fruitfulness, precision, unifying power, and the like—then we are warranted in (provisionally) accepting that candidate as the right explanation given the evidence in question (Lipton 1991, 58). Some advocates see design arguments as inferences to the best explanation, taking design explanations—whatever their weaknesses—as prima facie superior to chance, necessity, chance-driven evolution, or whatever.

A general schema deployed in the current case would give us the following:

Schema 3 : Some things in nature (or nature itself, the cosmos) exhibit exquisite complexity, delicate adjustment of means to ends (and other relevant R characteristics). The hypothesis that those characteristics are products of deliberate, intentional design (Design Hypothesis) would adequately explain them. In fact, the hypothesis that those characteristics are products of deliberate, intentional design (Design Hypothesis) is the best available overall explanation of them. Therefore (probably) Some things in nature (or nature itself, the cosmos) are products of deliberate, intentional design (i.e., the Design Hypothesis is likely true).

In arguments of this type, superior explanatory virtues of a theory are taken as constituting epistemic support for the acceptability of the theory or for the likely truth of the theory.

There are, of course, multitudes of purported explanatory, epistemic virtues, including the incomplete list a couple of paragraphs back. Assessing hypotheses in terms of such virtues is often contentious. The assessment of ‘best’ is not only a value-tinged judgment, but is notoriously tricky (especially given the ambiguous and hard to pinpoint import of the R s in the present case). There is also the very deep question of why we should think that features which we humans find attractive in proposed explanations should be thought to be truth-tracking. What sort of justification might be available here?

2.3.1 IBE, Likelihood and Bayes

One key underlying structure in this context is typically traced to Peirce’s notion of abduction . Suppose that some otherwise surprising fact e would be a reasonably expectable occurrence were hypothesis h true. That, Peirce argued, would constitute at least some provisional reason for thinking that h might be true. Peirce’s own characterization was as follows (Peirce 1955, 151):

Schema 3: The surprising fact, C , is observed. But if A were true, C would be a matter of course. Hence, There is reason to suspect that A is true.

The measure of C being a ‘matter of course’ given A is frequently described as the degree to which C could be expected were A true. This intuition is sometimes—though explicitly not by Peirce himself—formalized in terms of likelihood, defined as follows:

The likelihood of hypothesis \(h\) (given evidence \(e\)) = \(P(e | h)\)

The likelihood of h is the probability of finding evidence e given that the hypothesis h is true. In cases of competing explanatory hypotheses \(h_1\) and \(h_2\) the comparative likelihoods on specified evidence can be taken to indicate which of the competitors the evidence better supports, i.e.:

Likelihood Principle : \( [P(e| h_1) > P(e|h_2)] \leftrightarrow\) (\(e\) supports \(h_1\) more than it does \(h_2\))

Higher likelihood of \(h_1\) than \(h_2\) on specific evidence does not automatically imply that \(h_1\) is likely to be true, or is better in some overall sense than is \(h_2\). \(h_1\) might, in fact, be a completely lunatic theory which nonetheless entails e , giving \(h_1\) as high a likelihood as possible. Such maximal likelihood relative to e would not necessarily alter \(h_1\)’s lunacy. Likelihood thus does not automatically translate into a measure of how strongly some specific evidence e supports the hypothesis \(h_1\) in question (Jantzen 2014a, Chap. 11). Given this limitation, some argue that only a full-blown Bayesian analysis should be used to assess competing hypotheses. For a contrast between IBE and Bayesianism, see the entry on abduction . For an important recent critique of theistic design arguments in Bayesian terms, see Sober 2009, the reply in Kotzen 2012, and the response in Jantzen 2014b.

There are other potential issues here as well. Sober argues that without additional very specific assumptions about the putative designer we could specify no particular value for \(P(e | h)\) — e.g., the likelihood that a designer would produce vertebrate eyes with the specific features we observe. Depending on the specific assumptions made we could come up with any value from 0 to 1 (e.g., Sober 2003, 38). Jantzen argues that the same problem applies to any likelihood involving chance as an alternative hypothesis to design. Chance is equally vague. If we allow the naturalist to fill it out in ways that reduce this vagueness, the design theorist should be accorded the same benefit (Jantzen 2014a, 184).

There is also the potential problem of new, previously unconsidered hypotheses all lumped together in the catch-all basket. Without knowing the details of what specific unconsidered hypotheses might look like, there is simply no plausible way to anticipate the apparent likelihood of a novel new hypothesis. This, on some views, is essentially what happened with traditional design arguments. Such arguments were the most reasonable available until Darwinian evolution provided a plausible (or better) alternative the details and likelihood of which were not previously anticipatable. We should note that the problem of unconsidered hypotheses is an issue for all likelihood arguments, not merely those involving design.

3. Alternative Explanation

Without going into the familiar details, Darwinian processes fueled by undesigned, unplanned, chance variations that are in turn conserved or eliminated by way of natural selection would, it is argued, over time produce organisms exquisitely adapted to their environmental niches. [ 7 ] And since many of the characteristics traditionally cited as evidences of design just were various adaptations, evolution would thus produce entities exactly fitting traditional criteria of design. Natural selection, then, unaided by intention or intervention could account for the existence of many (perhaps all) of the R s which we find in biology. (A parallel debate can be found between those who believe that life itself requires a design explanation (Meyer 2009) and those proposing naturalistic explanations; see the entry on life .)

That was—and is—widely taken as meaning that design arguments depending upon specific biological gaps would be weakened—perhaps fatally.

Premise (10)—not to mention the earlier (6)—would thus look to simply be false. What had earlier appeared to be purpose (requiring intent) was now apparently revealed as mere unintended but successful and preserved function .

Of course, relevant premises being false merely undercuts the relevant schemas in present form—it does not necessarily refute either the basic design intuition or other forms of design arguments. But some critics take a much stronger line here. Richard Dawkins, for instance, subtitles one of his books: “Why the evidence of evolution reveals a universe without design” (Dawkins, 1987). Typically underlying claims of this sort is the belief that Darwinian evolution, by providing a relevant account of the origin and development of adaptation, diversity, and the like, has explained away the alleged design in the biological realm—and an attendant designer—in much the same way that kinetic theory has explained away caloric. Indeed, this is a dominant idea underlying current responses to design arguments. However, undercutting and explaining away are not necessarily the same thing, and exactly what explaining away might mean, and what a successful explaining away might require are typically not clearly specified. So before continuing, we need clarity concerning some relevant conceptual landscape.

3.1 Explaining Away [ 8 ]

That an alleged explanatory factor α is provisionally explained away requires that there be an alternative explanation Σ meeting these conditions:

  • Σ is explanatorily adequate to the relevant phenomenon (structure, property, entity, event)
  • Σ can be rationally supported in terms of available (or likely) evidence
  • Σ is relevantly superior to the original in terms either of adequacy or support
  • Σ requires no essential reference to α

However, (a) – (d) are incomplete in a way directly relevant to the present discussion. Here is a very simple case. Suppose that an elderly uncle dies in suspicious circumstances, and a number of the relatives believe that the correct explanation is the direct agency of a niece who is primary heir, via deliberately and directly administering poison. However, forensic investigation establishes that the cause of death was a mix-up among medications the uncle was taking—an unfortunate confusion. The suspicious relatives, however, without missing an explanatory beat shift the niece’s agency back one level, proposing that the mix-up itself was orchestrated by the niece—switching contents of prescription bottles, no doubt. And that might very well turn out to be the truth.

In that sort of case, the α in question (e.g., niecely agency) is no longer directly appealed to in the relevant initial explanatory level, but is not removed from all explanatory relevance to the phenomenon in question. In general, then, for α to be explained away in the sense of banished from all explanatory relevance the following condition must also be met:

  • no reference to α is required at any explanatory level underlying Σ

Roughly this means that Σ does not depend essentially on any part β of any prior explanation where α is essential to β. There are some additional possible technical qualifications required, but the general intuition should be clear.

Thus, e.g., whereas there was no need to appeal to caloric at some prior or deeper level, with design, according to various design advocates, there is still an explanatory lacuna (or implicit promissory note) requiring reference to design at some explanatory level prior to Darwinian evolution. Indeed, as some see it (and as Paley himself suggested), there are phenomena requiring explanation in design terms which cannot be explained away at any prior explanatory level (short of the ultimate level).

That some phenomenon α has been explained away can be taken to mean two very different things—either as

  • showing that it is no longer rational to believe that α exists
  • showing that α does not exist

(And often, of course, both.)

For instance, few would assert that there is still an extant rational case for belief in phlogiston—any explanatory work it did at the proximate level seems to have ceased, and deeper explanatory uses for it have never subsequently materialized. Perhaps its non-existence was not positively established immediately, but removal of rational justification for belief in some entity can morph into a case for non-existence as the evidence for a rival hypothesis increases over time.

3.1.1 Level-shifting

Purported explanations can be informally divided into two broad categories—those involving agents, agency, intention, and the like; and those involving mechanism, physical causality, natural processes, and the like. The distinction is not clean (functioning artifacts typically involve both), but is useful enough in a rough and ready way, and in what follows agent explanations and mechanical explanations respectively will be used as convenient handles. Nothing pernicious is built into either the broad distinction or the specified terminology.

There are some instructive patterns that emerge in explanatory level-shifting attempts, and in what immediately follows some of the more basic patterns will be identified.

(a) Agent explanations

Intention, intervention, and other agency components of explanations can very frequently be pushed back to prior levels—much as many defenders of teleological arguments claim. The earlier case of the alleged poisoning of the rich uncle by the niece is a simple example of this.

But in some cases, the specifics of the agent explanation in question may appeal to some prior level less plausible or sensible. For example, suppose that one held the view that crop circles were to be explained in terms of direct alien activity. One could, upon getting irrefutable video proof of human production of crop circles, still maintain that aliens were from a distance controlling the brains of the humans in question, and that thus the responsibility for crop circles did still lie with alien activity. While this retreat of levels preserves the basic explanation, it of course comes with a significant cost in inherent implausibility.

Still the level-changing possibility is as a general rule available with proposed agent explanations.

(b) Mechanical explanations

Pushing specific explanatory factors back to a prior level often works less smoothly in cases of purely mechanical/physical explanations than in intentional/agency explanations. In many attempted mechanistic relocation cases, it is difficult to see how the specific relocated explanatory factor is even supposed to work, much less generate any new explanatory traction. Exactly what would caloric do if pushed back one level, for instance?

Although level shifting of specific explanatory factors seems to work less easily within purely physical explanations, relocation attempts involving broad physical principles can sometimes avoid such difficulties. For instance, for centuries determinism was a basic background component of scientific explanations (apparently stochastic processes being explained away epistemically). Then, early in the 20th century physics was largely converted to a quantum mechanical picture of nature as involving an irreducible indeterminism at a fundamental level—apparently deterministic phenomena now being what was explained away. However, DeBroglie, Bohm and others (even for a time Einstein) tried to reinstate determinism by moving it back to an even deeper fundamental level via hidden variable theories. Although the hidden variable attempt is generally thought not to be successful, its failure is not a failure of principle.

3.1.2 Possible disputes

How one assesses the legitimacy, plausibility, or likelihood of the specific counter-explanation will bear substantial weight here, and that in turn will depend significantly on among other things background beliefs, commitments, metaphysical dispositions, and the like. If one has a prior commitment to some key α (e.g., to theism, atheism, naturalism, determinism, materialism, or teleology), or assigns a high prior to that α, the plausibility of taking the proposed (new) explanation as undercutting, defeating, or refuting α (and/or Σ) will be deeply affected, at least initially.

Tilting the conceptual landscape via prior commitments is both an equal opportunity epistemic necessity and a potential pitfall here. Insisting on pushing an explanatory factor back a level is often an indication of a strong prior commitment of some sort. Disagreement over deeper philosophical or other principles will frequently generate divergence over when something has or has not been explained away. One side, committed to the principle, will accept a level change as embodying a deeper insight into the relevant phenomenon. The other, rejecting the principle, will see an ad hoc retreat to defend an α which has in fact been explained away.

Returning to the present issue, design argument advocates will of course reject the claim that design, teleology, agency and the like have been explained away either by science generally or by Darwinian evolution in particular. Reasons will vary. Some will see any science—Darwinian evolution included—as incompetent to say anything of ultimate design relevance, pro or con. (Many on both sides of the design issue fit here.) Some will see Darwinian evolution as failing condition (a), (b) and/or (c), claiming that Darwinian evolution is not explanatorily adequate to selected α’s, is inadequately supported by the evidence, and is far from superior to agency explanations of relevant phenomena. (Creationists and some—not all—‘intelligent design’ advocates fit here.) Some will argue that a Darwinian failure occurs at (d), citing e.g., a concept of information claimed to be both essential to evolution and freighted with agency. (Some intelligent design advocates fit here; see Dembski 2002 and Meyer 1998.) However, the major contention of present interest involves (e).

Historically, design cases were in fact widely understood to allow for indirect intelligent agent design and causation, the very causal structures producing the relevant phenomena being themselves deliberately designed for the purpose of producing those phenomena. [ 9 ] For instance, it was typically believed that God could have initiated special conditions and processes at the instant of creation which operating entirely on their own could produce organisms and other intended (and designed) results with no subsequent agent intervention required. Paley himself, the authors of the Bridgewater Treatises and others were explicitly clear that whether or not something was designed was an issue largely separable from the means of production in question. Historically it was insisted that design in nature did track back eventually to intelligent agency somewhere and that any design we find in nature would not—and could not—have been there had there ultimately been no mind involved. But commentators (including many scientists) at least from the early 17th century on (e.g., Francis Bacon and Robert Boyle) very clearly distinguished the creative initiating of nature itself from interventions within the path of nature once initiated. For instance, over two centuries before Darwin, Bacon wrote:

God … doth accomplish and fulfill his divine will [by ways] not immediate and direct, but by compass; not violating Nature, which is his own law upon the creation. (Quoted in Whewell 1834, 358)

Indeed, if the R s in question did directly indicate the influence of a mind, then means of production—whether unbroken causation or gappy—would be of minimal evidential importance. Thus, the frequent contemporary claim that design arguments all involve appeal to special divine intervention during the course of nature’s history—that in short design arguments are “God-of-the-gaps” arguments—represents serious historical (and present) inaccuracy.

However, if R s result from gapless chains of natural causal processes, the evidential impact of those R s again threatens to become problematic and ambiguous, since there will a fortiori be at the immediate level a full natural causal account for them. [ 10 ] Design will, in such cases, play no immediate mechanistic explanatory role, suggesting its superfluousness. But even if such conceptions were explanatorily and scientifically superfluous at that level, that does not entail that they are conceptually, alethically, inferential, or otherwise superfluous in general. The role of mind might be indirect, deeply buried, or at several levels of remove from the immediate production mechanism but would still have to be present at some level. In short, on the above picture Darwinian evolution will not meet condition (e) for explaining away design, which is not itself a shortcoming of Darwinian evolution.

But any gap-free argument will depend crucially upon the R s in question being ultimately dependent for their eventual occurrence upon agent activity. That issue could be integrated back into an altered Schema 2 by replacing (6) with:

(6a) Design-like properties ( R ) are (most probably) not producible by means ultimately devoid of mind/intention—i.e., any phenomena exhibiting such R s must be a product (at least indirectly) of intentional design.

The focus must now become whether or not the laws and conditions required for the indirect production of life, intelligent life, etc., could themselves be independent of intention, design, and mind at some deep (perhaps primordial, pre-cosmic) point. In recent decades, exactly that question has arisen increasingly insistently from within the scientific community.

4. Further Contemporary Design Discussions

4.1 cosmological: fine-tuning.

Intuitively, if the laws of physics were different, the evolution of life would not have taken the same path. If gravity were stronger, for example, then flying insects and giraffes would most likely not exist. Contemporary physics provides significantly more drama to the story. Even an extraordinarily small change in one of many key parameters in the laws of physics would have made life impossible anywhere in the universe. Consider two examples:

The expansion rate of the universe is represented by the cosmological constant Λ. If Λ were slighter greater, there would be no energy sources, such as stars. If it were slightly less, the Big Bang would have quickly led to a Big Crunch in which the universe collapsed back onto itself. For life to be possible, Λ cannot vary more than one part in 10 53 (Collins 2003)

Life depends on, among other things, a balance of carbon and oxygen in the universe. If the strong nuclear force were different by 0.4%, there would not be enough of one or the other for life to exist (Oberhummer, Csótó, and Schlattl 2000). Varying this constant either way “would destroy almost all carbon or almost all oxygen in every star” (Barrow 2002, 155).

Many examples of fine-tuning have to do with star formation. Stars are important since life requires a variety of elements: oxygen, carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, calcium, and phosphorus. Stars contain the only known mechanism for producing large quantities of these elements and are therefore necessary for life. Lee Smolin estimates that when all of the fine-tuning examples are considered, the chance of stars existing in the universe is 1 in 10 229 . “In my opinion, a probability this tiny is not something we can let go unexplained. Luck will certainly not do here; we need some rational explanation of how something this unlikely turned out to be the case” (Smolin 1999, 45). Smolin is not merely claiming that all improbable events require an explanation, but some improbable events are special. (In poker, every set of five cards dealt to the dealer has the same probability, assuming that the cards are shuffled sufficiently. If the dealer is dealt a pair on three successive hands, no special explanation is required. If the dealer is dealt a royal flush on three successive hands, an explanation would rightly be demanded, and the improbability of this case isn’t even close to the magnitude of the improbability that Smolin mentioned.) Physicists who have written on fine-tuning agree with Smolin that it cries out for an explanation. (What physicists in general think is, of course, harder to determine.) One explanation is that the universe appears to be fine-tuned for the existence of life because it literally has been constructed for life by an intelligent agent.

There are two other types of responses to fine-tuning: (i) it does not, in fact, require a special explanation, and (ii) there are alternative explanations to theistic design. Let’s briefly consider these (also see the entry on fine-tuning ).

Three approaches have been taken to undermine the demand for explanation presented by fine-tuning.

4.1.1.1 Weak anthropic principle

In a sense, it is necessary for the fine-tuned constants to have values in the life-permitting range: If those values were not within that range, people would not exist. The fine-tuned constants must take on the values that they have in order for scientists to be surprised by their discovery in the first place. They could not have discovered anything else. According to the weak anthropic principle, we ought not to be surprised by having made such a discovery, since no other observation was possible. But if we should not have been surprised to have made such a discovery, then there is nothing unusual here that requires a special explanation. The demand for explanation is simply misplaced.

4.1.1.2 Observational selection effect

Sober gives a related but stronger argument based on observational selection effects (Sober 2009, 77–80). Say that Jones nets a large number of fish from a local lake, all of which are over 10 inches long. Let \(h_{\textrm{all}}\) = ‘all of the fish in the lake are over 10 inches long’ and \(h_{1/2}\) = ‘Half of the fish in the lake are over 10 inches long’. The evidence \(e\) is such that \(P(e|h_{\textrm{all}}) > P(e | h_{1/2})\). Now say that Jones discovers that his net is covered with 10 inch holes, preventing him from capturing any smaller fish. In that case, \(e\) does not favor one hypothesis over the other. The evidence \(e\) is an artifact of the net itself, not a random sample of the fish in the lake.

When it comes to fine-tuning, Sober considers \(h_{\textrm{design}}\) = ‘the constants have been set in place by an intelligence, specifically God’, and \(h_{\textrm{chance}}\) = ‘the constants are what they are as a matter of mindless random chance’. While intuitively

\(P(\textrm{constants are just right for life} | h_{\textrm{design}}) >\) \(\;\; P(\textrm{constants are just right for life} | h_{\textrm{chance}}) \)

one has to consider the role of the observer, who is analogous to the net in the fishing example. Since human observers could only detect constants in the life-permitting range, Sober argues, the correct probabilities are

\( P(\textrm{you observe that the constants are right} | h_{\textrm{design}} \amp \textrm{you exist}) =\) \(\;\; P(\textrm{you observe that the constants are right} | h_{\textrm{chance}} \amp \textrm{you exist}) \)

Given this equality, fine-tuning does not favor \(h_{\textrm{design}}\) over \(h_{\textrm{chance}}\). The selection effect prevents any confirmation of design.

Sober’s analysis is critiqued in Monton 2006 and Kotzen 2012. Also see Jantzen 2014a (sec. 18.4). We should note that if Sober is correct, then the naturalistic explanations for fine-tuning considered below (4.1.2) are likewise misguided.

4.1.1.3 Probabilities do not apply

Let C stand for a fine-tuned parameter with physically possible values in the range [0, ∞). If we assume that nature is not biased toward one value of C rather than another, then each unit subinterval in this range should be assigned equal probability. Fine-tuning is surprising insofar as the life-permitting range of C is tiny compared to the full interval, which corresponds to a very small probability.

As McGrew, McGrew & Vestrup argue (2001), there is a problem here in that, strictly speaking, mathematical probabilities do not apply in these circumstances. When a probability distribution is defined over a space of possible outcomes, it must add up to exactly 1. But for any uniform distribution over an infinitely large space, the sum of the probabilities will grow arbitrarily large as each unit interval is added up. Since the range of C is infinite, McGrew et al . conclude that there is no sense in which life-friendly universes are improbable; the probabilities are mathematically undefined.

One solution to this problem is to truncate the interval of possible values. Instead of allowing C to range from [0, ∞), one could form a finite interval [0, N ], where N is very large relative to the life-permitting range of C . A probability distribution could then be defined over the truncated range.

A more rigorous account employs measure theory. Measure is sometimes used in physics as a surrogate for probability. For example, there are many more irrational numbers than rational ones. In measure theoretic terms, almost all real numbers are irrational, where “almost all” means all but a set of zero measure. In physics, a property found for almost all of the solutions to an equation requires no explanation; it’s what one should expect. It’s not unusual, for instance, for a pin balancing on its tip to fall over. Falling over is to be expected. In contrast, if a property that has zero measure in the relevant space were actually observed to be the case, like the pin continuing to balance on its tip, that would demand a special explanation (Earman 1987, 315). Assuming one’s model for the system is correct, nature appears to be strongly biased against such behavior (Gibbons, Hawking & Stewart 1987, 736). The argument for fine-tuning can thus be recast such that almost all values of C are outside of the life-permitting range. The fact that our universe is life-permitting is therefore in need of explanation.

The question of whether probabilities either do not apply or have been improperly applied to cosmological fine-tuning continues to draw interest. For more, see Davies 1992, Callender 2004, Holder 2004, Koperski 2005, Manson 2009, Jantzen 2014a (sec. 18.3), and Sober 2019 (sec. 5.1). Manson (2018) argues that neither theism nor naturalism provides a better explanation for fine-tuning.

Assuming that fine-tuning does require an explanation, there are several approaches one might take (Koperski 2015, section 2.4).

4.1.2.1 Scientific progress

That the universe is fine-tuned for life is based on current science. Just as current science explained or explained away many past anomalies, future science may explain or explain away fine-tuning. Science may one day find a naturalistic answer, eliminating the need for design. For suggestions along these lines, see Harnik, Kribs & Perez 2006, and Loeb 2014.

While this is a popular stance, it is a promissory note rather than an explanation. The appeal to what might yet be discovered is not itself a rival hypothesis.

4.1.2.2 Exotic life

It’s conceivable that life could exist in a universe with parameter values that we do not typically believe are life-permitting. In other words, there may be exotic forms of life that could survive in a very different sort of universe. If so, then perhaps the parameter intervals that are in fact life-permitting are not fine-tuned after all.

The main difficulty with this suggestion is that all life requires a means for overcoming the second law of thermodynamics. Life requires the extraction of energy from the environment. Any life-form imaginable must therefore have systems that allow for something like metabolism and respiration, which in turn require a minimal amount of complexity (e.g., there can be no single-molecule life forms). Many examples of fine-tuning do not allow for such complexity, however. If there were no stars, for example, then there would be no stable sources of energy and no mechanism for producing the heavier elements in the periodic table. Such a universe would lack the chemical building blocks needed for a living entity to extract energy from the environment and thereby resist the pull of entropy.

4.1.2.3 Multiverse

While the odds of winning a national lottery are low, your odds would obviously increase if you were to buy several million tickets. The same idea applies to the most popular explanation for fine-tuning: a multiverse. Perhaps physical reality consists of a massive array of universes each with a different set of values for the relevant constants. If there are many—perhaps infinitely many—universes, then the odds of a life-permitting universe being produced would seem to be much greater. While most of the universes in the multiverse would be unfit for life, so the argument goes, ours is one of the few where all of the constants have the required values.

While the philosophical literature on the multiverse continues to grow (see Collins 2009, 2012, and Kraay 2014), many of the arguments against it share a common premise: a multiverse would not, by itself, be a sufficient explanation of fine-tuning. More would have to be known about the way in which universes are produced. By analogy, just because a roulette wheel has 38 spaces does not guarantee that the probability of Red 25 is 1/38. If the wheel is rigged in some way—by using magnets for example—to prevent that outcome, then the probability might be extremely small. If the table were rigged and yet Red 25 was the actual winner, that would require a special explanation. Likewise, one would have to know whether universe production within the multiverse is biased for, against, or is indifferent to the life-permitting values of the relevant constants. Depending on the outcome, the existence of a multiverse might or might not explain fine-tuning.

A more pressing problem would be the proliferation of “Boltzmann brains” (BB) in a multiverse (Carroll 2020). BBs are intelligent beings produced by quantum fluctuations. The beliefs of such nonstandard observers are formed by random processes and therefore lack rational support. Since there would be many orders of magnitude more BBs than standard observers in a multiverse, it is statistically likely that you are not, in fact, a standard observer after all. This fact serves as a defeater for most of your beliefs, including your belief in a multiverse. Belief in a multiverse is therefore self-defeating.

4.2 Biological: Intelligent Design

A high-profile development in design arguments over the past 20 years or so involves what has come to be known as Intelligent Design (ID). Although there are variants, it generally involves efforts to construct design arguments taking cognizance of various contemporary scientific developments (primarily in biology, biochemistry, and cosmology)—developments which, as most ID advocates see it, both reveal the inadequacy of mainstream explanatory accounts (condition (a)) and offer compelling evidence for design in nature at some level (condition (e) again).

ID advocates propose two specialized R s— irreducible complexity (Behe 1996) and specified complex information (Dembski 1998, 2002). [ 11 ] Although distinctions are sometimes blurred and while ID arguments involving each of those R s tend to be gap arguments, an additional focus on mind-reflective aspects of nature is typically more visible in ID arguments citing specified complexity than in arguments citing irreducible complexity.

The movement has elicited vociferous criticism and opposition (Pennock 2000). Opponents have pressed a number of objections against ID including, inter alia contentions that ID advocates have simply gotten the relevant science wrong, that even where the science is right the empirical evidences cited by design advocates do not constitute substantive grounds for design conclusions, that the existence of demonstrably superior alternative explanations for the phenomena cited undercuts the cogency of ID cases, and that design theories are not legitimate science , but are just disguised creationism, God-of-the-gaps arguments, religiously motivated, etc.

We will not pursue that dispute here except to note that even if the case is made that ID could not count as proper science, which is controversial, [ 12 ] that would not in itself demonstrate a defect in design arguments as such. Science need not be seen as exhausting the space of legitimate conclusions from empirical data. In any case, the floods of vitriol flowing from both sides in the current ID discussion suggest that much more than the propriety of selected inferences from particular empirical evidences is at issue.

That question is: why do design arguments remain so durable if empirical evidence is inferentially ambiguous, the arguments logically controversial, and the conclusions vociferously disputed? One possibility is that they really are better arguments than most philosophical critics concede. Another possibility is that design intuitions do not rest upon inferences at all. The situation may parallel that of the existence of an external world, the existence of other minds, and a number of other familiar matters. The 18th century Scottish Common Sense philosopher Thomas Reid (and his contemporary followers) argued that we are simply so constructed that in certain normally-realized experiential circumstances we simply find that we in fact have involuntary convictions about such a world, about other minds, and so forth. That would explain why historical philosophical attempts to reconstruct the arguments by which such beliefs either arose or were justified were such notorious failures—failures in the face of which ordinary belief nonetheless proceeded happily and helplessly onward. If a similar involuntary belief-producing mechanism operated with respect to intuitions of design, that would similarly explain why argumentative attempts have been less than universally compelling but yet why design ideas fail to disappear despite the purported failure of such arguments.

A number of prominent figures historically in fact held that we could determine more or less perceptually that various things in nature were candidates for design attributions—that they were in the requisite respects design- like . Some, like William Whewell, held that we could perceptually identify some things as more than mere candidates for design (1834, 344). Thomas Reid also held a view in this region, [ 13 ] as did Hume’s Cleanthes, and, more recently, Alvin Plantinga (2011, 263–264).

If something like that were the operative process, then ID, in trying to forge a scientific link to design in the sense of inferences from empirically determined evidences would be misconstructing the actual basis for design belief, as would be design arguments more generally. It is perhaps telling, in this regard, that scientific theorizing typically involves substantial creativity and that the resultant theories are typically novel and unexpected. Design intuitions, however, do not seem to emerge as novel construals from creative grappling with data, but are embedded in our thinking nearly naturally—so much so that, again, Crick thinks that biologists have to be immunized against it.

Perception and appreciation of the incredible intricacy and the beauty of things in nature—whether biological or cosmic—has certainly inclined many toward thoughts of purpose and design in nature, and has constituted important moments of affirmation for those who already accept design positions. Regardless of what one thinks of the arguments at this point, so long as nature has the power to move us (as even Kant admitted that the ‘starry heavens above’ did), design convictions and arguments are unlikely to disappear quietly.

  • Babbage, Charles, 1838. Ninth Bridgewater Treatise: A Fragment , London: J. Murray.
  • Barrow, John D. 2002. The Constants of Nature , New York: Pantheon Books.
  • Behe, Michael, 1996. Darwin’s Black Box , New York: Free Press.
  • Boyle, Robert, 1685–6. Free Inquiry into the Vulgarly Receiv’d Notions of Nature , in Hall 1965, pp. 150–153.
  • –––, 1688. A Disquisition about the Final Causes of Natural Things , London: John Taylor.
  • Broad, C.D., 1925. The Mind and its Place in Nature , London: Kegan Paul.
  • Callender, Craig, 2004. “Measures, Explanations and the Past: Should ‘Special’ Initial Conditions Be Explained,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 55(2): 195–217.
  • Carroll, Sean M., 2020. “Why Boltzmann Brains Are Bad,” in Current Controversies in Philosophy of Science , edited by Shamik Dasgupta, Brad Weslake, and Ravit Dotan, 7–20. New York: Routledge.
  • Chesterton, G.K., 1908. “Ethics of Elfland,” in Orthodoxy , New York: John Lane, pp. 106–7.
  • Collins, Robin, 2003. “Evidence for Fine-Tuning,” in God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science , edited by Neil A. Manson, 178–99. New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 2009. “The Teleological Argument: An Exploration of the Fine-Tuning of the Universe,” in The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology , edited by William Lane Craig and J.P. Moreland, 202–81. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • –––, 2012. “Modern Cosmology and Anthropic Fine-Tuning: Three Approaches,” in Georges Lemaître: Life, Science and Legacy , edited by Rodney D. Holder and Simon Mitton. Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer.
  • Crick, Francis, 1988. What Mad Pursuit , New York: Basic.
  • Darwin, Charles, 1859 [1966]. On the Origin of Species , Facsimile first edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Darwin, Charles, 1887. Life and Letters of Charles Darwin , Vol. 1, Francis Darwin (ed.), New York: D. Appleton.
  • –––, 1902 [1995]. The Life of Charles Darwin , Francis Darwin (ed.), London: Senate.
  • –––, 1987. Charles Darwin’s Notebooks, 1836–1844 . Transcribed and edited by Paul Barrett, Peter Gautrey, Sandra Herbert, Dave Kohn and Sydney Smith, Ithaca: Cornell.
  • Davies, Paul, 1992. The Mind of God , New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • –––, 1995. Are We Alone? , New York: Basic.
  • Dawkins, Richard, 1987. Blind Watchmaker , New York: Norton.
  • Dembski, William, 1998. The Design Inference , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Earman, John. 1987. “The SAP Also Rises: A Critical Examination of the Anthropic Principle,” American Philosophical Quarterly , 24(4): 307–17.
  • Edwards, Jonathan, 1980. The Works of Jonathan Edwards Wallace Anderson (ed.), Volume 6: Scientific and Philosophical Writings , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Fitelson, Brandon, 2007. “Likelihood, Bayesianism, and Relational Confirmation,” Synthese , 156: 473–489.
  • Foster, John, 1982–3. “Induction, Explanation and Natural Necessity,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 83: 87–101.
  • Foster, John, 1985. A. J. Ayer , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Gillispie, Neal C., 1990. “Divine Design and the Industrial Revolution: William Paley’s Abortive Reform of Natural Theology,” Isis , 81: 213–229.
  • Glass, Marvin and Julian Wolfe, 1986. “Paley’s Design Argument for God,” Sophia , 25(2): 17–19.
  • Gibbons, G. W., S. W. Hawking, and J. M. Stewart, 1987. “A Natural Measure on the Set of All Universes,” Nuclear Physics B , 281(3–4): 736–51.
  • Hall, Marie Boas, 1965. Robert Boyle on Natural Philosophy , Bloomington: Indiana University.
  • Harnik, Roni, Graham Kribs, and Gilad Perez, 2006. “A Universe without Weak Interactions,” Physical Review D , 74(3), doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.74.035006
  • Harrison, Edward, 1985. Masks of the Universe , New York: Macmillan.
  • Holder, Rodney D., 2004. God, the Multiverse, and Everything: Modern Cosmology and the Argument from Design , Aldershot: Ashgate.
  • Hoyle, Frederick, 1982. “The Universe: Past and Present Reflections,” Annual Review of Astronomy and Astrophysics , 20: 1–35.
  • Hume, David, 1779 [1998]. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion , Richard Popkin (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Janet, Paul, 1884. Final Causes , 2nd edition, Robert Flint (trans.), New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
  • Jantzen, Benjamin C., 2014a. An Introduction to Design Arguments , New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2014b. “Piecewise versus Total Support: How to Deal with Background Information in Likelihood Arguments,” Philosophy of Science , 81(3): 313–31.
  • Kingsley, Charles, 1890. Water Babies , London: Macmillan.
  • Koperski, Jeffrey. 2005. “Should We Care about Fine-Tuning?” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 56(2): 303–19.
  • –––, 2015. The Physics of Theism: God, Physics, and the Philosophy of Science . Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Kotzen, Matthew, 2012. “Selection Biases in Likelihood Arguments,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 63(4): 825–39.
  • Kraay, Klaas. 2014. God and the Multiverse: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Perspectives . Routledge.
  • Lenoir, Timothy, 1982. Strategy of Life , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Lipton, Peter, 1991. Inference to the Best Explanation . 1st Edition. London: Routledge.
  • Loeb, Abraham, 2014. “The Habitable Epoch of the Early Universe,” International Journal of Astrobiology , 13(4): 337–339.
  • Manson, Neil (ed.), 2003. God and Design: The teleological argument and modern science , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 2009. “The Fine-Tuning Argument,” Philosophy Compass , 4(1): 271–86.
  • –––, 2018. “How Not to Be Generous to Fine-Tuning Sceptics,” Religious Studies , first online 21 September 2018, doi:10.1017/S0034412518000586
  • McGrew, Timothy, Lydia McGrew, and Eric Vestrup, 2001. “Probabilities and the Fine-Tuning Argument: A Sceptical View,” Mind , 110(440): 1027–38.
  • McPherson, Thomas, 1965. The Philosophy of Religion , London: Van Nostrand.
  • Meyer, Stephen, 1998. “DNA by Design: An inference to the best explanation for the origin of biological information,” Rhetoric & Public Affairs , 1: 519–555.
  • –––, 2009. Signature in the Cell: DNA and the Evidence for Intelligent Design , New York: HarperOne.
  • Monton, Bradley. 2006. “God, Fine-Tuning, and the Problem of Old Evidence,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 57: 405–24.
  • Murray, Michael (ed.), 1999. Reason for the Hope Within , Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.
  • Oberhummer, H.H., A. Csótó, and H. Schlattl. 2000. “Fine-Tuning of Carbon Based Life in the Universe by Triple-Alpha Process in Red Giants,” Science , 289: 88–90.
  • Paley, William, 1802. Natural Theology , Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1963.
  • Peirce, Charles S., 1955. Philosophical Writings of Peirce , Justus Buchler (ed.), New York: Dover.
  • Pennock, Robert T., 2000. Tower of Babel: The Evidence against the New Creationism , Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • Penrose, Roger, 1990. The Emperor’s New Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Plantinga, Alvin, 2011. Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, and Naturalism , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ratzsch, Del, 2001. Nature, Design and Science , Albany: SUNY Press.
  • Rott, Hans, 2010. “Idealizations, Intertheory Explanations and Conditionals,” in Belief Revision Meets Philosophy of Science (Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, Volume 21), edited by E. J. Olsson and S. Enqvist, 59–76, New York: Springer.
  • –––, 2003. “Perceiving Design,” in Manson 2003, pp. 124–144.
  • Smolin, Lee. 1999. The Life of the Cosmos , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Sober, Elliott, 1993. Philosophy of Biology , Boulder: Westview.
  • –––, 2003. “The Design Argument” in Manson 2003, pp. 27–54.
  • –––, 2009. “Absence of Evidence and Evidence of Absence: Evidential Transitivity in Connection with Fossils, Fishing, Fine-Tuning, and Firing Squads,” Philosophical Studies , 143(1): 63–90.
  • –––, 2019. The Design Argument. Elements in the Philosophy of Religion , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/9781108558068
  • Whewell, William, 1834. Astronomy and General Physics Considered with Reference to Natural Theology , London: William Pickering.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • The Fine Tuning Argument: A Curated Bibliography , by Neil Manson (The University of Mississippi).
  • Natural Theology; or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity , by William Paley.
  • Design Arguments for the Existence of God , by Kenneth Einar Himma (Seattle Pacific University), hosted by the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • The Teleological Argument and the Anthropic Principle , by William Lane Craig (Talbot School of Theology), hosted by Leadership U.
  • Was the Universe Made For Us? , maintained by Nick Bostrom (Oxford University).

abduction | Bayes’ Theorem | creationism | Darwinism | fine-tuning | Hume, David | Hume, David: on religion | Kant, Immanuel | teleology: teleological notions in biology

Acknowledgments

Del Ratzsch would like to thank his colleagues in the Calvin College Philosophy Department, especially Ruth Groenhout, Kelly Clark and Terrence Cuneo, and to David van Baak.

Jeffrey Koperski would like to thank Hans Halvorson, Rodney Holder, and Thomas Tracy for helpful comments on source material for section 4. Special thanks to Benjamin Jantzen and an anonymous referee for several comments and corrections on the 2019 version.

Copyright © 2023 by Del Ratzsch Jeffrey Koperski < koperski @ svsu . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Teleological Argument

Telos - Goal, target, purpose. The Teleological Argument (Argument from Design)

1. Ancient History

Cicero is one of the earliest philosophers to discuss the idea of design in nature. In De Natura Deorum he writes,  "What could be more clear or obvious when we look up to the sky and  contemplate the heavens, than that there is some divinity or superior  intelligence?"  quoted in Davies, B. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion, p.94

Plato speaks of an "intelligible living creature" which is the model by which the Creator works (Timaeus 39).

Thomas Aquinas also discusses the evidence of Design in creation. In the fifth of his Five Ways he says, "Everything operates as to a design. This design is from God." In Summa Theologiae he links causation to purpose. Causation gives things their perfections,

"Something therefore causes in all other things their being, their  goodness, and whatever other perfections they have. And that is what  we call God"

This is then linked to the concept of purpose,

"Goal directed behaviour is observed in all bodies obeying natural laws,  even when they lack awareness…. But nothing lacking awareness can  tend to a goal except it be directed by someone with awareness and  understanding; the arrow, for example, requires an archer. Everything  in nature, therefore, is directed to its goal by someone with  understanding, and this we call God"

Aquinas argues, from the first three of his ways, that something causes things to come into existence. He goes on to argue that because everything appears to work to a purpose (c.f. Aristotle's Ideas of Causality:-

Causality - Aristotle used the example of rain:

1. Material Cause - the clouds

2. Efficient Cause - The process by which the rain is made

3. Formal Cause - The form, or nature, of the rain is to fall

4. Final Cause - The rain provides water for plants and animals to grow.

And that the purpose is from some intelligent being. This being is God.

Aquinas is arguing for Design qua Regularity - that there is something regulating the universe. This would be similar to the gardener in the parable by John Wisdom (see Jordan, Lockyer and Tate, Philosophy of Religion for 'A' Level, p.14). The gardener maintains the garden, keeping it weed free and neat and tidy. The rotation of the planets, and the mechanisms of the universe, appear to be the result of a regulating intelligence:-

Boethius, a sixth century Roman philosopher wrote:-

There are three types of music. The first type is the music of the universe, the  second, that of the human being, and the third type is that type which is  created by certain instruments…

Now the first type, that is the music of the universe, is best observed in those  things which one perceives in heaven itself, or in the structure of the  elements, or in the diversity of the seasons. How could it possibly be that such  a swift heavenly machine move so silently in its course? The orbits of the stars  are joined by such a harmony that nothing so perfectly structured can be  imagined. Thus there must be some fixed order of musical modulation in this  celestial motion.

Quoted in Wilson-Dixon, Christian Music, p40

2. William Paley (1743 - 1805)

This is the most famous form of the Argument by Design. Paley's idea of the watch is a little redundant in the world of the quartz watch, but there are other useful analogies.

"In crossing a heath, suppose I pitched my foot against a stone, and were  asked how the stone came to be there, I might possibly answer, that, for  anything I knew to be the contrary, it had lain there for ever; nor would it  perhaps be very easy to show the absurdity of this answer. But suppose I  found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the watch  happened to be in that place, I should hardly think of the answer which I had  before given, that, for anything I knew, the watch might always have been  there. Yet why should not this answer serve for the watch, as well as for the  stone? Why is it not as admissible in the second case as in the first? For this  reason, and for no other, viz., that, when we came to inspect the watch, we  perceive (what we would not discover in the stone) that its several parts  are framed and put together for a purpose, e.g. that they are so  formed and adjusted to produce motion, and that motion so regulated  as to point out the hour of the day; that, if the different parts had been  differently shaped from what they are, if a different size from what they are,  or placed after any other manner, or in any other order than that in which  they are placed either no motion at all would have been carried on in the  machine, or none which would have answered these that is now served by it.

William Paley, Natural Theology Oxford 1838

Suppose I should find a 35mm Automatic Camera. It has infrared focussing, automatic exposure control and automatic film advance. It is completely self-contained - a true "point-and-shoot" camera. Paley suggests that to argue that the camera happened "by accident" is nonsense. The camera shows obvious signs of having been designed.

Yet people suggest that the human eye, with its automatic focus and

exposure, was not the result of an intelligent design.

The argument is in two stages.

  • It tries to establish that there is order and purpose in the universe.
  • It then makes the step to the conclusion that there is something divine behind this order and purpose.

3. And now..?

The argument "to design" notes that nature appears to plan in advance for the needs of animals and plants. The possible randomness of sub atomic particles would count against life on earth - there appears to be a pattern or order at the smallest level.

Richard Swinburne suggests that the modern developments in biochemistry actually support the Teleological Argument. He notes that the work done in biochemistry appears to suggest that evolution could not be as random as the "Natural Selection" theory maintains. Terms such as "anti-chance" have been introduced into the discussion, and some have argued that the existence of the Universe is "beyond chance". F. R. Tennant argues that the Universe is "saturated" with beauty at every level. The pattern that can be detected from the subatomic to the universal level is seen as evidence for some sort of nonrandomness in the Universe (see Paul Davies , quoted on p.71 in see Jordan, Lockyer and Tate, Philosophy of Religion for 'A' Level). In reply, Dawkins and others have continued to argue for a random, yet self-arranging universe.

4. What are the odds for a random universe?

Harold Morowitz is a biochemist at George Mason University in the USA. He uses a chart of all the chemical reactions that occur in the body to study the way that life itself works.

He looked at the problem of probability for the existence of life in the Universe. He noted that there is an evens chance of heads or tails.

  • A 1/1015 chance is so remote as to become completely unlikely.
  • A 1/1050 chance could not happen in 15 billion years (the age of the Universe).

Dr Morowitz looked at the complexity of protein molecules, and concluded that the odds for such an object to happen by chance stand at 1/10236. This takes into account all the atoms in the universe, and the chances that the right ones could come together to form a protein molecule.

"The universe would have to be trillions of times older, and  trillions of times larger, for a protein molecule to have occurred by  random chance."

Morowitz’s research is a bit like saying that you could toss 4 billion coins in the air. The odds of them all landing heads up is the same as the odds for that protein molecule to exist at all.

For the protein molecule to exist, you would need more than 15 billion years, and more atoms. In Other Words – there aren’t enough atoms, and there isn’t enough time.

Science and Creation

Scientists are divided over the possibility of design and purpose in the Universe.

  • Some argue that the universe is entirely random (see Dawkins et al). They say that life is more probable that we might think, and that it occurs throughout the universe.
  • However, despite years of searching, SETI (Search for Extra-Terrestrial Intelligence) has failed to find any evidence for life anywhere other than on earth.

SETI is searching for an intelligible radio signal from somewhere in the Universe. Much of what is detected by SETI’s radio telescopes is simply random static. However, if SETI should detect something nonrandom (even something simple like a dot-dash morse code signal) they would regard it as evidence of intelligence in the universe. A signal “2-2-4” would involve 10 bytes of digital information. This simple signal would be accepted by SETI as intelligent. DNA involves 4 billion bytes of information.

Francis Crick (one of the scientists who discovered DNA in the 1950s) is quoted as saying: "To the honest man ... the origin of life appears ... to be almost a miracle,  so many are the conditions which would have to be satisfied to get it  going"

sign up to revision world banner

Philosophy A Level

Teleological Argument

£ 0.00

Does the order of the universe prove that God exists? (25 marks)

This question is asking you to discuss the teleological argument (the argument that says that certain features of the world seem so perfect as to be designed by a God) and argue that it either does or doesn’t successfully prove God exists.

Similar questions:

  • Assess the teleological argument. (25 marks)
  • Do spatial and temporal order provide proof that God exists? (25 marks)

Description

An A* grade example answer to a 25 mark question on teleological arguments. This document also includes a bullet-point essay plan to help students understand how to structure their essays for maximum marks.

After completing your purchase, a download link will be sent to the email address used at checkout. If you cannot see this email, please check your spam folder or refer to our order FAQ .

teleological argument a level essay

Skip to content

Get Revising

Join get revising, already a member, the teleological argument essay.

  • Created by: Josh Bovill
  • Created on: 28-04-10 09:27
  • Ideas of gods

No comments have yet been made

Similar Philosophy resources:

The Teleological Argument and Design 0.0 / 5

Design Argument A01 0.0 / 5

How to Set Up a Philosophy Essay 0.0 / 5

How to write a philosophy essay 0.0 / 5

Design Argument 0.0 / 5

Notes on Design Argument A01 and A02 0.0 / 5

The Teleological Argument 4.0 / 5 based on 7 ratings

Medical Ethics Unit 2 Model 0.0 / 5

Utilitarianism Full Notes 0.0 / 5

Related discussions on The Student Room

  • Eduqas religious studies a level 2023 »
  • A-level Religious Studies Study Group 2022-2023 »
  • 11 weeks going from C to A* - Alevel »
  • Sociology A level »
  • AQA A Level History Exemplars »
  • AQA A Level Philosophy Paper 1 + 2 (7172/1+2) 18th and 26th May 2023 [Exam Chat] »
  • How in-depth do essay plans need to be? »
  • OCR A-Level Religious Studies Paper 1 (H573/01) 12th June 2023 [Exam Chat] »
  • BCL essay submission »
  • [deleted] »

teleological argument a level essay

Marked by Teachers

  • TOP CATEGORIES
  • AS and A Level
  • University Degree
  • International Baccalaureate
  • Uncategorised
  • 5 Star Essays
  • Study Tools
  • Study Guides
  • Meet the Team
  • Religious Studies (Philosophy & Ethics)
  • Existence of God

The Teleological Argument

Authors Avatar

Examine the main ideas and strengths of the design argument for the existence of God.

This essay will examine the main ideas and strengths of the design argument; an argument for the existence of God. This argument is also known as the teleological argument. The word ‘teleological’ derives from the Greek ‘telos’ which means an end, or an ultimate purpose. This essay will focus on William Paley’s view and his famous watchmaker analogy. William Paley was a British born philosopher who lived from 1743 to 1805 and he is best remembered for this analogy.

In William Paley’s watchmaker analogy, he likens a watch to the universe. He does this because a watch is a very intricate, complicated and sophisticated design. A watch is also designed to serve a purpose; to tell the time. Similarly, the universe is very intricate, complicated and sophisticated and just like the watch it serves a purpose - natural resources provide food, light and shelter, all of which are necessary for human existence and sustainability. Both a watch and the universe are products of intelligent design; they simply could not have appeared just by chance. Because a watch has a designer, William Paley believes that the universe too must have a designer, which leads us on to the belief that this designer is God, thus, proving his existence.

Join now!

Firstly, the watchmaker analogy is very good as it is easy to comprehend and understand. Also, a systematic approach has been taken. By this I mean that we start with the end product, the universe or watch, and work our way backwards. For example, the watch serves a purpose, the watch has been designed, the watch has a designer; a watchmaker. Likewise, the universe serves a purpose, the universe has been designed, the universe has a designer; God.

This is a preview of the whole essay

One strength of William Paley’s argument is the appearance of structure in the world - the world is not full of chaos, but of beneficial order and stability. The conditions seem to be perfect to sustain life. Surely this could not have come about by chance? The universe is made up of many different parts, all of which work together in harmony to fulfill a purpose. William Paley believed that the order apparent is evidence of an intelligent designer, for if the universe had not have been designed it would be chaotic and dysfunctional.

Another strength of the design argument is the complexity of things in the world that serve purpose. An example of this is how the human eye works. The human eye is complex not only in its structure but in its function too. It automatically focuses, analyses colour and detects light and motion. The human eye, like everything else, fulfils a purpose. In this case it’s very important, it enables us to see. Some people argue that natural selection plays a part in this, but surely something so complex and so important could not just appear over time – it must have a designer.

The anthropic principle suggests that the fundamental constants of the universe are too finely tuned to have appeared by chance or coincidence. Without these constants life would not exist. This supports the design argument as it suggests that parts of the universe are too complex and crucial to be accidental, they must therefore be a product of intelligent design. Astronomer Fred Hoyle said that the likelihood of the conditions necessary for life coming about by chance were akin to a hurricane sweeping through a scrap yard and assembling a Boeing 747.  An example of the anthropic principle is the distance between the sun and the Earth. If the sun were too far away, the planet would be too cool for a stable water system. Yet if the sun were too close, the planet would be too hot for a stable water system. We all know that water is a necessity in sustaining life, but if this fine tuning were slightly different, we would have no water and therefore, no life.

In this essay I have explained the main ideas of the design argument and have addressed a number of strengths as to how the argument proves the existence of God. To conclude, if a watch is a product of intelligent design then so is the universe, therefore, an intelligent designer must exist.  

The Teleological Argument

Document Details

  • Word Count 723
  • Page Count 1
  • Subject Religious Studies (Philosophy & Ethics)

Related Essays

The Teleological Argument.

The Teleological Argument.

Philosophy - teleological argument.

Philosophy - teleological argument.

The Teleological Argument

Outline the design argument for the existence of God. The teleological argu...

A Level Philosophy & Religious Studies

OCR Philosophy possible exam questions

These questions are taken from the wording of the specitication, meaning they could all actually come up in the exam. They are roughly sorted into easy, medium and hard.

Find revision notes for Philosophy here.

Ancient Philosophical influences (Plato & Aristotle)

Easy Critically compare Plato’s rationalism with Aristotle’s empiricism. Does Plato or Aristotle make more sense of reality? Assess Plato’s understanding of reality Does the world of Forms exist?

Medium Is Plato right that there is more to reality than we observe? Critically discuss the ideas expressed in Plato’s analogy of the cave. Analyse Aristotle’s four causes. How convincing is Aristotle’s idea of the Prime Mover? ‘Aristotelian teleology is false’ – Discuss. ‘The true reality is accessible only by reason’ – Discuss. Evaluate Plato’s purpose for the analogy of the cave. Do the senses provide the best understanding of reality? “Plato’s hierarchy of the forms tells us nothing about reality” – Discuss. ‘Plato’s form of the Good is not real’ – Discuss.

Hard Critically compare Plato’s form of the good with Aristotle’s prime mover. ‘Aristotelian teleology is outdated’ – Discuss. Critically compare Plato’s hierarchy of the forms with Aristotle’s four causes.

Soul, mind and body

Easy Assess the approach of Materialism to understanding the mind. Evaluate dualism. Are the mind and the body separate? Are Plato’s views on the soul correct? How successful is Descartes’ substance dualism?

Medium Does the soul exist? Should the soul as a spiritual substance be rejected? Can consciousness be fully explained by physical interactions? Can the mind/soul and body problem be resolved? Assess materialist critiques of dualism Assess dualist arguments against materialism Is the soul an essential and immaterial part of a human? ‘The soul is only temporarily united with the body’ – Discuss. Is the soul the form of the body? ‘There is a soul but it cannot be separated from the body’ – How far do you agree? Are the mind and body distinct substances? Critically compare Descartes and Aristotle’s view of the soul. What is consciousness? How convincing is Descartes’ solution to the mind-body problem?

Hard ‘Discussion of the mind-body distinction is a category error’ – Critically assess this view. Is the concept of the soul best understood metaphorically or as a reality? Assess the philosophical language of soul, mind and body in Plato and Aristotle’s work. ‘The soul is the way the body behaves and lives’ – Discuss. Analyse the metaphysics of consciousness.

Arguments based on observation

Easy Can the teleological/cosmological arguments overcome their criticisms? Assess the teleological/cosmological argument Can God’s existence be established by observation? Can evidence of God’s existence be observed? Are there logical fallacies in the teleological/cosmological arguments that cannot be overcome?

Medium Can teleological arguments be defended against the challenge of ‘chance’? Do Cosmological arguments jump to the conclusion of a transcendent creator without sufficient explanation? ‘Hume’s criticisms of the teleological/cosmological argument succeed’ – How far do you agree? ‘Aquinas’ first three ways show that we should believe in God’ – How far do you agree? Assess Paley’s design argument

Hard Is a posteriori a more successful form of argument than a priori? Is God’s existence better proven by a priori or a posteriori argument? ‘A priori argument is stronger than a posteriori’ – Discuss. Assess Aquinas’ 5 th way “The teleological argument fails due to the challenge of evolution” – Discuss. Does evolution disprove the teleological argument?

Arguments based on reason

Easy Assess Anselm’s ontological argument Does the ontological argument justify belief? Are there logical fallacies in the ontological argument that cannot be overcome?

Medium Can existence be treated as a predicate? Are Gaunilo’s criticisms of the ontological argument the most effective? Assess whether Kant or Gaunilo’s critique poses the greater challenge to the ontological argument.

Hard Is a posteriori a more successful form of argument than a priori? ‘A priori argument is stronger than a posteriori’ – Discuss. Assess Gaunilo’s criticisms of the ontological argument. Assess Kant’s criticisms of the ontological argument

Religious experience

Easy Are religious experiences just illusions? ‘religious experience justifies belief in God’ – How far do you agree?

Medium Are religious experiences evidence of God? ‘Religious experiences are union with a greater power’ – Discuss. Do religious experiences prove God’s existence? Assess whether testimony and witness is sufficient to validate religious experiences ‘Mystical experiences are of God’ – how far do you agree? Assess whether religious experiences are the product of a physiological effect

Hard Are corporate religious experiences more reliable than individual experiences? How successful are the views and main conclusions of William James? Does the influence religious experiences have show they have a supernatural source? ‘Conversion experiences are more reliable than mystical experiences’ – How far do you agree?

The problem of evil

Easy Assess Augustine’s theodicy Assess Hick’s sole making theodicy Can monotheism be defended in the face of evil?

Medium Does the logical problem of evil succeed? To what extent does the evidential problem of evil challenge belief? Does Augustine’s use of original perfection and the Fall solve the problem of evil? Assess Hick’s reworking of the Irenaean theodicy ‘natural evil enables human beings to reach divine likeness’ – How far do you agree? Critically compare the success of Augustine and Hick’s theodicies.

Hard Is the logical or evidential problem of evil the greater challenge to belief? Is it easier to show that God’s existence lacks evidence than that it is logically impossible? ‘Augustine solves the logical problem of evil’ – Discuss Does Augustine’s theodicy succeed against the evidential problem of evil? ‘Hick cannot solve the evidential problem of evil’ – How far do you agree? How successfully can the evidental problem of evil be addressed through the explanation of soul-making?

The nature or attributes of God

Easy Is the concept of God coherent? What is the relationship between divinity and time? ‘If God is omniscient, humans can’t have free will’ – Discuss. Analyse the implications of God’s eternity.

Medium Is Swinburne correct that God is everlasting/temporal? Can God be omnipotent? Can God be omnibenevolent? ‘The divine attributes of God conflict with each other’ – Discuss. Assess Boethius and Anselm’s view on God’s relationship with time. Does God know future human actions? ‘God is limited by divine self-limitation’ – how far do you agree? Does God have divine foreknowledge? Can God justly judge human actions? Critically compare Boethius with Swinburne on God’s relationship with time. Assess Boethius’ claim that God is eternal/atemporal.

Hard Assess Anselm’s four-dimensionalist approach. Does Anselm’s four-dimensionalist approach adequately explain divine action in time? Evaluate Boethius’ view of divine action and time. Critically compare Anselm with Swinburne on God’s relationship with time. “It is not necessary to resolve the apparent conflicts between divine attributes” – Discuss.

Religious language: Negative, Analogical or Symbolic

Easy Assess the apophatic way (via negative) Assess the cataphatic way (via positiva) ‘God can be talked about symbolically’ – How far do you agree?

Medium ‘Analogy is more effective than symbol for talking about God’ – Discuss. Does Tillich capture religious language better than the apophatic way? Critically compare analogy and via negative as methods of approaching religious language. Is God a symbol? Can Religious language be understood through Aquinas’ analogy of attribution and proper proportion? Critically assess whether theological language is best approached by negation. Does the apophatic way enable effective understanding of theological discussion?

Hard Does Aquinas’ analogical approach support effective expression of language about God? Is symbolic religious language comprehensible?

Religious Language: Twentieth Century Perspectives

Easy Assess logical positivism Assess Wittgenstein’s views on language games. Is religious language meaningful? Is verificationism an accurate theory of meaning?

Medium ‘Words must have a verifiable connection to empirical reality to be meaningful’ – Do you agree? Assess Flew’s views on religious language Critically compare Aquinas’ cognitivism with Wittgenstein’s non-cognitivism. Is religious language non-cognitive? ‘Hare’s account of religious language is correct’ – Discuss. Which was the most convincing point of view in the falsification symposium? Does religious language have a factual quality?

Hard Assess Mitchell’s contribution to the falsification symposium Is religious language a form of life? To what extent is Aquinas’ analogical view of religious language valuable in the philosophy of religion. Should non-cognitive approaches influence interpretation of religious texts?

  • International
  • Schools directory
  • Resources Jobs Schools directory News Search

Teleological Argument essay

Teleological Argument essay

Subject: Religious education

Age range: 16+

Resource type: Worksheet/Activity

NP1064513

Last updated

3 January 2024

  • Share through email
  • Share through twitter
  • Share through linkedin
  • Share through facebook
  • Share through pinterest

docx, 14.7 KB

‘The teleological argument is unconvincing’. Example essay for students to analyse.

Tes paid licence How can I reuse this?

Get this resource as part of a bundle and save up to 17%

A bundle is a package of resources grouped together to teach a particular topic, or a series of lessons, in one place.

A Level RS essay examples, some with tasks.

Essays for OCR H573. A Level RS. I find it helpful to give students example essays, which we analyse together. I will usually set these as essays for the students to complete, either having gone through a plan with them, or taking them through a good example afterwards so they can compare and reflect on their writing. There is a substantial collection here. Most are high-standard full essays, some are set out in shorter form on PPT (making them easier to engage with), and some include tasks to maximise the learning from the resource.

Your rating is required to reflect your happiness.

It's good to leave some feedback.

Something went wrong, please try again later.

This resource hasn't been reviewed yet

To ensure quality for our reviews, only customers who have purchased this resource can review it

Report this resource to let us know if it violates our terms and conditions. Our customer service team will review your report and will be in touch.

Not quite what you were looking for? Search by keyword to find the right resource:

IMAGES

  1. Analyse In Detail The True Meaning of Paley's Teleological Argument

    teleological argument a level essay

  2. Teleological argument

    teleological argument a level essay

  3. Teleological Arguments Essay A-Level AQA Philosophy (7172)

    teleological argument a level essay

  4. Teleological Argument Essay by Christine Carter

    teleological argument a level essay

  5. Existence of God: Cosmological and Teleological Arguments Free Essay

    teleological argument a level essay

  6. Explain Paley's teleological argument

    teleological argument a level essay

VIDEO

  1. Apologetics 3

  2. TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT (OCR A LEVEL RELIGIOUS STUDIES

  3. Introduction to Philosophy Lecture #6: Philosophy of Religion/Logic

  4. Arguments for God's Existence?

  5. Theists are TERRIFIED of this CRUCIAL argument

  6. Teleological Argument: OCR Religious Studies

COMMENTS

  1. The Teleological argument A* grade summary notes

    A Level Philosophy & Religious Studies. Menu AQA Philosophy; OCR RS; Edexcel RS; AQA RS; WJEC/Eduqas RS; Tutoring & essay marking; The Teleological argument A* grade summary notes. OCR Philosophy.

  2. PDF Teleological Argument

    Teleological arguments, also known as arguments from design, aim to prove the existence of God from examples of order in the universe. Examples of this order can be divided into two ... are perfectly suited to sustaining life. In this essay I will argue that neither type of order is sufficient to prove that God (the God as typically understood ...

  3. The Teleological/design argument

    They argue there is insufficient evidence to justify belief in God. Design arguments directly targets that position by attempting an inductive proof of God. They use a posteriori evidence as premises to inductively support the conclusion that God exists. Weakness: Hume's evidential problem of evil.

  4. PDF The Teleological Argument

    The Teleological Argument 4 Challenges to the teleological argument Hume Paley wrote his design argument 26 years after the death of Hume. Therefore Hume never read Paley's work, but Paley's argument from analogy was not original. In his book 'Dia-logues Concerning Natural religion' Hume argued against the form of the design argument

  5. Teleological Argument

    The Teleological Argument. Definition: The Teleological Argument, also known as the Design Argument, suggests that the design evident in the universe implies a designer - God. William Paley: His watchmaker analogy is a central part of the Teleological Argument. Paley posits that if one were to find a watch, its complexity and functionality ...

  6. Teleological Arguments

    Both arguments propose a deity as the best explanation for observed phenomena - design and existence, respectively. This combination can provide a stronger argument for the existence of God, but it also invites criticisms grounded in both arguments. Everything you need to know about Teleological Arguments for the A Level Philosophy AQA exam ...

  7. Teleological Arguments for God's Existence

    Teleological Arguments for God's Existence. First published Fri Jun 10, 2005; substantive revision Wed Apr 5, 2023. Some phenomena within nature exhibit such exquisiteness of structure, function or interconnectedness that many people have found it natural to see a deliberative and directive mind behind those phenomena.

  8. Teleological Argument

    A-level (AS and A2) Religious Studies looking at the existence of god and the Teleological Argument. This Philosophy of religion section looks at the pros and cons of such an argument. ... The Teleological Argument (Argument from Design) 1. Ancient History. Cicero is one of the earliest philosophers to discuss the idea of design in nature.

  9. The Teleological Argument

    The Teleological Argument. The word 'teleological' comes from the Greek word 'telos' which means 'end' or 'purpose'. The teleological argument is also known as the design argument, which is an a posteriori argument because it is an argument based on external evidence. The argument makes the basic assumptions that there is order ...

  10. teleological argument

    The design argument, known as the Teleological argument, comes from the Greek word 'Telos' which means purpose. The basic premise, of all teleological arguments for the existence of God, is that the world exhibits an intelligent purpose based on experience from nature such as its order, unity, coherency, design and complexity.

  11. Teleological Argument ESSAY PLAN

    Age range: 16+. Resource type: Assessment and revision. File previews. docx, 17.32 KB. An extremely detailed essay plan on the Teleological Argument, with a great structure that entwines information and analysis together. Even if your essay question is different, this will be really useful for taking evaluative points for this topic!

  12. Does God Exist?

    A level philosophy looks at 4 arguments relating to the existence of God. These are: The ontological argument. The teleological argument. The cosmological argument. The problem of evil. There are various versions of each argument as well as numerous responses to each.

  13. 6.2.1 Teleological Arguments for the Existence of God

    Strengths and weaknesses of the teleological argument. Teleological arguments suggest that the seeming order and purposefulness of the natural universe suggests the existence of a "designer.". Intelligent Design: Crash Course Philosophy #11. Or watch the video here. "Telos" is Greek for "purpose" or "goal," and the teleological ...

  14. Teleological Argument

    An A* grade example answer to a 25 mark question on teleological arguments. This document also includes a bullet-point essay plan to help students understand how to structure their essays for maximum marks. After completing your purchase, a download link will be sent to the email address used at checkout.

  15. A Level Philosophy & Religious Studies

    Soul, mind & body. Arguments based on observation: the teleological argument. Arguments based on observation: the cosmological argument. Arguments based on reason: the ontological argument. Religious experience. The problem of evil. The nature or attributes of God. RL: Negative, Analogical or Symbolic. RL: Verificationism, Falsificationism ...

  16. Teleological arguments

    Teleological intro. - a posteriori arguments as they are based on experience. - attempt to prove the existence of God by appealing to features of nature. - claims that 'God exists' is synthetic. - e.g. order and regularity in our universe. - known as arguments from design. Argument from analogy. - inductive a posteriori.

  17. Teleological Arguments Essay: AQA A-Level Philosophy

    This essay evaluates whether it is possible to "prove the existence of God a priori" through means of teleological arguments. It was awarded 25/25 by an examiner under the AQA marking guidelines. It is a c.2k word essay and reaches a well reasoned conclusion having evaluated various teleological arguments and potential responses.

  18. The Teleological Argument Essay

    The Teleological Argument Essay Word Document 23.5 Kb. Philosophy; Ideas of gods; AS; Download. Save to favourites. Share: Tweet. Comments. No comments have yet been made. ... OCR Religious Studies A-level Essay feedback » OCR A Level Religious Studies Philosophy of religion H573/01 - 9 Jun 2022 [Exam Chat] » ...

  19. The Teleological Argument

    This argument is also known as the teleological argument. The word 'teleological' derives from the Greek 'telos' which means an end, or an ultimate purpose. This essay will focus on William Paley's view and his famous watchmaker analogy. William Paley was a British born philosopher who lived from 1743 to 1805 and he is best remembered ...

  20. Teleological Arguments Essay A-Level AQA Philosophy (7172)

    A-Level Philosophy AQA Notes + Essay Bundle! Included is a full pack of notes for all topics under AQA A-Level Philosophy, specification 7172. These notes clearly explain the main concepts, the objections to the argument and in most cases counters to the objections. Furthermore, also included is a collection of essay plans.

  21. OCR Philosophy possible exam questions

    'A priori argument is stronger than a posteriori' - Discuss. Assess Aquinas' 5 th way "The teleological argument fails due to the challenge of evolution" - Discuss. Does evolution disprove the teleological argument? Arguments based on reason. Easy Assess Anselm's ontological argument Does the ontological argument justify belief?

  22. Teleological Argument essay

    A Level RS. I find it helpful to give students example essays, which we analyse together. I will usually set these as essays for the students to complete, either having gone through a plan with them, or taking them through a good example afterwards so they can compare and reflect on their writing. There is a substantial collection here.