Pitchgrade

Presentations made painless

  • Get Premium

130 Criminal Procedure Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

Inside This Article

Criminal procedure is a vital aspect of the legal system that ensures fairness and justice for all individuals involved in criminal cases. If you are a law student or a legal professional looking for essay topic ideas in criminal procedure, you have come to the right place. This article presents 130 topic ideas and examples that can serve as a starting point for your research and writing. These topics cover a wide range of issues, including the Fourth Amendment, search and seizure, arrest and detention, trial procedure, and much more. Let's dive in!

  • The evolution of criminal procedure laws in the United States.
  • The importance of the Fourth Amendment in criminal procedure.
  • A comparative analysis of criminal procedure in common and civil law jurisdictions.
  • The impact of technology on search and seizure in criminal procedure.
  • The role of probable cause in search and seizure.
  • The concept of reasonable expectation of privacy in criminal procedure.
  • The exclusionary rule and its impact on criminal procedure.
  • The controversy surrounding stop-and-frisk practices in criminal procedure.
  • The use of body-worn cameras by law enforcement officers and its implications for criminal procedure.
  • The legality of warrantless searches in exigent circumstances.
  • The balancing test between individual rights and law enforcement interests in search and seizure.
  • The role of consent in search and seizure in criminal procedure.
  • The impact of racial profiling on search and seizure practices.
  • The legality of drug testing in schools under criminal procedure laws.
  • The use of thermal imaging technology in search and seizure.
  • The impact of the Patriot Act on search and seizure in criminal procedure.
  • The legality of drug checkpoints under criminal procedure laws.
  • The implications of the "fruit of the poisonous tree" doctrine in criminal procedure.
  • The role of the plain view doctrine in search and seizure.
  • The legality of GPS tracking in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of social media on search and seizure in criminal procedure.
  • The role of the Terry stop in criminal procedure.
  • The legality of vehicle searches during routine traffic stops.
  • The impact of racial bias in jury selection in criminal trials.
  • The role of eyewitness testimony in criminal procedure.
  • The concept of double jeopardy and its implications for criminal procedure.
  • The legality of plea bargains in criminal procedure.
  • The role of expert witnesses in criminal trials.
  • The impact of the media on criminal trials and the right to a fair trial.
  • The use of forensic evidence in criminal procedure.
  • The implications of DNA testing in criminal investigations.
  • The role of confessions and their admissibility in criminal trials.
  • The impact of mental health issues on criminal procedure.
  • The legality of the death penalty under constitutional law.
  • The role of defense attorneys in criminal procedure.
  • The impact of race and socioeconomic status on access to justice in criminal cases.
  • The role of the grand jury in criminal procedure.
  • The implications of prosecutorial misconduct on criminal trials.
  • The legality of warrantless wiretapping under criminal procedure laws.
  • The impact of plea bargaining on the right to a fair trial.
  • The role of the judge in ensuring a fair trial in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the insanity defense in criminal trials.
  • The legality of the use of force by law enforcement officers in criminal procedure.
  • The impact of mandatory minimum sentences on criminal procedure.
  • The role of expert testimony in determining guilt or innocence in criminal trials.
  • The implications of eyewitness misidentification in criminal cases.
  • The legality of the use of informants in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of pretrial publicity on the right to a fair trial.
  • The role of the defendant's right to confront witnesses in criminal trials.
  • The implications of the right to remain silent in criminal procedure.
  • The legality of the use of lie detector tests in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of the war on drugs on criminal procedure.
  • The role of the exclusionary rule in deterring police misconduct.
  • The implications of plea bargaining on the right to a jury trial.
  • The legality of the use of drones in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of eyewitness confidence on juror decision-making in criminal trials.
  • The role of the jury in determining guilt or innocence in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to a speedy trial in criminal procedure.
  • The legality of the use of social media evidence in criminal trials.
  • The impact of pretrial motions on criminal procedure.
  • The role of the defense attorney in negotiating plea bargains in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to counsel in criminal procedure.
  • The legality of the use of cell site location information in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of racial bias in jury deliberations in criminal trials.
  • The role of the judge's instructions to the jury in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in the digital age.
  • The legality of the use of facial recognition technology in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of the "War on Terror" on criminal procedure.
  • The role of the bail system in criminal procedure.
  • The implications of prosecutorial discretion in criminal cases.
  • The legality of the use of body cavity searches in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of the right to a public trial on access to justice in criminal cases.
  • The role of the judge's impartiality in ensuring a fair trial in criminal procedure.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in non-capital cases.
  • The legality of the use of cell phone tracking in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of the "CSI effect" on criminal trials.
  • The role of the defendant's right to testify in criminal procedure.
  • The implications of the right to a unanimous jury verdict in criminal cases.
  • The legality of the use of lie detector tests in preemployment screenings.
  • The impact of the right to confront witnesses on the use of hearsay evidence in criminal trials.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in sentencing in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to effective assistance of counsel in criminal procedure.
  • The legality of the use of stingray devices in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of the right to a public defender in ensuring access to justice in criminal cases.
  • The role of the defendant's right to remain silent in plea negotiations.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in juvenile delinquency cases.
  • The legality of the use of lie detector tests in employment discrimination cases.
  • The impact of the right to a fair trial on the use of peremptory challenges in jury selection.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in granting pretrial release in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in cases involving child victims.
  • The legality of the use of facial recognition technology in airport security.
  • The impact of the right to effective assistance of counsel on post-conviction relief.
  • The role of the defendant's right to a speedy trial in cases involving complex evidence.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in cases involving hate crimes.
  • The legality of the use of polygraph tests in child custody disputes.
  • The impact of the right to a fair trial on the use of peremptory challenges based on race or gender.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in granting parole in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in cases involving national security.
  • The legality of the use of facial recognition technology in public spaces.
  • The impact of the right to effective assistance of counsel on the use of forensic evidence in criminal trials.
  • The role of the defendant's right to a public trial in cases involving sensitive information.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in cases involving organized crime.
  • The legality of the use of voice recognition technology in criminal investigations.
  • The impact of the right to a fair trial on the use of peremptory challenges based on sexual orientation.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in granting probation in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in cases involving confidential informants.
  • The legality of the use of facial recognition technology in schools.
  • The impact of the right to effective assistance of counsel on the use of forensic psychology in criminal trials.
  • The role of the defendant's right to a speedy trial in cases involving international extradition.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in cases involving cybercrime.
  • The legality of the use of voice recognition technology in border security.
  • The impact of the right to a fair trial on the use of peremptory challenges based on religion.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in granting post-conviction relief in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in cases involving intelligence agencies.
  • The legality of the use of facial recognition technology in public transportation.
  • The impact of the right to effective assistance of counsel on the use of forensic anthropology in criminal trials.
  • The role of the defendant's right to a public trial in cases involving classified information.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in cases involving terrorism.
  • The legality of the use of voice recognition technology in workplace surveillance.
  • The impact of the right to a fair trial on the use of peremptory challenges based on disability.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in granting expungement of criminal records.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in cases involving national security whistleblowers.
  • The legality of the use of facial recognition technology in public protests.
  • The impact of the right to effective assistance of counsel on the use of forensic entomology in criminal trials.
  • The role of the defendant's right to a speedy trial in cases involving war crimes.
  • The implications of the right to trial by jury in cases involving human trafficking.
  • The legality of the use of voice recognition technology in online surveillance.
  • The impact of the right to a fair trial on the use of peremptory challenges based on socioeconomic status.
  • The role of the judge's discretion in granting clemency in criminal cases.
  • The implications of the right to confront witnesses in cases involving witness protection programs.

These essay topic ideas and examples cover a broad spectrum of criminal procedure issues, allowing you to explore various aspects of this field. Remember to conduct thorough research, gather evidence, and provide sound arguments to support your analysis. Good luck with your essay!

Want to create a presentation now?

Instantly Create A Deck

Let PitchGrade do this for me

Hassle Free

We will create your text and designs for you. Sit back and relax while we do the work.

Explore More Content

  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms of Service

© 2023 Pitchgrade

Home — Essay Samples — Law, Crime & Punishment — Criminal Procedure — Criminal Procedure Assignment

test_template

Criminal Procedure Assignment

  • Categories: Criminal Procedure

About this sample

close

Words: 785 |

Published: Mar 25, 2024

Words: 785 | Pages: 2 | 4 min read

Image of Dr. Oliver Johnson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr. Heisenberg

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Law, Crime & Punishment

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

6 pages / 3625 words

8 pages / 4033 words

1 pages / 569 words

3 pages / 1478 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Criminal Procedure

Based on the evidence collected, it appears that the suspect gained entry to the residence by forcing open the front door. The living room was ransacked, suggesting that the suspect was searching for valuables. The open kitchen [...]

Crime prevention is important because it attempts to reduce and deter the crimes. It refers to the range of strategies that are implemented by individuals, communities, businesses, non-government organisations and all levels of [...]

In order for a profiler to be successful in their attempts, several facets of the crime need to be considered. Modus Operandi (M.O.) and Signature are two key components. Through the exploration of the crime scene, all involved [...]

Michael J. Sandel discusses how there are three different approaches to justice: welfare, virtue, and freedom. The theme of the book is on how and what is considered moral. He introduces several perspectives on morality and we [...]

Toxicology is the study of all the adverse effects of drugs and chemicals that can take a toll on biological systems. Forensic toxicology has to take into consideration the application of toxicology for the purposes of the [...]

The importance of examining a hair or fiber was documented in the early stages of forensic science. One of the first forensic science reports involving the scientific study of hair was published in France, in 1857. This [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

what is criminal procedure essay

  • criminal procedure

Primary tabs

Criminal procedure deals with the set of rules governing the series of proceedings through which the government enforces substantive  criminal law . Municipalities , states , and the federal government each have their own criminal codes , defining types of conduct that constitute  crimes .  Title 18  of the U.S. Code outlines all federal crimes. Typically, federal crimes deal with activities that either extend beyond state boundaries or directly impact federal interests.

Federal prosecutions follow the  Federal Rules of Criminal Procedure , cited as Fed. R. Crim. P., which the U.S. Supreme Court promulgated and Congress passed. The Federal Rules outline the procedure for conducting federal criminal trials . The Federal Rules incorporate and expound upon all guarantees included within the  U.S. Constitution's Bill of Rights , such as the guarantee to  due process  and  equal protection , the  right to legal counsel ,  the right to confront witnesses , the  right to a jury trial , and the  right to not testify against oneself .

State prosecutions follow the criminal procedure code of the individual state. Although every state has its own criminal procedure code, many states choose to mimic the  Federal Rules . State procedural rules may offer greater protection to a defendant in a criminal trial than the U.S. Constitution or the Federal Rules, but may not offer less protection than guaranteed by the U.S. Constitution.

Investigatory and Accusatory Police Procedure

The  U.S. Constitution , the Federal Rules, state and local rules , and court interpretation of these documents not only set out how trials are run but also prescribe the procedures that law enforcement agencies must follow. Should an officer fail to abide by the proper procedure, the trial court may  suppress   evidence obtained in violation of proper procedure, which could even lead to the suspect's acquittal. 

Law enforcement agencies are limited in their abilities well before an arrest is made. A portion of the criminal procedure process deals with an officers’ ability to stop individuals, search them or their properties , and seize any incriminating evidence the officer finds. This pre-arrest investigation is limited by the  Fourth ,  Fifth ,  Sixth , and  Fourteenth Amendments .

Fourth Amendment

The  Fourth Amendment  protects individuals from  unreasonable searches and seizures . As the Supreme Court explained in   Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643 (1961) , evidence obtained by searches and seizures in violation of the U.S. Constitution is inadmissible in a criminal trial. In order to avoid illegally searching or seizing the property of a suspect, law enforcement personnel typically obtain  search warrants . To obtain a search warrant, law enforcement must show  probable cause , must support the showing by oath or affirmation, and must describe in particularity the place they will search and the items they will seize. 

Just as criminal procedure limits what is a reasonable search, it also specifies what constitutes a reasonable interrogation . In  Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966) , the Supreme Court held that police must make defendants aware of their rights prior to the defendant making any statements, provided the government intends to use those statements as evidence against the defendant. The Fifth Amendment and the Sixth Amendment require law enforcement to ensure that defendants understand their right to remain silent and their right to have an attorney present during the interrogation.

The Fourteenth Amendment applies all the aforementioned  substantive due process  rights to state criminal defendants.

Pre-Trial Procedure

Right to a speedy trial.

The  Sixth Amendment  to the U.S. Constitution guarantees criminal defendants the right to a  speedy trial . Consequently,  prosecutors  cannot wait an inordinate amount of time before filing charges or proceeding with the prosecution after filing charges. Under the  Speedy Trial Act , which Congress passed to clarify the speedy trial guarantee, a trial must begin within 70 days of the prosecutor filing the indictment .

The Sixth Amendment also guarantees the right to a public trial by an impartial  jury  of one's peers. One manner in which the criminal justice system attempts to provide for an impartial jury is by permitting both sides to use  peremptory challenges  during jury selection . If a party exercises a peremptory challenge against a prospective juror, then the court must excuse that juror from the panel . These challenges occur during jury  voir dire , and are meant to root out bias . While neither the prosecution nor the defendant needs to explain their reasons for a challenge, not every challenge is permissible. As the Supreme Court explained in  Batson v. Kentucky, 476 U.S. 79 (1986) , and   J.E.B. v. Alabama, 511 U.S. 127 (1994) , a  party  cannot remove a juror solely for the juror’s race or gender.

Guarantee of a Fair Trial

The Fifth Amendment's guarantee of due process requires that criminal defendants receive a fair trial. In high-publicity trials, trial judges have the responsibility to minimize effects of the publicity on jurors’ decisions, such as through implementing a  gag-order  on the parties. In  Carey v. Musladin, 549 U.S. 70 (2006) , the Supreme Court held that a jury was not unduly influenced by the family of the victim wearing buttons with the picture of the victim on them. 

Other Miscellaneous Guarantees

Due process  further commands that defendants have the right to call their own witnesses , mount their own evidence, and present their own theories of the facts . The prosecution must turn over all evidence that will be presented against the defendant and allow the defendant pre-trial access to question the prosecutor's witnesses to properly mount a defense.

Pre-trial would also be the point at which the defense might raise a defense of  double jeopardy , if such a defense existed in that case . The  Fifth Amendment , through the  Double Jeopardy  Clause, prohibits states from charging the same defendant with substantially the same crime on the same facts.

Trial Procedure

Once a trial begins, the  U.S. Constitution  affords further rights to criminal defendants. The law only permits the prosecution to overcome the defendant's  presumption of innocence  if they can show the defendant's guilt beyond a  reasonable doubt . This very high burden differs drastically from a civil trial's much lower standard in which the plaintiff must only prove a claim by a  preponderance of the evidence .

One right guaranteed by the  Sixth Amendment  is the  right of an individual to confront witnesses . The difficulty of upholding this right arises when a witness testifies to the police and passes away shortly after. In such a case, the prosecution would be unable to allow the defendant to cross-examine the witness. 

Right to Effective Counsel

The  Sixth Amendment  also guarantees a defendant the right to assistance of counsel during trial. If a defendant cannot afford an attorney, the government is required to provide one. Such defendants receive legal representation from the Public Defender's Office. The  Federal Rules of Criminal Procedure  provide that an accused shall have access to counsel at every stage of the proceedings, beginning with the defendant's initial appearance. If a defendant demands the presence of counsel during police interrogation, police must stop the interrogation until the defendant's counsel is present. In  Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963) , the Supreme Court held that the Sixth Amendment's guarantee of counsel applies to state criminal proceedings as well.

However, a defendant may choose to voluntarily and intelligently waive assistance of counsel and self-represent. This is called " pro se " representation.

The legal counseling received must also constitute "effective counseling." Ineffective assistance of counsel may serve as grounds for a new trial. Establishing ineffective assistance of counsel requires establishing that the prevailing professional norms at the time of trial render the actual assistance received inadequate and that the ineffective assistance caused a fundamentally unfair result.

Right not to Self-Incriminate

Under the Fifth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution provides that a defendant enjoys a right of not having to provide self-incriminating testimony. At the stage of a trial when the jury determines guilt or innocence, a jury cannot infer the defendant's failure to appear or answer as an admission of guilt.

Stages of a Trial

After law enforcement arrests a suspect, a judge will set the suspect's initial  bail , which is a specified amount of cash that allows the defendant to get out of jail after the initial arrest. If the defendant shows up for the proper court dates, the court refunds the bail, but if the defendant skips the date, then the court keeps the bail and issues a warrant for the individual's arrest.

Arraignment

The  arraignment  comes next. During an arraignment, a judge calls an individual charged with committing a crime, reads to the individual the criminal charges against laid against them, asks the accused whether the accused has access to an attorney or needs the assistance of a court-appointed attorney, asks the accused to plead, decides whether to amend the initial bail amount, and sets the dates of future proceedings.

Preliminary Hearing

The  preliminary hearing  follows the arraignment. At the preliminary hearing, the judge determines whether enough evidence exists for the prosecution to meet its  burden of persuasion . The burden of persuasion refers to whether the prosecution even has enough evidence to make the defendant stand trial. The defense has the right to  cross examine  the government witnesses during this proceeding. Under the Fifth Amendment, a  grand jury , rather than a judge, makes this determination when the defendant is charged with a "capital or infamous crime.” 

Pre-Trial Hearing

A pre-trial hearing is the next step in the process. The prosecution and the defense team use the pre-trial to file motions before a judge. These motion usually concern whether the court should suppress certain evidence, whether certain individuals can testify, or whether the judge should dismiss all charges for lack of evidence.

After all these preliminary stages, the defendant stands trial. Both sides offer opening statements first, although the defense can reserve their opening statement until the prosecution “rests”—finishes presenting their case. The prosecution presents its witnesses and evidence first. Then, the defense presents its witnesses and evidence. After the defense rests, the defense offers a closing argument, and then the prosecution offers its final closing argument. After closing arguments, the jury deliberates and returns a verdict.

Sentencing  usually occurs immediately for  infractions  and  misdemeanors . For such minor infractions penalties may include  probation ; fines; short-term  incarceration ; long-term incarceration; suspended sentence, which only takes effect if the convict fails to meet certain conditions; payment of restitution to the victim; community service; or drug and alcohol rehabilitation.

More serious crimes result in the trier of fact hearing evidence and arguments from both the prosecution and the defense regarding the appropriate sentence. Some jurisdictions allow the judge alone to determine the sentence; others will have a separate sentencing phase trial, complete with a new jury, to determine the sentence for certain crimes.

During a sentencing trial, the prosecution presents evidence of  aggravating factors , and the defense presents evidence of  mitigating factors . The U.S. Supreme Court has interpreted the U.S. Constitution to protect the right to a jury sentencing trial for all defendants facing the  death penalty .

Before the judge announces the sentence, a defendant is entitled to  allocution . Allocution is the right of the defendant to directly address the judge without the help of counsel. During this direct address, the defendant may offer a personal explanation of any unknown facts, may ask for mercy, or may offer an apology for the criminal behavior. This is an opportunity for defendants to show remorse or to offer the motivations behind their criminal acts, to influence the judge to be lenient.

Sentencing Guidelines

The federal government and state governments have created various sentencing guidelines. Federal courts use the  Federal Sentencing Guidelines,  while state courts will look at state-specific sentencing guidelines.  

Further Reading

For more on criminal procedure, see this  Columbia Law Review article titled Criminal Procedure and the Good Citizen, and this  University of Nevada Law Journal Forum article titled Statewide Rules of Criminal Procedure: A 50 State Review.

[Last updated in July of 2022 by the Wex Definitions Team ]

  • ACADEMIC TOPICS
  • legal education and writing
  • the Constitution
  • THE LEGAL PROCESS
  • criminal law and procedure
  • wex articles
  • criminal law
  • Federal Rules of Criminal Procedure

Criminal Procedure: Arrest Essay

Introduction, criminal procedures, reference list.

A primary dilemma encountered in societies is how to establish correct procedures of societal control, providing security, and enforcing correct standards of order. The law forms the fundamental basis of defining all societal undertakings. Authorities play the role of enforcing the laws that protect individual rights. In addition, the rule of law helps to differentiate dictatorial from egalitarian societies (Scheb, 2008, p.3).

Criminal procedures help to protect suspected criminals from indiscriminate treatment and harassment from law enforcing agents, hence protect suspects’ and defendants’ constitutional rights. All law enforcing agents must follow these procedures from the original encounter with suspects, arrest, investigation, trial, sentencing, and appeal. The law guarantees individual liberties from unwarranted arrests and ransacking. In addition, it guarantees the security of people in any environment, even if suspected (Gales, 2009, Para. 1-4). Scheb further adds that all law-enforcing officers must have a firm basis for conducting searches. In addition, arrestees must permit officers to ransack their property, unless in tricky situations (2008, p.8).

Different municipalities and federal governments have varying crime codes. These codes define the conduct of its citizens and law enforcing bodies in combating crime. Failure by the law enforcement agents to follow such procedures may cause loss of evidence, hence hindering justice. To ensure that no evidence is lost, officers should have arrest warrants, unless the officer strongly believes that, the suspect has committed a criminal offense (Legal information institute, 2009, Para. 1-5).

A warrant is a document that gives police officers rights to search and apprehend suspects. The fourth amendment as dictated by the Supreme Court never conditions police officers to have warrants during all arrests. However, it guides law enforcement bodies’ conduct; on how and when to conduct searches. In addition, the arrest can be made without a warrant if, a person commits the offense in the presence of a law enforcement officer. An unacceptable arrest does not guarantee fair prosecution. This is because; the use of wrong arrest procedures invalidates some evidence (Criminal procedure, 2009, Para. 1-3). Officer Smith was right when he followed Radley’s car, due to it being not common in that locality. In addition, he applied the correct questioning procedures. This is because he requested Radley to interrogate him, which he went ahead and did.

Fundamental rights in criminal procedures include freedom from perverse ransacking, freedom from harsh punishment, a fast trial, rights from jeopardy, conflict with opposing witnesses, and self-blame. In addition, all individuals have the right to have a trial by a jury and get help from counsel (Criminal procedure act, 1977, p. 23-27). By checking Radley’s car without his consent, Officer Smith violated Radley’s rights. Although the officer lacked satisfaction from what Radley had told him, he had no right to check his car without his permission. This is because, although smith found some evidence that linked to the crimes that had been committed, there was a likelihood of evidence invalidation. If Smith was dissatisfied with answers from Radley, he was to seek permission from Radley first. As gale argues, the state does not permit any officer to search an automobile, unless there is reasonable suspicion. He further adds searches conducted without enough suspicion, go against the fourth amendment.

For example under the vehicle search requirements, police officers have the authority to search vehicles if they have a strong conviction that the vehicle is carrying materials that will give clues on specific crimes. This is because vehicles are in motion and the majority of drivers lack privacy (Gales, 2009, Para. 14-16).

When officer smith consulted the dispatcher on any crimes reported and whether Radley had an arrest warrant, the only feedback he got was on t burglaries committed. In addition, the dispatcher gave him evidence that linked the tools that Radley was carrying. Although he had no arrest warrant, he had the right to arrest him due to suspicion. Smith never explained to Radley why he was arresting him, which was wrong. In addition, Smith never questioned Radley on why he was carrying the tools before apprehending him. As Orfield argues such arrests, cause a lot of inconvenience to motorists depending on duties that await them in case they are not burglars. He further argues, law-enforcing agents, must thoroughly interview the suspects if they are carrying no dangerous weapons. This helps officers to make decisions on whether to arrest the suspects or not (2005, p. 33-34).

In addition, the arrestee must receive the Miranda warnings from the law-enforcing agent before the arrest. The warnings accord the suspect rights to call for advocates and remain quiet. The warnings help in collecting evidence from arrestees when taken into custody (Criminal procedure, 2009, Para. 2). Smith’s approach was wrong because at some point the case against Radley may lack evidence

In conclusion, for charges against individuals to be justifiable, all law-enforcing agents must follow correct criminal procedures. This helps to ensure that all evidences are important in supporting prosecution. Smith never followed the required procedures in checking and arresting radley. This jeopardizes the quality of the case, because the prosecution may lack a firm basis for arguing.

Criminal procedure act. (1977). Web.

Criminal procedure: arrest. (2009).

Gales, T. (2009). Criminal procedure. Web.

Legal information institute: Cornell university law school. (2009). Criminal procedure.

Orfield, L. B. (2005). Criminal procedure from arrest to appeal . New York: New York University Press

Scheb, J. (2008). Criminal procedure . New York: Wadsworth publishing

  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2021, November 8). Criminal Procedure: Arrest. https://ivypanda.com/essays/criminal-procedure-arrest/

"Criminal Procedure: Arrest." IvyPanda , 8 Nov. 2021, ivypanda.com/essays/criminal-procedure-arrest/.

IvyPanda . (2021) 'Criminal Procedure: Arrest'. 8 November.

IvyPanda . 2021. "Criminal Procedure: Arrest." November 8, 2021. https://ivypanda.com/essays/criminal-procedure-arrest/.

1. IvyPanda . "Criminal Procedure: Arrest." November 8, 2021. https://ivypanda.com/essays/criminal-procedure-arrest/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Criminal Procedure: Arrest." November 8, 2021. https://ivypanda.com/essays/criminal-procedure-arrest/.

  • Concepts of Police Ethics and Deviance
  • Steps of Criminal Procedure in US
  • Analysis and Application of Criminal Procedures
  • Crime Commitment and Punishment
  • Mockingbirds: The Similarities and Differences Between Tom Robinson and Boo Radley
  • Racism in “To Kill Mocking Bird” by Harper Lee
  • To Kill a Mockingbird
  • Social Issues in the "To Kill a Mockingbird" by Harper Lee
  • Jem's Character in the "To Kill a Mocking Bird" by Harper Lee
  • Analysis of Harper Lee’s To Kill a Mockingbird
  • Criminal Justice for Physically Injured Crime Victims
  • Research on Punishment in America
  • Arming Police Assault Rifles
  • Criminal Justice: Term Definition
  • Punishment Against Rehabilitation: Discussion

Logo for M Libraries Publishing

Want to create or adapt books like this? Learn more about how Pressbooks supports open publishing practices.

1.2 Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure

Learning objective.

  • Compare criminal law and criminal procedure.

This book focuses on criminal law , but it occasionally touches on issues of criminal procedure , so it is important to differentiate between the two.

Criminal law generally defines the rights and obligations of individuals in society. Some common issues in criminal law are the elements of specific crimes and the elements of various criminal defenses. Criminal procedure generally concerns the enforcement of individuals’ rights during the criminal process. Examples of procedural issues are individuals’ rights during law enforcement investigation, arrest, filing of charges, trial, and appeal.

Example of Criminal Law Issues

Clara and Linda go on a shopping spree. Linda insists that they browse an expensive department store. Moments after they enter the lingerie department, Linda surreptitiously places a bra in her purse. Clara watches, horrified, but does not say anything, even though a security guard is standing nearby. This example illustrates two issues of criminal law: (1) Which crime did Linda commit when she shoplifted the bra? (2) Did Clara commit a crime when she failed to alert the security guard to Linda’s shoplifting? You learn the answer to issue (1) in Chapter 11 “Crimes against Property” and issue (2) in Chapter 4 “The Elements of a Crime” and Chapter 7 “Parties to Crime” .

Example of Criminal Procedure Issues

Review the example in Section 1.2.1 “Example of Criminal Law Issues” . Assume that Linda and Clara attempt to leave the store and an alarm is activated. Linda begins sprinting down the street. Colin, a police officer, just happens to be driving by with the window of his patrol car open. He hears the store alarm, sees Linda running, and begins shooting at Linda from the car. Linda is shot in the leg and collapses. Linda is treated at the hospital for her injury, and when she is released, Colin arrests her and transports her to the police station. He brings her to an isolated room and leaves her there alone. Twelve hours later, he reenters the room and begins questioning Linda. Linda immediately requests an attorney. Colin ignores this request and continues to question Linda about the reason the department store alarm went off. Whether Colin properly arrested and interrogated Linda are criminal procedure issues beyond the scope of this book. However, this example does illustrate one criminal law issue: did Colin commit a crime when he shot Linda in the leg? You learn the answer to this question in Chapter 5 “Criminal Defenses, Part 1” .

Figure 1.1 Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure

image

Key Takeaway

  • Criminal law generally defines the rights and obligations of individuals in society. Criminal procedure generally concerns the enforcement of individuals’ rights during the criminal process.

Answer the following questions. Check your answers using the answer key at the end of the chapter.

  • Paul, a law enforcement officer, arrests Barney for creating a disturbance at a subway station. While Barney is handcuffed facedown on the ground, Paul shoots and kills him. Paul claims that he accidentally grabbed his gun instead of his Taser. Is this an issue of criminal law or criminal procedure?
  • Read Payton v. New York , 445 U.S. 573 (1980). In Payton , the US Supreme Court held a New York statute unconstitutional under the Fourth Amendment. Did the Payton ruling focus on criminal law or criminal procedure? The case is available at this link: http://supreme.justia.com/us/445/573 .

Criminal Law Copyright © 2015 by University of Minnesota is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License , except where otherwise noted.

Criminal Procedure

Seeking equity in electronic monitoring: mounting a bearden challenge.

In  Bearden v. Georgia , the Supreme Court held a defendant cannot be imprisoned for failure to pay a fine they could not afford. Yet, many defendants remain incarcerated because they cannot pay for Electronic Monitoring. This Comment seeks to remedy that disparity by applying  Bearden  to Electronic Mo…

The Fourth Amendment and General Law

This Article contends that courts should interpret the Fourth Amendment by looking to “general law”—common-law rules under the control of no particular sovereign. This approach finds strong support in the Fourth Amendment’s text, doctrine, and historical background, and would protect the Amendment’s…

Excessive Sentencing Reviews: Eighth Amendment Substance and Procedure

Using Louisiana law as a case study, this Essay describes the consequences of the lack of substantive limits on noncapital sentences. It then critiques the focus on procedural rights that results from this vacuum of substantive rights, and discusses how to harness procedural changes to address exces…

Equalizing Access to Evidence: Criminal Defendants and the Stored Communications Act

The Stored Communications Act poses an increasing threat to criminal defendants’ ability to access evidence. This Note analyzes pathways criminal defendants can pursue to access evidence within the current statutory framework and argues that the statute is unconstitutional as applied to cases where …

Fruit of the Racist Tree: A Super-Exclusionary Rule for Racist Policing Under California’s Racial Justice Act

What would it take for a state to eliminate racial bias in policing? This Comment explores one intervention set forth in California’s new Racial Justice Act: a guarantee of charging or sentencing relief for anyone subjected to police racism during arrest or investigation.

The Ostensible (and, at Times, Actual) Virtue of Deference

Rethinking Police Expertise  reveals how litigators can use police officers’ assertions of expertise against them. This Response questions the value, however, of urging judges to treat police expertise as a “professional technology” as opposed to a “professional virtue.” Insisting on this conceptual …

Probable Cause Pluralism

According to the Supreme Court, the most important phrase in the Fourth Amendment,  “ probable cause, ”   is not possible  to define. This Article disagrees. It proposes a novel and comprehensive account of probable cause—one that offers meaningful and predictable constraints on law enforcement ,  while avo…

The Power of Police Officers to Give “Lawful Orders”

Forty-four states, the District of Columbia, and the federal government criminalize disobeying the “lawful orders” of police officers. But it is uncertain which orders are lawful. This Comment proposes a model statute that would clarify and limit police authority while informing civilians about the …

(Un)Constitutional Punishments: Eighth Amendment Silos, Penological Purposes, and People’s “Ruin”

Timbs v. Indiana reaffirms the Constitution's role in determining the bounds of licit punishment. This Essay weaves together doctrines that are often siloed but answer the same question: what can't governments do as punishment? I argue that the law has begun to build the principle that governments n…

A Proposal to Stop Tinkering with the Machinery of Debt

In the wake of the Supreme Court’s  2019  decision in  Timbs  v. Indiana , which applied the Excessive Fines Clause to the States, this Essay argues  that defendants are better protected by  replac ing  the clause’s “gross disproportionality” standard with the more rigorous proportionality guarantee of the E…

Financial Hardship and the Excessive Fines Clause: Assessing the Severity of Property Forfeitures After Timbs

This Essay sketches the outlines of a  forfeitures  jurisprudence under the Eighth Amendment’s Excessive Fines Clause in which the effect of property deprivations on individuals and their families—in particular, the infliction of financial hardship—is a core criterion in assessing a forfeiture’s sever…

Bias In, Bias Out

The rise of criminal justice risk assessment has generated concerns about its disparate racial impact. Yet the prevailing responses to this problem, this Article contends, are inadequate. The real issue is the nature of prediction itself, and this demands a fundamental rethinking of risk assessment …

Jury Selection as Election: A New Framework for Peremptory Strikes

The ability of peremptory strikes to contribute to impartial juries has long been debated. This Note argues that both defenders and critics have overlooked an important value served by peremptory strikes beyond impartiality: democratic legitimacy. Just as elections help legitimate the state’s coerci…

The Voluntariness of Voluntary Consent: Consent Searches and the Psychology of Compliance

The Fourth Amendment allows police to perform warrantless searches of individuals if they give consent to be searched and that consent is voluntary. Based on original laboratory research, this Essay posits that fact-finders assessing voluntariness underappreciate the extent to which suspects feel pr…

The High Stakes of Low-Level Criminal Justice

Alexandra Natapoff reviews Misdemeanorland , summarizing the book’s key contributions and extending its insights about New York City’s system of misdemeanor managerial social control to illuminate the broader dynamics and democratic significance of the U.S. misdemeanor process.

The Present Crisis in American Bail

This Essay reviews the recent rise of systemic injunctions against money bail systems and a major question they raise: what level of scrutiny applies to allegedly unconstitutional bail systems. It concludes that, in light of history and precedent, strict scrutiny is the appropriate standard. 

Fourth Amendment Reasonableness After Carpenter

In  Carpenter v. United States , the Supreme Court held that a warrant is required when the government collects certain categories of third-party data. This Essay argues that a categorical warrant requirement for electronic surveillance is a mistake, and that, when faced with warrantless electronic su…

Democratic Policing Before the Due Process Revolution

Prevailing narratives of the Warren Court’s Due Process Revolution emphasize how it constrained police behavior. This Essay questions this account. It returns to the legal culture before the Revolution, focusing on three lectures by the prominent scholar Jerome Hall. Due process, it concludes, as mu…

The Punishment Bureaucracy: How to Think About “Criminal Justice Reform”

The “criminal justice reform” movement is in danger. Efforts to change the punishment bureaucracy are at risk of being co-opted by bureaucrats who have created and profited from mass human caging. This Essay seeks to understand the true functions of the punishment bureaucracy and to offer suggestion…

What Break Do Children Deserve? Juveniles, Crime, and Justice Kennedy’s Influence on the Supreme Court’s Eighth Amendment Jurisprudence

Many read Justice Kennedy’s landmark Eighth Amendment sentencing cases to herald a fundamental change in how juveniles are treated in the criminal justice system. But the better reading is more modest. Instead, they force us to ask what it means to say that youth is relevant to the determination of …

The Pope and the Capital Juror

The Pope recently pronounced capital punishment impermissible. Counterintuitively, this might make capital punishment less popular but more prevalent. This Essay anticipates this dynamic, and explores how “death qualification” of juries insulates the death penalty even as community morality evolves …

In the Shadow of Child Protective Services: Noncitizen Parents and the Child-Welfare System

The noncitizen parent exists between two often-conflicting legal identities: that of an immigrant and that of a parent. This Essay argues that state child services should strive to mitigate the tension between these identities and take an active role in shielding these parents from immigration conse…

Beyond the Box: Safeguarding Employment for Arrested Employees

Most criminal system reform efforts neglect the collateral consequences experienced by individuals with pending criminal cases. This Essay argues that meaningful reform requires enhanced protections for current employees and applicants with open criminal cases.

Dangerous Defendants

Bail reformers aspire to untether pretrial detention from wealth and condition it instead on the risk that a defendant will commit crime if released. In setting this risk threshold, this Article argues that there is no clear constitutional, moral, or practical basis for distinguishing between equall…

Government Hacking

The United States government hacks computer systems for law enforcement purposes. This Article provides the first comprehensive examination of how federal law regulates government malware, and argues that government hacking is inherently a Fourth Amendment search—a question on which the courts have …

Machine Testimony

Machines play increasingly crucial roles in establishing facts in legal disputes. Some machines convey information—the images of cameras, the measurements of thermometers, the opinions of expert systems. When a litigant offers a human assertion for its truth, the law subjects…

Cops and Pleas: Police Officers’ Influence on Plea Bargaining

abstract.Police officers play an important, though little-understood, role in plea bargaining. This Essay examines the many ways in which prosecutors and police officers consult, collaborate, and clash with each other over plea bargaining. Using original interviews with criminal justice of…

The Bostic Question

Introduction Federal criminal procedure regularly struggles with a tension between fairness and finality. The Constitution provides defendants with special privileges and protections designed to prevent injustice,1 but systemic concerns about efficiency, comity, and finality make i…

Systemic Triage: Implicit Racial Bias in the Criminal Courtroom

Crook County: Racism and Injustice in America’s Largest Criminal Court By Nicole van cleve Stanford university press, april 2016 author. Professor of Law, U.C. Irvine School of Law. A.B. Harvard College, J.D. Yale Law School. I wish to thank Rick Banks, Erwin Chemerins…

From False Evidence Ploy to False Guilty Plea: An Unjustified Path To Securing Convictions

introduction On June 20, 1991, two police officers brought an African American man named Anthony Gray into custody for questioning related to the unsolved rape and murder of a woman in Calvert County, Maryland.1 During the interrogation, the detectives lied to Mr. Gray about the evid…

Innocence and Override

For the past three decades, the practice of judicial override in capital cases has allowed Alabama judges to impose the death penalty even where the jury voted for life. However, recent developments have cast doubt on the future of override in Alabama. The United States Supreme Court struck down par…

Ideological Imbalance and the Peremptory Challenge

Legal scholars, by and large, revile peremptory challenges. Allowing parties to unilaterally strike prospective jurors without explanation has been attacked as undemocratic,1 as prone to manipulation,2 as a potential First Amendment violation,3 and—most often of all—as racist.4 Judge…

The New Public

By exploring the intertwined histories of the automobile, policing, criminal procedure, and the administrative state in the twentieth-century United States, this Essay argues that the growth of the police’s discretionary authority had its roots in the governance of an automotiv…

Will Putting Cameras on Police Reduce Polarization?

In the wake of national outrage and polarization over several high-profile police shootings of unarmed citizens, reformers have called for police officers to wear body cameras. This Note argues that, despite the seeming objectivity of the camera, video footage remains susceptible…

The Lost “Effects” of the Fourth Amendment: Giving Personal Property Due Protection

In addition to “persons, houses, [and] papers,” the Constitution protects individuals against unreasonable searches and seizures of “effects.” However, “effects” have received considerably less attention than the rest of the categories in the Fourth Amendment. Rec…

Roundup: Recent Developments in Criminal Justice and Mental Health Law

Over the past few weeks, several major developments have occurred at the intersection of criminal justice and mental health law. This Roundup briefly summarizes these matters and discusses how each reflects current trends in the criminal justice system’s approach to individuals with mental …

Riley 's Implications for Fourth Amendment Protection in the Cloud

In June 2014, the Supreme Court unanimously held in Riley v. California1 that the digital content of cell phones does not fall within the search-incident-to-arrest exception to the Fourth Amendment’s prohibition against unreasonable searches. The Court provided a clear answer “to the qu…

A Conversation with Justice Sotomayor

On February 3, 2014, Justice Sonia Sotomayor delivered the James A. Thomas Lecture at Yale Law School. This transcript is adapted (with slight editing) from that lecture, which took the form of a conversation between Justice Sotomayor and Linda Greenhouse. The lecture touched on topics including Jus…

Secrecy, Intimacy, and Workable Rules: Justice Sotomayor Stakes Out the Middle Ground in United States v. Jones

In this Essay, Professor Miriam Baer focuses on Justice Sotomayor’s concurrence in United States v. Jones , which has attracted widespread notice due to Justice Sotomayor’s suggestion that the Court reconsider its reasonable expectation of privacy test and the related third-party doctrine. Professor …

Justice Sotomayor and Criminal Justice in the Real World

As part of the symposium to reflect on Justice Sotomayor’s first five years on the Supreme Court, this Essay explores Justice Sotomayor’s contributions to the Court’s criminal law jurisprudence. Professor Rachel Barkow argues that Justice Sotomayor’s prior experience working on criminal law cases as…

Reading Michigan v. Bryant , “Reading” Justice Sotomayor

What are we to make of Justice Sotomayor’s criminal procedure jurisprudence? In this Essay, Professor I. Bennett Capers attempts to answer that question by offering three readings of her Confrontation Clause decision in Michigan v. Bryant . All three close readings, coupled with details from her memo…

Justice Sotomayor and the Jurisprudence of Procedural Justice

In this Essay, Professors Tyler and Meares highlight the ways in which recent social science research supports the model of jurisprudence articulated by Justice Sotomayor. Her model defines building identification with political and legal institutions as an important goal for the Court.  It further …

Justice Sotomayor and the Supreme Court’s Certiorari Process

The Supreme Court’s certiorari process is generally a black box. Occasionally, however, Justices issue statements explaining their dissent from or concurrence in the denial of certiorari. Since she joined the Court, Justice Sotomayor has produced more of these statements than any of her colleagues. …

On Estimating Disparity and Inferring Causation: Sur-Reply to the U.S. Sentencing Commission Staff

In this Essay, Professors Starr and Rehavi respond to the U.S. Sentencing Commission’s empirical staff’s criticisms of their recent article, which found, contrary to the Commission’s prior work, no evidence that racial disparity in sentences increased in response to United States v. Booker . As Starr…

Why Judges Matter at Sentencing: A Reply to Starr and Rehavi

In this Essay, researchers at the United States Sentencing Commission respond to criticisms by Sonja Starr and Marit Rehavi, published in the Yale Law Journal , of the Commission’s past analyses of demographic differences in federal sentences. The researchers explain the legal and practical foundatio…

Why Civil Gideon Won’t Fix Family Law

This Essay explains why we should hesitate before throwing full support behind a civil Gideon initiative for family law, regardless of how wholeheartedly we embrace the proposition that parental rights are as important as physical liberty. The comparable importance of these interests does not necess…

Gideon Exceptionalism?

122 Yale L.J. 2126 (2013). There is no doubt that Gideon v. Wainwright is extraordinary, but in thinking about its uniqueness, we are reminded of “American exceptionalism” and the diametrically opposed meanings that advocates have ascribed to the phrase. Gideon too is exceptional, in both the laudato…

Poor People Lose: Gideon and the Critique of Rights

122 Yale L.J. 2176 (2013). A low income person is more likely to be prosecuted and imprisoned post- Gideon than pre- Gideon . Poor people lose in American criminal justice not because they have ineffective lawyers but because they are selectively targeted by police, prosecutors, and law makers. The crit…

Celebrating the “Null” Finding: Evidence-Based Strategies for Improving Access to Legal Services

122 Yale L.J. 2206 (2013). Recent empirical studies tested whether litigants with access to lawyers fared better than litigants with access only to advice or limited assistance. Two of the three studies produced null findings—the litigants with access to lawyers, the treatment group, fared no better …

Race and the Disappointing Right to Counsel

122 Yale L.J. 2236 (2013). Critics of the criminal justice system observe that the promise of Gideon v. Wainwright remains unfulfilled. They decry both the inadequate quality of representation available to indigent defendants and the racially disproportionate outcome of the criminal process. Some hop…

Searching for Solutions to the Indigent Defense Crisis in the Broader Criminal Justice Reform Agenda

122 Yale L.J. 2316 (2013). As we mark the fiftieth anniversary of the Gideon v. Wainwright decision, the nearly universal assessment is that our indigent defense system remains too under-resourced and overwhelmed to fulfill the promise of the landmark decision, and needs to be reformed. At the same t…

Gideon’s Amici: Why Do Prosecutors So Rarely Defend the Rights of the Accused?

122 Yale L.J. 2336 (2013). In Gideon v. Wainwright , twenty-three state attorneys general, led by Walter F. Mondale and Edward McCormack, joined an amicus brief on the side of the criminal accused, urging the Supreme Court to recognize indigent defendants’ Sixth Amendment right to appointed counsel in…

Valuing Gideon’s Gold: How Much Justice Can We Afford?

122 Yale L.J. 2358 (2013). In this Essay, we explore Gideon ’s impact in our community, El Paso, Texas, which has the will to try to meet Gideon ’s challenge, but lacks the resources to deliver fully Gideon ’s promise. We look at the origins of our community’s indigent defense reform and examine our off…

Investigating Gideon’s Legacy in the U.S. Courts of Appeals

122 Yale L.J. 2376 (2013). This Essay investigates the legacy of Gideon by examining the de facto courts of last resort for convicted offenders: the federal courts of appeals. Part I focuses on the U.S. courts of appeals’ judges and caseloads, revealing that very few federal appellate judges have pri…

Gideon at Guantánamo

122 Yale L.J. 2416 (2013). The right to counsel maintains an uneasy relationship with the demands of trials for war crimes. Drawing on the author’s personal experiences from defending a Guantánamo detainee, the Author explains how Gideon set a baseline for the right to counsel at Guantánamo. Whether …

Enforcing Effective Assistance After Martinez

122 Yale L.J. 2428 (2013). This Essay argues that the Court’s effort to expand habeas review of ineffective assistance of counsel claims in Martinez v. Ryan will make little difference in either the enforcement of the right to the effective assistance of counsel or the provision of competent represen…

Gideon’s Law-Protective Function

122 Yale L.J. 2460 (2013). Gideon v. Wainwright dramatically affects the rights of indigent defendants by entitling them to representation. But Gideon has another systemic consequence as well. In addition to protecting the rights of individual defendants in particular trials, Gideon also protects the…

Gideon’s Shadow

122 Yale L.J. 2482 (2013). The right to counsel is regarded as a right without peer, even in a field of litigation saturated with constitutional protections. But from this elevated, elite-right status, the right to counsel casts a shadow over the other, less prominent criminal procedure rights. Elabo…

Gideon at Guantánamo: Democratic and Despotic Detention

122 Yale L.J. 2504 (2013). One measure of Gideon v. Wainwright is that it made the U.S. government’s efforts to isolate 9/11 detainees from all outsiders at Guantánamo Bay conceptually and legally unsustainable. Gideon , along with Miranda v. Arizona , is part of a democratic narrative shaped over dec…

Fear of Adversariness: Using Gideon To Restrict Defendants’ Invocation of Adversary Procedures

122 Yale L.J. 2550 (2013). Fifty years ago Gideon promised that an attorney would vindicate the constitutional rights of any accused too poor to afford an attorney. But Gideon also promised more. Writ small, Gideon promised to protect individual defendants; writ large, Gideon promised to protect our …

Federal Public Defense in an Age of Inquisition

122 Yale L.J. 2578 (2013). This Essay asks whether federal criminal defendants receive fairer process today than they did in 1963, when Gideon v. Wainwright was decided. It concludes that in many situations they do not; indeed, they often receive far worse. Although Gideon and the Criminal Justice Ac…

Effective Trial Counsel After Martinez v. Ryan: Focusing on the Adequacy of State Procedures

122 Yale L.J. 2604 (2013). Everyone knows that excessive caseloads, poor funding, and a lack of training plague indigent defense delivery systems throughout the states, such that the promise of Gideon v. Wainwright is largely unfulfilled. Commentators have disagreed about how best to breathe life int…

Implicit Racial Bias in Public Defender Triage

122 Yale L.J. 2626 (2013). Despite the promise of Gideon , providing “the guiding hand of counsel” to indigent defendants remains unmanageable, largely because the nation’s public defender offices are overworked and underfunded. Faced with overwhelming caseloads and inadequate resources, public defend…

Effective Plea Bargaining Counsel

122 Yale L.J. 2650 (2013). Fifty years ago, Clarence Earl Gideon needed an effective trial attorney. The Supreme Court agreed with Gideon that the Sixth Amendment guaranteed him the right to counsel at trial. Recently, Galin Frye and Anthony Cooper also needed effective representation. These two men,…

Lessons from Gideon

122 Yale L.J. 2676 (2013). Why has the promise of Gideon gone largely unfulfilled and what can be learned from this? Gideon was an unfunded mandate to state governments, requiring them to provide the money to ensure competent counsel for all criminal defendants facing possible prison sentences. Gideo…

Gideon at Fifty: A Problem of Political Will

122 Yale L.J. 2694 (2013). Although it is fitting to celebrate Gideon ’s promise of representation for indigent criminal defendants at this landmark anniversary, it is important also to note that part of Gideon ’s legacy should be our recognition of the limits of law in the fulfillment of that promise.…

Mere Negligence or Abandonment? Evaluating Claims of Attorney Misconduct After Maples v. Thomas

122 Yale L.J. 1328 (2013). In recent terms the Supreme Court has attempted to carve out remedies for habeas petitioners with negligent lawyers. This Note explores the analysis used by the Court in these cases and applies a novel descriptive model to explain how the Court has applied two different mod…

Asymmetries and Incentives in Plea Bargaining and Evidence Production

122 Yale L.J. 690 (2012). Legal rules severely restrict payments to fact witnesses, though the government can often offer plea bargains or other nonmonetary inducements to encourage testimony. This asymmetry is something of a puzzle, for most asymmetries in criminal law favor the defendant. The asymm…

Targeting the Twenty-First-Century Outlaw

122 Yale L.J. 724 (2012). This Note proposes using outlawry proceedings to bring legitimacy to the government’s targeted killing regime. Far from clearly contrary to the letter and spirit of American due process, outlawry endured for centuries at English common law and was used to sanction lethal for…

Confronting Crawford v. Washington in the Lower Courts

122 Yale L.J. 782 (2012). Crawford v. Washington is arguably the most significant criminal procedure decision of the last decade. Critics have argued that the Crawford line is a doctrinal muddle that has led to arbitrary and unpredictable results in the lower courts. I respond to this critique by pre…

Burden of Proof

121 Yale L.J. 738 (2012).

The burden of proof is a central feature of all systems of adjudication, yet one that has been subject to little normative analysis. This Article examines how strong evidence should have to be in order to assign liability when the objective is to maximize social welfare. I…

Padilla v. Kentucky: The Effect of Plea Colloquy Warnings on Defendants’ Ability To Bring Successful Padilla Claims

121 Yale L.J. 944 (2012).

In Padilla v. Kentucky, the Supreme Court held that a lawyer’s failure to advise her noncitizen client of the deportation consequences of a guilty plea constitutes deficient performance of counsel in violation of a defendant’s Sixth Amendment rights. In the plea conte…

Baseline Framing in Sentencing

121 Yale L.J. 426 (2011).

When judges sentence criminal offenders, they begin their analysis with a baseline sentence established by statutes or guidelines. Cognitive biases will likely cause this initial baseline to frame judges’ thought processes, such that judges will impose different sentenc…

Deal or No Deal? Remedying Ineffective Assistance of Counsel During Plea Bargaining

120 Yale L.J. 1532 (2011). 

What happens when a defendant receives defective counsel during plea bargaining but subsequently receives a fair trial? This Note discusses three different approaches: no remedy, specific performance of the plea bargain, and a retrial. It argues that specific performance…

Neuroscience and Institutional Choice in Federal Sentencing Law

120 Yale L.J. 367 (2010). 

Huppert v. City of Pittsburg: The Contested Status of Police Officers’ Subpoenaed Testimony After Garcetti v. Ceballos

119 Yale L.J. 2143 (2010). 

The Reverse-Batson: Wrestling with the Habeas Remedy

119 Yale L.J. 1739 (2010). 

Discovery Audits: Model Rule 3.8(d) and the Prosecutor's Duty To Disclose

119 Yale L.J. 1339 (2010). 

Fourth Amendment Seizures of Computer Data

119 Yale L.J. 700 (2010). 

What does it mean to “seize” computer data for Fourth Amendment purposes? Does copying data amount to a seizure, and if so, when? This Article argues that copying data “seizes” it under the Fourth Amendment when copying occurs without human observation and interrupts the …

Our Imperial Criminal Procedure: Problems in the Extraterritorial Application of U.S. Constitutional Law

118 Yale L.J. 1660 (2009).

From the early days of the Republic, courts have encountered the question of whether and to what extent provisions of the Constitution establishing individual rights have force beyond the borders of the United States—that is, whether the Constitution has “extraterritor…

The Example of America

what is criminal procedure essay

The Pocket Part is pleased to present an adapted version of Professor Fis…

The Mismatch Between Probable Cause and Partial Matching

http://www.flickr.com/photos/gravitywave/7715395/

The Sentence Imposed Versus the Statutory Maximum: Repairing the Armed Career Criminal Act

118 Yale L.J. 369 (2008).

John Doe Subpoenas: Toward a Consistent Legal Standard

118 Yale L.J. 320 (2008).

This Note considers the rising trend of anonymous online harassment and the use of John Doe subpoenas to unmask anonymous speakers. Although anonymity often serves as an important shield for valuable speech, it also protects online harassment that can chill or completel…

Discovering Arrest Warrants: Intervening Police Conduct and Foreseeability

118 Yale L.J. 177 (2008).

Comparative Corporate Criminal Liability: Exploring the Uniquely American Doctrine Through Comparative Criminal Procedure

118 Yale L.J. 126 (2008).

In the United States, corporations—as entities—can be criminally tried and convicted for crimes committed by individual directors, managers, and even low-level employees. From a comparative perspective, such corporate liability marks the United States as relatively uniqu…

Citing the Transcript of Oral Argument: Which Justices Do It and Why

http://www.flickr.com/photos/jcarole/2380885836/

Undermining Excessive Privacy for Police: Citizen Tape Recording To Check Police Officers' Power

117 Yale L.J. 1549 (2008).

Federal Sentencing in 2007: The Center Holds—The Supreme Court Doesn't

117 Yale L.J. 1374 (2008).

This essay takes stock of federal sentencing after 2007, the year of the periphery. On Capitol Hill, Attorney General Alberto Gonzales resigned in the face of widespread criticism over his role in the replacement of several U.S. Attorneys. In the Supreme Court, the trio o…

The Arc of the Pendulum: Judges, Prosecutors, and the Exercise of Discretion

117 Yale L.J. 1420 (2008).

Early scholarship on the Federal Sentencing Guidelines focused on the transfer of sentencing authority from judges to the Sentencing Commission; later studies examined the transfer of discretion from judges to prosecutors. Of equal significance are two other institutional…

The Case Against Automatic Reversal of Structural Errors

117 Yale L.J. 1180 (2008).

This Note describes the case law governing three structural errors and shows that the rule of automatic reversal has led appellate courts to narrow the scope of the rights at issue. To avoid this effect, the Note proposes a new framework for determining whether a given ty…

Re-Justifying the Fair Cross Section Requirement: Equal Representation and Enfranchisement in the American Criminal Jury

116 Yale L.J. 1568 (2007)

This Note proposes a new justification for the fair cross section (FCS) requirement governing criminal jury composition. While the Supreme Court has defended the requirement by invoking demographic conceptions of the jury’s legitimacy, many scholars have observed that this…

What Booker Means for Convicted Corporations

what is criminal procedure essay

The Organizational Guidelines: R.I.P.?

In a recent issue of this Journal, Timothy A. Johnson argues that Congress may not make the Federal Sentencing Guidelines provisions on the sentencing of organizations (the “Organizational Guidelines”) mandatory because United States v. Booker guarantees the constitutional right of corporations…

Right and Responsibility in Fourth Amendment Jurisprudence: The Problem with Pretext

Since Whren v. United States , Fourth Amendment analysis has failed to appreciate the serious wrongfulness of pretextual police behavior—especially searches and seizures. This is not because a pretext test is impractical or philosophically unsound. Rather, the problem lies in the current focus of our…

Throwing Away the Key

The problem today is not only the draconian sentences that white-collar offenders are receiving, but the fact that because of the elimination of parole they will actually have to serve them. For example, if Michael Milken had been sentenced under today's sentencing regime, and if he had been made to…

Combatant Status Review Tribunals: Flawed Answers to the Wrong Question

116 Yale L.J. 667 (2006)

Read  Geoffrey Corn, Eric Talbot Jensen, and Sean Watts's Response, Understanding the Distinct Function of the Combatant Status Review Tribunals: A Response to Blocher.

Should the Criminal Defendant Be Assigned a Seat in Court?

115 Yale L.J. 2203 (2006) In this Comment I question the U.S. Attorney's claim that every criminal defendant should be required to sit at the table farthest from the jury. Courtroom seating is properly within a trial judge's discretion, and there are good reasons for seating some criminal defendants …

Unaccountable at the Founding: The Originalist Case for Anonymous Juries

115 Yale L.J. 1823 (2006) This Comment argues that the courts overlook important Founding-era evidence on juror accountability. It concludes that the Public Trial Clause does not require juror identification. Part I describes the Public Trial Clause accountability argument made against the anonymous …

A Fair Trial Remedy for Brady Violations

115 Yale L.J. 1450 (2006) This Note proposes a new remedy for criminal defendants when the government fails to fulfill its constitutional duty to disclose favorable evidence. When evidence that should have been disclosed earlier emerges during or shortly before trial, the court should consider instru…

Managing Transitional Moments in Criminal Cases

115 Yale L.J. 922 (2006) As long as some courts review the work of others, there will be situations in which governing precedent shifts during the interval between an initial decision and the underlying dispute's ultimate resolution. Although such "transitional moments" follow many appellate court de…

A Quantitative Look at the Two-Suspect Scenario

115 Yale L.J. 1167 (2006) Two men are placed at the scene of a homicide. Each has an unsavory past and either could be the murderer--or an innocent man. It all depends on whether a witness should be believed, how the evidence is pieced together, and how the prosecutor decides to proceed. Should he tr…

Viewing CSI and the Threshold of Guilt: Managing Truth and Justice in Reality and Fiction

The " CSI effect" is a term that legal authorities and the mass media have coined to describe a supposed influence that watching the television show CSI: Crime Scene Investigation has on juror behavior. Some have claimed that jurors who see the high-quality forensic evidence presented on CSI raise th…

Can Attorneys and Clients Conspire?

114 Yale L.J. 1819 (2005) A conspiracy is traditionally defined as "[a]n agreement between two or more persons to commit an unlawful act." The condition that two or more persons be involved is known as the "plurality" requirement. In Farese v. Scherer, the Eleventh Circuit held that an attorney acti…

Overlooking a Sixth Amendment Framework

114 Yale L.J. 905 (2005) As the Supreme Court further plunges the world of criminal sentencing into turmoil, state courts in particular are scrutinizing their own statutory sentencing schemes and judicial practices. Ever since the Court's holding in Apprendi v. New Jersey (recently reformulated and…

Solving the Due Process Problem with Military Commissions

114 Yale L.J. 921 (2005) The terrorist attacks of September 11, 2001 prompted the creation of two new adjudicatory bodies within the Department of Defense. First, military commissions were established by presidential order just two months after the attacks in order to prosecute members of al Qaeda fo…

Integrating Remorse and Apology into Criminal Procedure

114 Yale L.J. 85 (2004) Criminal procedure largely ignores remorse and apology or, at most, uses them as proxies for an individual defendant's badness. The field is preoccupied with procedural values such as efficiency, accuracy, and procedural fairness, to the exclusion of the criminal law's substan…

Dual Sovereignty and the Sixth Amendment Right to Counsel

113 Yale L.J. 1991 (2004) United States v. Bird, 287 F.3d 709 (8th Cir. 2002); United States v. Avants, 278 F.3d 510 (5th Cir.), cert. denied, 536 U.S. 968 (2002). In Texas v. Cobb, the Supreme Court affirmed that the Sixth Amendment right to counsel is "offense specific" and attaches only to charg…

What Feeney Got Right: Why Courts of Appeals Should Review Sentencing Departures De Novo

113 Yale L.J. 1955 (2004) Last summer, when a panel of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the First Circuit issued its initial ruling in United States v. Thurston, it plunged into a war between federal judges and Congress, as well as between district and appellate courts, over how much flexibility trial j…

A Better Interpretation of "Special Needs" Doctrine After Edmond and Ferguson

112 Yale L.J. 2591 (2003)

Why Contempt Is Different: Agency Costs and "Petty Crime" in Summary Contempt Proceedings

112 Yale L.J. 1223 (2003) For as long as they have existed, contempt proceedings have been the source of significant controversy, their necessity and abuse hotly contested by the legal community, the legislature, and the judiciary. The raw, unchecked power of summary contempt--the ability of a judge …

Are Police Free To Disregard Miranda?

112 Yale L.J. 447 (2002) This Article contends that the common understanding of Miranda as a direct restraint on custodial interrogation by police is mistaken. Instead, Miranda, like the privilege against compulsory self-incrimination that serves as its constitutional foundation, is a rule of admissi…

Local Policing After the Terror

111 Yale L.J. 2137 (2002) Crime waves always carry with them calls for more law enforcement authority. What happened on September 11, 2001 was, among other things, a crime wave--because of that one day, the number of homicides in America in 2001 will be twenty percent higher than the year before. It…

Between Local Knowledge and National Politics: Debating Rationales for Jury Nullification After Bushell's Case

111 Yale L.J. 1815 (2002)

Unreasonable Probability of Error

111 Yale L.J. 435 (2001)

Jury Secrecy During Deliberations

110 Yale L.J. 1493 (2001)  

Judicial Fact-Finding and Sentence Enhancements in a World of Guilty Pleas

110 Yale L.J. 1097 (2001) Last June, in Apprendi v. New Jersey , the Supreme Court held that any fact that increases a defendant's statutory maximum sentence must be proved to a jury beyond a reasonable doubt. This rule, like most of criminal procedure law and scholarship, rests on the assumption that…

Rethinking the Puzzle of Escalating Penalties for Repeat Offenders

110 Yale L.J. 733 (2001) The general principle of escalating penalties based on offense history is so widely accepted that it strikes most people as simple common sense. This principle, however, tests the explanatory limits of economics. Contrary to the assumptions in the existing literature, probabi…

DNA's Dark Side

110 Yale L.J. 163 (2000)  

Prisoners of Their Own War: Can Policymakers Look Beyond the “War on Drugs” to Drug Treatment Courts?

http://www.flickr.com/photos/takomabibelot/229261477/

Announcing the YLJ Academic Summer Grants Program

Announcing the editors of volume 134, announcing the first-year editors of volume 133, featured content, lock them™ up: holding transnational corporate human-rights abusers accountable, administrative law at a turning point, law and movements: clinical perspectives.

Banner

Study Aids & Exam Prep

  • About This Guide
  • General Exam Prep
  • Administrative Law
  • Business Organizations & Corporations
  • Civil Procedure
  • Constitutional Law
  • Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Environmental Law
  • Intellectual Property
  • Legal Research & Writing
  • Legislation & Regulation
  • Native American Law
  • Negotiation and Mediation
  • Wills, Trusts, & Estates

Reviews, Outlines, & Checklists

Cover Art

Practice Questions

Cover Art

Audio & Visual Materials

Cover Art

Other Materials

Cover Art

Use your CALI username & password to access these lessons. Email  [email protected]  if you need to register for CALI.

  • << Previous: Criminal Law
  • Next: Family Law >>
  • Last Updated: Nov 14, 2023 10:49 AM
  • URL: https://guides-lawlibrary.colorado.edu/c.php?g=1354579

THE PLACE OF “THE PEOPLE” IN CRIMINAL PROCEDURE

Jocelyn simonson *.

The rules and practices of criminal procedure assume a clean separa­tion between the interests of the public and the interests of the lone defendant who stands accused. Even the names given to criminal pros­ecutions often declare this dichotomy, as in jurisdictions such as California, Illinois, Michigan, and New York that caption criminal cases “The People of the State of X v. John Doe.” This Essay argues that this traditional people/defendant dichotomy is critically flawed and then builds on that critique to point the way toward a more realistic, inclu­sive, and just vision of the role of the public in the criminal pro­cess.

The people/defendant dichotomy in the ideology of contemporary crimi­nal procedure rests on two mistaken premises: first, that prosecu­tors are and should be the primary representatives of the public in the court­room; and second, that the rules of criminal procedure must limit direct public participation to an illusory, limited subset of the public that is deemed “neutral” and “unbiased.” These conceptions of representa­tion and neutrality distort the criminal legal system’s understand­ing of who “the People” are, marginalizing and excluding the voices of those members of the community who stand to be harmed by the defendant’s prosecution or incarceration. As a result, the ideology of the people/defendant dichotomy promotes practices that are more puni­tive than the multifaceted interests of the public dictate.

This Essay puts forth a new, alternative approach to thinking about popular participa­tion in criminal procedure, an approach that recognizes that “the People” can and do appear on both sides of the scale of justice. This recogni­tion casts new light on the role of bottom-up resistance to local police actions and prosecutions—such as through courtwatching, participa­tory defense, and community bail funds—by those who otherwise do not have a voice in the process. And it directs us toward proce­dural rules and constitutional jurisprudence that both acknowledge com­munal interests beyond merely protecting “public safety” and pro­mote an inclusive system of criminal adjudication responsive to the multidi­mensional demands of the popular will.

* Assistant Professor, Brooklyn Law School. For helpful comments and conversa­tions, thank you to Amna Akbar, Rachel Barkow, Shima Baradaran Baughman, Rabia Belt, Bennett Capers, Jenny Carroll, Erin Collins, Andrew Crespo, Sharon Dolovich, Andrew Guthrie Ferguson, Russell Gold, Susan Herman, Brian Lee, Benjamin Levin, Kate Levine, Janet Moore, Kelli Moore, Erin Murphy, Alice Ristroph, David Sklansky, Sandra Guerra Thompson, and the faculties of Brooklyn Law School, UConn School of Law, the University of Texas School of Law, and Willamette University College of Law. I also received helpful feedback from participants in the Junior Criminal Law Faculty Roundtable, CrimFest Conference, Brooklyn/St. John’s Junior Scholars Roundtable, Criminal Justice Ethics Schmooze, and the AALS Annual Meeting Criminal Law & Procedure Works-in-Progress Session. I am grateful to the Brooklyn Law School Dean’s Summer Research Stipend for financial support.

INTRODUCTION

  • The Ideology of Criminal Procedure
  • The Public Participation Dilemma
  • Communal Participation from Below
  • The People v. the Defendant: Mapping the Dichotomy
  • The Representation Problem
  • The Neutrality Problem
  • Communal Contestation Through Criminal Procedure
  • Moving Beyond Representation
  • When the People Are on Both Sides
  • Communal Resistance and the Rule of Law
  • Procedure and the Possibility of Decarceration Today

Introduction

The customary case caption in criminal court, “The People v. Defendant,” pits the local community against one lone person in an act of collective condemnation. 1 1 See, e.g., Law Reporting Bureau of the State of N.Y., New York Law Reports Style Manual § 8.1(a) (2012), http://www.courts.state.ny.us/reporter/new_styman.htm [https://perma.cc/F93H-53DD] (“In criminal actions, the prosecuting authority is usually described as ‘The People of the State of New York.’”). In some jurisdictions, the prosecu­tion is termed “the State,” “the Commonwealth,” or “the United States,” rather than “the People.” See, e.g., Orin S. Kerr, How to Read a Legal Opinion, 11 Green Bag 2d 51, 52 (2007) (describing different types of case captions). ... Close Or, as the opening credits of Law and Order tell us, “The people are represented by two separate yet equally impor­tant groups: the police, who investigate crime, and the district attorneys, who prosecute the offenders.” 2 2 Title Sequence, Law & Order (NBC television broadcast 1990–2010). ... Close Procedures for policing, adjudication, and punishment often flow from this understanding of prosecutors and police officers as representatives of the public at large. 3 3 As discussed in Part II, prosecutors and the police are also bound by obligations beyond representing public sentiment, including constitutional limits on their conduct and ethical obligations to serve as “ministers of justice” in a neutral manner. ... Close We construct the rules of interaction between accused individuals and the state based on a balance between, on the one hand, giving individual defendants ade­quate protections against state power and, on the other hand, smoothing the wheels of justice so that state actors can do their work of promoting safety and punishing transgressions on behalf of us all. The public is brought into conversation with “the People” by voting for prosecutors and serving on the occasional jury, 4 4 Cf. Stephanos Bibas, The Machinery of Criminal Justice 1–40, 176 n.48, 177 n.56 (2012) [hereinafter Bibas, Machinery of Criminal Justice] (contrasting colonial American criminal justice, in which the public participated in individual cases, with the modern sys­tem of criminal procedure, in which the limited public input comes through elections, community policing or prosecution, and the rare jury trial). ... Close but rarely are members of the public at large—the people—envisioned as being on the side of defendants them­selves. 5 5 See infra Part II. ... Close

And yet acts of popular intervention on the side of defendants hap­pen every day: A community bail fund posts bail for a stranger; 6 6 See, e.g., People Freed, Chi. Cmty. Bond Fund, https://www.chicagobond.org/#people_freed [https://perma.cc/J5GC-DUAS] (last vis­ited Sept. 12, 2018) (describing stories of people in Chicago for whom the Chicago Community Bond Fund has posted bond). ... Close activists surround a police car in which officers have detained a fourteen-year-old black boy whom the activists have never met; 7 7 See Activists Helping Teen Detained by Police Pepper Sprayed in Cleveland , Al Jazeera Am. (July 27, 2015), http://america.aljazeera.com/articles/2015/7/27/black-lives-matter-activists-pepper-sprayed-in-cleveland.html [https://perma.cc/C6NQ-MGC2] (describing a crowd of Black Lives Matter activists in Cleveland gathering around a police van in which a fourteen-year-old had been detained, resulting in the release of the child to his mother without being arrested). ... Close a participatory defense team creates a biographical video about a defendant; 8 8 See ACJPDEBUG, Photo Recap: National Social Biography Media Boot Camp!, Albert Cobarrubias Justice Project (June 6, 2017), https://acjusticeproject.org/2017/06/06/photo-recap-national-social-biography-media-boot-camp/ [https://perma.cc/SR92-9QZH] (describing a meeting of participatory defense hubs from around the country to share strategies for creating social biography videos for use in court). ... Close a group of court­watch­ers sits in the audience section of a courtroom to demonstrate sup­port for the accused. 9 9 See, e.g., Black Lives Matter Supporters Gather 57,000 Signatures, Vow to Pack Pasadena Court During Jasmine Richards’ Sentencing Tuesday, Pasadena Now (June 6, 2016), http://www.pasadenanow.com/main/black-lives-matter-supporters-gather-57000-signatures-vow-to-pack-pasadena-court-during-jasmine-richards-sentencing-tuesday [https://perma.cc/W6U2-XW2M] (describing the plans of supporters of an activist con­victed of the felony charge of attempting to unlawfully remove a suspect from police offi­cers to “pack” the court at her sentencing hearing). ... Close These acts are sometimes isolated or spontane­ous. But often, they are part of long-term efforts by marginalized groups, especially poor people of color, to participate in a criminal legal system that they feel does not represent them. Organizer and writer Mariame Kaba explains this choice starkly: “Petitioning the state which is set up to kill us for help and protection can be untenable and therefore forces us to consider new ways of seeking some justice.” 10 10 Mariame Kaba, Free Us All: Participatory Defense Campaigns as Abolitionist Organizing, New Inquiry (May 8, 2017), https://thenewinquiry.com/free-us-all/ [https://perma.cc/QF98-2NQV] [hereinafter Kaba, Free Us All] (explaining why Kaba and other activists engage in participatory defense campaigns). ... Close For Kaba and many other activists, the futility of trying to have their voices heard by those in charge of policing and prosecution has led them to turn toward interven­tions on behalf of defendants as a means of collective action.

In the context of the criminal courthouse, in particular, marginal­ized groups have pursued methods of popular participation outside of the formal mechanisms of voting and jury service, through tactics such as community bail funds, participatory defense, and courtwatching. Main­stream reactions to these forms of participation range from outrage and disgust to more subtle requests for dialogue and decorum. 11 11 See infra section I.C. ... Close But rarely are these bottom-up acts of participation recognized as a legitimate part of our work of seeing justice done; rarely do we acknowledge in any formal manner that the arrest and prosecution of an individual can run against the interests of local community members. 12 12 See infra sections I.B–.C. ... Close By relegating com­munal interventions on behalf of defendants to the status of problematic interference, rather than productive public participation, the ideology of criminal procedure facilitates the exclusion of marginalized communities from everyday crimi­nal adjudication.

This Essay explores the disconnect between the leading conceptions of the proper place of public interventions in criminal procedure and the on-the-ground reality of groups who participate in everyday adjudica­tion on behalf of defendants. The idea that “the Prosecution” is synony­mous with “the People,” implicit in the case captions of California, Illinois, Michigan, and New York, serves as a jumping-off point for a larger examination of how we think about public participation in the crimi­nal process. Despite this focus on the term “the People,” this Essay is not centrally concerned with the meaning of “the People” in the text of the Constitution—whether it is “the People” of the Second or Fourth Amendments 13 13 Compare District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 625 (2008) (limiting the operative meaning of “the people” in the Second Amendment to “law-abiding citizens”), with United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259, 265 (1990) (defining “the people” in the Fourth Amendment as “a class of persons who are part of a national community or who have otherwise developed sufficient connection with this country”). ... Close or the “We, the People” of the Preamble. 14 14 Cf. Michael Perry, We the People: The Fourteenth Amendment and the Supreme Court 15–32 (1999) (describing how the definition of “we” in “We, the People” changes based on which part of the Constitution is being analyzed); Gary Lawson & Guy Seidman, Originalism as a Legal Enterprise , 23 Const. Comment. 47, 58–59 (2006) (providing an originalist interpretation of the term “We, the People”); Sanford Levinson, Who, if Anyone, Really Trusts “We the People”? , 37 Ohio N.U. L. Rev. 311, 317 (2011) (arguing that it is a mistake to infer from the “We, the People” of the Preamble that “the People” should actually rule in any fundamental sense); David A. Strauss, We the People, They the People, and the Puzzle of Democratic Constitutionalism, 91 Tex. L. Rev. 1969, 1973–77 (2013) (distinguishing between “We, the People” at the time of the drafting of the Constitution and the meaning of “the People” in constitutional interpretation today). For an argument that the constitutional ideal of “We, the People” should be a central animat­ing goal of criminal procedure, see Joshua Kleinfeld, Three Principles of Democratic Criminal Justice, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1455, 1483–86 (2017) [hereinafter Kleinfeld, Three Principles]. ... Close Instead, I exam­ine the dominant ways in which we think about the uses and limits of public participation in criminal procedure, more broadly conceived: not only constitutional doctrine, but also statutory, administrative, and customary rules and practices that structure everyday criminal adjudica­tion. When a judge orders a spectator to leave the courtroom or a clerk tells a community group that they cannot post bail, those official acts are as much a part of procedure as any formal rule. 15 15 Cf. Herbert Packer, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction 149 (1968) [hereinafter Packer, Limits] (describing “the criminal process” as “a compendious term that stands for all the complexes of activity that operate to bring the substantive law of crime to bear (or to keep it from coming to bear) on persons who are suspected of having committed crimes”); Sharon Dolovich & Alexandra Natapoff, Introduction: Mapping the New Criminal Justice Thinking [hereinafter Dolovich & Natapoff, Introduction], in The New Criminal Justice Thinking 1, 5 (Sharon Dolovich & Alexandra Natapoff eds., 2017) [hereinaf­ter Dolovich & Natapoff, The New Criminal Justice] (“[I]t is not enough to look to formal rules and processes. We must also attend to the reality on the ground . . . .”). For an argument advocating for a grounded understanding of criminal procedure, see infra section I.A. ... Close What emerges from examining both constitutional doctrine and these on-the-ground realities of everyday procedure is a striking dichotomy between the idea of a collec­tive “people,” and the lone defendant on the other side of the “v.”

This people/defendant dichotomy is problematic for a number of rea­sons. First, it assumes that the prosecution and the police adequately represent, or at least are capable of adequately representing, the interests of a local “community.” In reality, however, the unequal distribution of political power means that the decisions of “the People” are often not responsive to the interests of the poor populations of color most likely to come into contact with the criminal process as arrestees, defendants, or victims. 16 16 See Nicola Lacey, Humanizing the Criminal Justice Machine: Re-Animated Justice or Frankenstein’s Monster?, 126 Harv. L. Rev. 1299, 1321 (2013) (book review) (“[T]he ‘truly disadvantaged’ groups—who are mainly located in inner-city areas and whose victim­iza­tion at the hands of both crime and criminal justice underpins their more com­plex view of crime and punishment—are rarely the median or decisive voters in the elec­toral contests that shape policy.”); see also Traci Burch, Trading Democracy for Justice: Criminal Convictions and the Decline of Neighborhood Political Participation 75–104 (2013) (docu­menting the decline of political participation in neighborhoods with higher concen­trations of people with criminal records); Amy E. Lerman & Vesla M. Weaver, Arresting Citizenship: The Democratic Consequences of American Crime Control 202–18 (2014) (describing how contact with the criminal justice system dilutes political engage­ment); William J. Stuntz, The Collapse of American Criminal Justice 255 (2011) [hereinaf­ter Stuntz, Collapse of American Criminal Justice] (noting that “voters with the largest stake [in the process of building and filling prisons]—chiefly African American residents of high-crime city neighborhoods—had the smallest voice in the relevant decisions”); Dorothy E. Roberts, The Social and Moral Cost of Mass Incarceration in African American Communities, 56 Stan. L. Rev. 1271, 1291–98 (2004) [hereinafter Roberts, Social and Moral Cost] (detailing the “role [of mass incarceration] in controlling the social, eco­nomic, and political engagement of African American communities in the national polity”). ... Close Moreover, seeking public input only on behalf of policing and prosecution ignores the multifaceted nature of any “community,” 17 17 See Laura I. Appleman, Defending the Jury: Crime, Community, and the Constitution 70–87 (2015) (discussing the difficulties with defining community in relation to criminal justice); Albert W. Alschuler & Stephen J. Schulhofer, Antiquated Procedures or Bedrock Rights?: A Response to Professors Meares and Kahan , 1998 U. Chi. Legal F. 215, 216–17 (critiquing the amorphous concept of community in the context of policing); Regina Austin, “The Black Community,” Its Lawbreakers, and a Politics of Identification, 65 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1769, 1770–74 (1992) (describing different conceptions of “community” among African Americans with respect to criminal justice); Richard Delgado, Goodbye to Hammurabi: Analyzing the Atavistic Appeal of Restorative Justice , 52 Stan. L. Rev. 751, 769 (2000) (“In a diverse, multicultural society, many collectivi­ties may vie for th[e] status [of community].”); Robert Weisberg, Restorative Justice and the Danger of “Community,” 2003 Utah L. Rev. 343, 343 (critiquing the idea of community in the context of the restorative justice and “community justice” movements). ... Close exclud­ing strong critiques of reigning practices and resulting in an echo chamber that reinforces existing notions of justice. I call this set of issues with the people/defendant dichotomy the representation problem .

The second problem with the people/defendant dichotomy is that it is imbued with a false sense that our procedures promote “neutrality” from the public during adjudication and other criminal procedures. To be “neutral” is to side with the prosecution, not the defendant. The ideal public (whether voters, juries, courtroom audiences, or the community at large) becomes a disinterested and decorous public, calm and orderly, without “bias” against the police or the prosecution. This false ideal of neutrality allows for the exclusion of members of the public attempting to participate in ways that align with defendants’ interests. For example, police officers arrest individuals filming officers in public for “interfer­ence” with police work; 18 18 See Jocelyn Simonson, Beyond Body Cameras: Defending a Robust Right to Record the Police, 104 Geo. L.J. 1559, 1560–63 (2016) [hereinafter Simonson, Beyond Body Cameras] (describing resistance against organized copwatchers and individuals who record the police). ... Close judges forbid courtroom audience members from wearing shirts demonstrating support for defendants; 19 19 See, e.g., Lindsay Corcoran, Judge Says Worcester Protestor Can’t Wear Black Lives Matter Shirt During Trial, Mass Live (Nov. 9, 2015), https://www.masslive.com/news/worcester/index.ssf/2015/11/judge_says_worcester_protes­tor.html [https://perma.cc/S276-5457]; Ruthann Robson, Judge Bans Spectator Symbols in Cecily McMillan’s Trial, Dressing Constitutionally (Apr. 7, 2014), http://www.dressingconstitutionally.com/2014/04/ 07/judge-bans-spectator-symbols-in-cecily-mcmillans-trial/ [https://perma.cc/XWJ8-35XS]. ... Close court clerks refuse to let community bail funds post bail for strangers; 20 20 See, e.g., Toby Sells, Just City’s Bail Program Worked in Nashville, Can’t Get Consensus in Memphis, Memphis Flyer (July 14, 2016), https://www.memphisflyer.com/NewsBlog/archives/2016/07/14/just-citys-bail-program-worked-in-nashville-cant-get-consensus-in-memphis [https://perma.cc/CV4H-VBSR] (describ­ing procedural hoops set up by clerks and judges in Memphis that prevented activ­ists from operating a community bail fund). ... Close and jury selec­tion excludes individuals with criminal records or negative views of the police. 21 21 See Brian C. Kalt, The Exclusion of Felons from Jury Service, 53 Am. U. L. Rev. 65, 70–71 (2003) (describing exclusion of individuals with criminal records from juries); Anna Roberts, Disparately Seeking Jurors: Disparate Impact and the (Mis)use of Batson , 45 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 1359, 1403–04 (2012) [hereinafter Roberts, Disparately Seeking] (describ­­ing doctrine that comfortably allows prosecutors to strike from juries individuals with negative views of, or interactions with, the police and the criminal justice system). ... Close Under the guise of neutrality, popular efforts to intervene on behalf of defendants become interference with the rule of law rather than welcome participation . In the process, our estimations of public senti­ment become distorted toward the prosecution. This focus on the creation of a neutral public that is not biased toward the defense also cements the status of arrestees and defendants as the “other,” as a group of outsiders different from the average member of the public, rather than of the public. 22 22 See Erin R. Collins, Status Courts, 105 Geo. L.J. 1481, 1522–23 (2017) (describing the “‘othering’ effect” of reigning retributivist models of American criminal courts); Robert M. Cover, Violence and the Word, 95 Yale L.J. 1601, 1608 (1986) [hereinafter Cover, Violence] (explaining that when interpretive communities focus on a judge’s neu­tral interpretation, they distance themselves from the pain of the defendant); cf. Sune Qvotrup Jensen, Othering, Identity Formation and Agency, 2 Qualitative Stud. 63, 66–67 (2011) (describing the process of “othering” of minority groups so that they are imbued in the dominant culture with undesirable characteristics). ... Close This, in turn, colors the interpretation and implementa­tion of procedural rules. I think of this as the neutrality prob­lem .

My argument is that under the umbrella of the people/defendant dichot­omy, the representation problem and the neutrality problem together contribute to a concept of criminal procedure that moves us away from truly responsive local justice 23 23 See Philippe Nonet & Philip Selznick, Law and Society in Transition 77 (1978) (defining responsive legal institutions as those which open themselves up to adaptation by “perceiv[ing] social pressures as sources of knowledge and opportunities for self-correction”). ... Close and toward practices that are more punitive than the multifaceted interests of the public dictate. The people/defendant dichotomy constructs a limited and exclusionary view of which “public” matters in criminal adjudication. If we think of all mem­bers of the public as represented by “the People” and all those who might side with a defendant as “biased,” then we exclude from criminal adjudication those who would disagree with a prosecution or support a defendant, shutting out an entire subset of the public who might bring more contestatory views to the table. In doing so, procedural rules and practices do not simply mirror existing political inequalities — they create them. 24 24 See Janet Moore, The Antidemocratic Sixth Amendment , 91 Wash. L. Rev. 1705, 1718–20 (2016) (noting how the inability of indigent defendants to choose counsel exacer­bates the already existing inequalities in the justice system); Alexandra Natapoff, Speechless: The Silencing of Criminal Defendants, 80 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1449, 1452 (2005) [hereinafter Natapoff, Speechless] (describing how procedure leads to the “expressive disempowerment of those disadvantaged groups who tend to become defendants”); Dorothy E. Roberts, Constructing a Criminal Justice System Free of Racial Bias: An Abolitionist Framework, 39 Colum. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 261, 279–86 (2007) [hereinafter Roberts, Constructing a Criminal Justice System] (describing the criminal justice system’s “anti-democratic function”). ... Close This Essay is thus about ideology, about how the reign­ing assumptions structuring how we think about the criminal adjudica­tory process legitimize inequitable practices and limit how we design proce­dures and approach reform.

I explore an alternative approach to thinking about popular partici­pa­tion in criminal procedure, and especially in the adjudication of criminal cases. With this approach, “the People” appear on both sides of the scale of justice in individual cases; no longer can the prosecution call itself “the People.” I look to the bottom-up practices of marginalized groups intervening on behalf of defendants to show the possibility of a different way of thinking about the place of the people in the criminal process, one in which members of the public are allowed to voice their support or opposition through procedural channels other than elections, juries, or community justice fora. If a central purpose of criminal proce­dure becomes to channel the will of the people into both sides of each individual criminal case—the prosecution and the defense—then popu­lar efforts to intervene on behalf of criminal defendants take on legitimacy and importance. They become part of our system, worthy of examina­tion in any comprehensive debate over how we design our proce­dures.

This Essay is part of a larger vision of the importance of leaving the sphere of criminal law open to communal resistance and to agonistic partici­pation—forms of direct participation that engage with powerful state institutions in a respectful but adversarial manner. 25 25 See Jocelyn Simonson, Democratizing Criminal Justice Through Contestation and Resistance, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1609, 1611–13 (2017) [hereinafter Simonson, Democratizing Criminal Justice] (describing this larger vision); see also Jocelyn Simonson, Copwatching, 104 Calif. L. Rev. 391, 413–27 (2016) [hereinafter Simonson, Copwatching] (using the lens of agonism to argue for the importance of respecting the practice of orga­nized copwatching by marginalized populations). On agonism, see generally Chantal Mouffe, Agonistics: Thinking the World Politically 1–19 (2013) [hereinafter Mouffe, Agonistics] (summarizing a theoretical framework of agonistic politics); I. Bennett Capers, Criminal Procedure and the Good Citizen, 118 Colum. L. Rev. 653, 700–01 (2018) [hereinaf­ter Capers, Good Citizen] (describing the benefits of agonistic confrontations between civilians and the police); Sunita Patel, Toward Democratic Police Reform: A Vision for “Community Engagement” Provisions in DOJ Consent Decrees, 51 Wake Forest L. Rev. 793, 804–07 (2016) (using the theory of agonism to argue that we should respect and uplift the partici­pation of grassroots groups in police consent decrees). ... Close Crucial to this vision is a view that local criminal adjudication is and should be a site of communal contestation and resistance. 26 26 On the importance of resistance to everyday criminal justice, see Jenny E. Carroll, The Resistance Defense , 64 Ala. L. Rev. 589, 641–42 (2013); Eric J. Miller, Encountering Resistance: Contesting Policing and Procedural Justice, 2016 U. Chi. Legal F. 295, 343 [hereinafter Miller, Encountering Resistance]; Alice Ristroph, Regulation or Resistance? A Counter-Narrative of Constitutional Criminal Procedure, 95 B.U. L. Rev. 1555, 1558–60 (2015). ... Close This does not mean that all contes­tation is healthy or desirable. In the end, some popular interven­tions on behalf of defendants may skew the results of adjudication in ways that subvert our notions of fairness or the rule of law. But our start­ing point should be a presumption that popular interventions on behalf of defendants are legitimate, followed by an examination of whether they excessively undermine other competing values.

Part I begins by situating my argument within current debates over both the ideology of criminal procedure and the politics of criminal law. It then describes how bottom-up forms of communal contestation in everyday justice, including community bail funds, participatory defense, and courtwatching, present a vision of public intervention that does not fit neatly into existing narratives of popular participation. Part II lays out the contours of the dichotomy between “the People” and the defendant in our reigning ideology of criminal procedure. I argue that the people/defendant dichotomy carries with it two particular ideologi­cal problems: first, a limited focus on public participation through repre­sent­atives, and second, an illusory conception of a public that is “neutral” and unbiased. Part III conceptualizes how the public might instead participate on both sides of individual conflicts in the criminal courtroom. Under this approach, a state might facilitate, rather than silence, direct, con­testatory forms of participation in criminal adjudica­tion most often found on the defendant side of the “v.” Finally, Part IV defends the conception of placing “the People” on both sides in individ­ual criminal cases against the charge that it would unduly undermine the rule of law by connecting everyday contestation in criminal adjudication to the possibility of large-scale decarceration more broadly.

I. Ideology, Criminal Procedure, and Democracy

This Essay identifies, and then sets out an alternative to, a central ideo­logical idea in criminal procedure: that the public’s input should fall only on the side of “the People,” or the prosecution. In this Part, I situate this argument within current debates over, on the one hand, the study of ideology in criminal procedure and, on the other, the place of popular participation in criminal adjudication. My goal is to bridge these two conversations, revealing the connection between how we think about criminal procedure and the inclusion of generally disempowered popula­tions in our reigning conceptions of justice and fairness. A criminal legal system responsive to all facets of a local “community” should be one that facilitates collective forms of participation that challenge powerful institu­tional actors and dominant ideas of justice. Current forms of bot­tom-up communal contestation led by members of historically disempow­ered populations demonstrate how this might be possible and should inform our understandings of the interaction between the design of crimi­nal procedures and the possibilities of public participation in every­day justice.

A. The Ideology of Criminal Procedure

In legal scholarship, there is a rich history of thinking broadly about the structure of rules, doctrines, and cultures that produce everyday crimi­nal law and its processes—and often reproduce existing hierarchies and pathologies. 27 27 For examples in criminal justice scholarship, see, e.g., David Sklansky, Democracy and the Police 1–13 (2008) [hereinafter Sklansky, Democracy] (describing the links between conceptions of democracy and policing models); Sharon Dolovich, Exclusion and Control in the Carceral State, 16 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 259, 265 (2011) (describing “the ‘cognitive conventions’ by which current penal practices are rendered at once logical and legitimate,” including the focus on defendant autonomy and responsibility); Malcolm M. Feeley & Jonathan Simon, The New Penology: Notes on the Emerging Strategy of Corrections and Its Implications, 30 Criminology 449, 452–55 (1992) (describing a shift in penological discourse marked by “the replacement of a moral or clinical description of the individual with an actuarial language of probabilistic calculations and statistical distribu­tions applied to populations”); Carol S. Steiker & Jordan M. Steiker, Lessons for Law Reform from the American Experiment with Capital Punishment, 87 S. Cal. L. Rev. 733, 783 (2014) (arguing for the importance of paying attention to the “public framing, dis­course, and rhetoric” in constitutional regulation of the death penalty); Michael Tonry, Evidence, Ideology, and Politics in the Making of American Criminal Justice Policy, 42 Crime & Just. 1, 8 (2013) (arguing that criminal justice policy is influenced by “the filter of prevailing paradigms and ways of thinking”). ... Close In the context of criminal procedure, Herbert Packer famously posed two competing “models” of criminal procedure in the 1960s: the “Due Process model” and the “Crime Control model.” 28 28 Packer, Limits, supra note 15, at 153; Herbert L. Packer, Two Models of the Criminal Process, 113 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1, 6 (1964). ... Close Packer argues that how we think of the purpose of criminal procedure—as a vehicle for due process or as a means of facilitating speedy prosecu­tions—in turn mediates the interpretation of constitutional and proce­dural rules. Packer’s models have spawned a wide range of critiques and adjustments, which further both positive and normative models of how we structure our criminal procedures. 29 29 See, e.g., Hadar Aviram, Packer in Context: Formalism and Fairness in the Due Process Model, 36 Law & Soc. Inquiry 237, 237–38, 240 (2011) (discussing John Griffiths’s critique that Packer’s models “in fact presented two sides of the same model: the ‘battle’ between the ‘police perspective’ and the ‘ACLU perspective’”); John Griffiths, Ideology in Criminal Procedure or a Third “Model” of the Criminal Process, 79 Yale L.J. 359, 367–75 (1970) (critiquing both of Packer’s models and proposing a new “Family Model” of crimi­nal procedure); Alexandra Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid, in Dolovich & Natapoff, The New Criminal Justice, supra note 15, at 72–73, 92 [hereinafter Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid] (proposing a new model of analyzing criminal procedure focusing on the differ­ences in the criminal process along lines of race, class, gender, and other factors); Kent Roach, Four Models of the Criminal Process, 89 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 671, 672 (1999) (acknowledging the significance of Packer’s Due Process and Crime Control models but suggesting an alternative approach). ... Close A central insight of the literature on ideology and criminal procedure is that the principles we use to frame our procedures in turn shape the cultures of our precincts, courthouses, prisons, and other sites of interaction between criminal justice actors and the public. Although these principles are not always explicit, nor are they uniform, they constitute a set of ideas and assumptions that run beneath the operation of the criminal process and legitimize the sta­tus quo. 30 30 See Mirjan Damaška, Structures of Authority and Comparative Criminal Procedure, 84 Yale L.J. 480, 530 (1975) (“In discovering affinities between ideology and criminal procedure we are actually canvassing ideological arguments advanced in support of existing procedural arrangements and in opposition to their change.”). To use the term ideology to describe a conception of procedure underscores the potential of ingrained ideas about the legal and political world to legitimate and normalize systemic injustices. In Gramscian terms, legal ideology plays a role in perpetuating hegemonic relationships. See Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci 180–81 (Quintin Hoare & Geoffrey Nowell Smith eds. & trans., 1971). See generally Tommie Shelby, Dark Ghettos (2017) (defining ideology as “a widely held set of associated beliefs and implicit judgments that misrepresent significant social realities and that function, through this distortion, to bring about or perpetuate unjust social relations”). The legitimating function of legal ideology is a core insight of both critical legal studies and critical race theory. See, e.g., Alan David Freeman, Legitimizing Racial Discrimination Through Antidiscrimination Law: A Critical Review of Supreme Court Doctrine, 62 Minn. L. Rev . 1049, 1051–52 (1978) (arguing that legal doctrine can legitimate the existing social structure—but only if “it holds out a promise of liberation”); Karl E. Klare, Judicial Deradicalization of the Wagner Act and the Origins of Modern Legal Consciousness, 1937–1941, 62 Minn. L. Rev. 265, 268 (1978) (noting that the Court began to elaborate the boundaries of “legitimate” labor activity through development of Wagner Act doctrine). ... Close

A full study of the ideology of criminal procedure requires moving beyond analyses of constitutional doctrine. As Packer puts it, study­ing criminal procedure demands attending to all of “the complexes of activity that operate to bring the substantive law of crime to bear (or to keep it from coming to bear) on persons who are suspected of having committed crimes.” 31 31 Packer, Limits, supra note 15, at 149. Packer further argues that criminal proce­dure is both the rules of law and “patterns of official activity that correspond only in the roughest kind of way to the prescriptions of procedural rules.” Id. In other words, if under our expansive criminal codes we are all technically criminals, procedure is the complex of activities and rules that allow us to differentiate between those whom the state controls and supervises in the name of public safety, and those whom it does not. Cf. Damaška, supra note 30, at 481 (arguing that scholars of ideology and criminal procedure should “discard[ ] a preoccupation with legal mythology to consider law as it is actually applied”); William J. Stuntz, The Uneasy Relationship Between Criminal Procedure and Criminal Justice, 107 Yale L.J. 1, 53 (1997) [hereinafter Stuntz, Uneasy Relationship] (“The prob­lem with the criminal process may not be particular rules or practices, but rather the sys­tem that defines what that process should look like.”). ... Close Indeed, although the term “criminal procedure” can at times be shorthand for “constitutional criminal procedure,” schol­ars and teachers are increasingly recognizing that we must study and teach well beyond the doctrine to capture the reality of criminal adjud­ica­tion on the ground. 32 32 See Andrew Manuel Crespo, The Hidden Law of Plea Bargaining, 118 Colum. L. Rev. 1303, 1305–06 (2018) (describing the importance of subconstitutional court rules and state laws governing procedures of plea bargaining); Dolovich & Natapoff, Introduction, supra note 15, at 5 (“[I]t is not enough to look to formal rules and processes. We must also attend to the reality on the ground . . . .”); Rachel A. Harmon, The Problem of Policing, 110 Mich. L. Rev. 761, 768–81 (2012) (arguing that scholars must look beyond constitu­tional doctrine in thinking about the regulation of the police); Adriaan Lanni & Carol Steiker, A Thematic Approach to Teaching Criminal Adjudication, 60 St. Louis U. L.J. 463, 464–66 (2016) (urging a move beyond constitutional rules in teaching about the rules of criminal adjudication); Kate Levine, Police Suspects, 116 Colum. L. Rev. 1197, 1199–223 (2016) (describing the importance of looking at procedural protections beyond constitu­tional rights in the context of interrogations). ... Close “Criminal procedure” is thus a combina­tion of the rules and practices—constitutional, statutory, administrative, and customary—that structure contact with the criminal legal system for those suspected and accused of crimes. Widely held conceptions of these interactions in turn structure scholarship, doctrine, and the day-to-day practices of our courthouses and precincts.

The ideology of criminal procedure is especially important in the post-trial world of mass prosecutions and plea bargaining, in which “processes”—a stop-and-frisk, the provision of counsel, the decision to set bail—often determine as much as anything else the “substantive” out­come of a case or interaction. 33 33 See Josh Bowers, Legal Guilt, Normative Innocence, and the Equitable Decision Not to Prosecute, 110 Colum. L. Rev. 1655, 1692–703 (2010) (describing how discretionary decisions by police officers and prosecutors lead to the processing of misdemeanor arrests in a way that diverges from determinations of guilt and innocence); Paul Heaton et al., The Downstream Consequences of Misdemeanor Pretrial Detention, 69 Stan. L. Rev. 711, 722–23, 747 (2017) (describing how the setting of bail in low-level cases leads to a greater likelihood of guilty pleas and longer jail sentences); Alexandra Natapoff, Misdemeanors, 85 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1313, 1346–47 (2012) (describing how procedural pressures lead to “the perfect storm of wrongful pleas”). Indeed, the procedures themselves are often the heart of the experience of being prosecuted. See Malcolm M. Feeley, The Process Is the Punishment 222–43 (1979) (describing how the pretrial process amounts to its own form of punish­ment); Issa Kohler-Hausmann, Misdemeanor Justice: Control Without Conviction, 119 Am. J. Soc. 351, 355–57 (2013) (describing how the charging and pro­cessing of misde­meanor cases serves as a form of control even in the absence of convictions). ... Close Alexandra Natapoff recently theorized a model of criminal procedure that accounts for the differences between the substance-driven prosecutions of well-resourced defendants charged with serious crimes, often in federal court, and the experiences of less privileged defendants who are rushed through the criminal justice system without a thorough airing of the charges against them. Natapoff locates the experiences of poor people of color charged with low-level offenses as the bottom of a “penal pyramid”: a place where under-resourced defen­­dants charged with low-level cases face “outcomes . . . driven by institu­tional practices and inegalitarian social relations.” 34 34 Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid, supra note 29, at 92. ... Close At the bottom of the penal pyramid, where the vast majority of criminal cases take place, formal rules and methods of public intervention escape from view in favor of top-down institutional practices that facilitate control and surveil­lance along lines of class, race, and gender. 35 35 Id. at 75–90. ... Close In these situations, proce­dure is the control and the surveillance—the system doles out what Issa Kohler-Hausmann has termed “procedural hassle,” rather than conviction or formal punishment. 36 36 Kohler-Hausmann, supra note 33, at 353. ... Close A full account of the ideology of crimi­nal procedure in the post-trial world must therefore explore the relationship between the beliefs and judgments underlying procedural practices and the perpetuation of on-the-ground conditions of inequality.

B. The Public Participation Dilemma

How we think about criminal procedure is intimately connected to how we think about popular participation in criminal adjudication. Should members of the public be active participants in everyday criminal justice, or should the world of plea bargaining foreclose public interven­tion in favor of neutral processing by public representatives? Haunting this question is the widespread (though not universal) view that the cur­rent phenomena of “mass incarceration” 37 37 See, e.g., Devon W. Carbado, Predatory Policing, 85 UMKC L. Rev. 545, 549 (2017) (“Today, mass incarceration rolls comfortably off the tongues of people of all ideologi­cal stripes.”); Benjamin Levin, The Consensus Myth in Criminal Justice Reform, 117 Mich. L. Rev. 259, 276–84 (2018) (describing the scholarly conception of mass incarceration). ... Close and “overcriminalization” 38 38 See generally Douglas N. Husak, Overcriminalization: The Limits of the Criminal Law (2008) (examining the relationship between “too much” criminal law and “too much punishment”); Andrew Ashworth, Conceptions of Overcriminalization, 5 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 407 (2008) (discussing the need for a “consequentialist audit of criminal laws”); Levin, supra note 37, at 292–302 (describing the scholarly conception of overcriminalization); Erik Luna, The Overcriminalization Phenomenon, 54 Am. U. L. Rev. 703 (2005) (defining overcriminalization as a phenomenon to be evaluated in the aggregate for “causes, conse­quences, and correctives”). ... Close have been caused by a public bent toward “penal populism,” a hunger for criminalization and punishment beyond what is fair or rational. 39 39 See generally Julian V. Roberts et al., Penal Populism and Popular Opinion: Lessons from Five Countries 310 (2002) (“Most populist penal policies create dispro­portion­ate punishment and are profligate with respect to the use of incarceration.”). ... Close This public, lacking a nuanced understanding of the causes of crime or the consequences of punishment, should perhaps not be trusted with control over efforts at decarceration or criminal-law reform at the individual level. At the same time, however, there is growing concern from scholars of criminal law and procedure that our post-trial world, in which juries are largely absent, too comfortably excludes the public from everyday adjudication, resulting in a system divorced from popular ideals of justice and fairness. 40 40 See Laura I. Appleman, Defending the Jury: Crime, Community, and the Constitution 91–219 (2015); Bibas, Machinery of Criminal Justice, supra note 4, at 29–60; Albert Dzur, Punishment, Participatory Democracy, and the Jury 21–41 (2012); Kleinfeld, Three Principles, supra note 14, at 1483–88; see also infra note 53. ... Close Under this view, we might do well to include the public more often in our adjudication of cases, whether by expanding the use of juries or creating new institutions of “community justice.” This public participation dilemma pervades contemporary scholarship. 41 41 See Samuel Walker, Popular Justice: A History of American Criminal Justice 5–7 (2d ed. 1998) (describing the “paradox of popular justice,” which “represents the best and worst of American criminal justice history”); Joshua Kleinfeld, Manifesto of Democratic Criminal Justice, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1367, 1371, 1375–77 (2017) [hereinafter Kleinfeld, Manifesto] (describing a conflict among legal scholars between those who focus on improv­ing criminal justice through bureaucratic professionalization and those who favor democratization); David Sklansky, Unpacking the Relationship Between Prosecutors and Democracy in the United States, in Prosecutors and Democracy: A Cross-National Study 276, 276–86 (Maximo Langer & David Alan Sklansky eds., 2017) [hereinafter Sklansky, Unpacking the Relationship] (describing the prevalence of this dilemma in the context of conceptions of the role of prosecutors). ... Close

The dominant contemporary conception of how to mediate public par­ticipation in contemporary criminal adjudication is to give the public input into systemic laws, policies, and priorities but keep individual cases against defendants free of public interference, except in the rare case of a jury trial. This is the backbone of a particular conception of the rule of law, in which procedural rules and criminal laws are defined by democrati­cally elected legislatures, and judges and other courtroom actors then enforce those rules in a neutral and uniform way. 42 42 See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., “The Rule of Law” as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse, 97 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 31­–33 (1997) (describing the “Legal Process” conception of the rule of law); Margaret Jane Radin, Reconsidering the Rule of Law, 69 B.U. L. Rev. 781, 809 (1989) (“The point of ‘the Rule of Law, not of individuals’ is that the rules are supposed to rule . . . . [J]udges [are] . . . merely instrumental functionaries.”). ... Close Even if legislation is influenced by penal populism, everyday criminal adjudica­tion can at least abide by neutral, orderly processing, treating all defen­dants equally. In the world of plea bargaining, this means that the representa­tion of the public by prosecutors becomes especially impor­tant—though jurors may sometimes serve as public representatives in individual cases, 43 43 See Jeffrey Abramson, Four Models of Jury Democracy, 90 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 861, 861–73 (2015) (describing different conceptions of how jurors can serve as public representa­tives in criminal court). ... Close juries are rare indeed. 44 44 Cf. Lafler v. Cooper, 566 U.S. 156, 170 (2012) (“[C]riminal justice today is for the most part a system of pleas, not a system of trials.”). ... Close Prosecutorial offices can improve their representation by setting up systems that combine demo­cratic inputs and internal checks and balances. 45 45 See Gerard E. Lynch, Our Administrative System of Criminal Justice, 66 Fordham L. Rev. 2117, 2123–24 (1998) (describing and defending a vision of the American criminal justice system in which “the brief formal procedure in court obscures what can be an invisi­ble, but elaborate and lengthy process of adjudication of the defendant’s guilt” within the prosecutor’s office). For scholarly discussions of ways to improve the administra­tive ideal, see, e.g., Rachel E. Barkow, Administering Crime, 52 UCLA L. Rev. 715, 798–812 (2005) (emphasizing the importance of institutional design in sentencing commissions, and suggesting that commissions be placed “in the middle of the political thicket” to expose influential actors to the voices of reformers and give the commission notice of the political viability of its proposals); Rachel E. Barkow, Prosecutorial Administration: Prosecutor Bias and the Department of Justice, 99 Va. L. Rev. 271, 331–41 (2013) (recommend­ing structural changes within the Department of Justice to eliminate prose­cuto­rial bias); Shima Baradaran Baughman, Subconstitutional Checks, 92 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1071, 1121–38 (2017) (providing a “blueprint” for ways in which prosecuto­rial power can be checked by each of the three branches of government, including within the Executive Branch). ... Close However, once the prosecu­tor enters the courtroom, a neutral, untainted procedure deter­mines a defendant’s fate. Under this view of procedure, criminal proce­dure becomes a way to ensure neutral and equal processing of a case after partisan inputs into systemic priorities. Conversely, any unpredictable or extrajudicial discretionary moves become interference with the orderly processing of cases. 46 46 Rachel Barkow connects the focus on neutral processing and reviewable decision­mak­ing with the rise of the administrative state, which lead scholars and jurists alike to look down on jury nullification, clemency, and other exercises of mercy other than the prosecutorial decision not to prosecute. See Rachel E. Barkow, The Ascent of the Administrative State and the Demise of Mercy, 121 Harv. L. Rev. 1332, 1336–55 (2008). ... Close

Although this administrative ideal continues to hold sway, a growing number of scholars and policymakers recognize the decline in public input into everyday criminal adjudication as a problem, and even a demo­cratic crisis, and look to democratic processes as a potential answer to the system’s ills. 47 47 See, e.g., Bibas, Machinery of Criminal Justice, supra note 4, at 29–58 (describing contemporary criminal adjudication as “the machinery of criminal justice,” a lawyer-driven system of pleas without public participation); Richard A. Bierschbach, Fragmentation and Democracy in the Constitutional Law of Punishment, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1437, 1452 (2017) (arguing that “[p]ushing more criminal justice power . . . down to directly affected communi­ties and neighborhoods could enhance representativeness and sharpen lines of authority”); Barry Friedman & Maria Ponomarenko, Democratic Policing, 90 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1827, 1832–35, 1848 (2015) (advocating for increased democratic inputs into policing priorities); Andrew E. Taslitz, The Criminal Republic: Democratic Breakdown as a Cause of Mass Incarceration, 9 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 133, 164–73 (2011) (advocating for improving democratic criminal justice more broadly through participatory procedures). But see Dorothy Roberts, Democratizing Criminal Law as an Abolitionist Project, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1597, 1600 (2017) [hereinafter Roberts, Democratizing Criminal Law] (arguing that American systems of law enforcement are by their nature antidemocratic, so that demo­cratiz­ing criminal law requires looking beyond increasing public participation in criminal justice to considering abolition more broadly). For recent collections of essays on the themes of democracy and criminal justice, see Democratic Theory and Mass Incarceration (Albert W. Dzur et al. eds., 2016); Prosecutors and Democracy: A Cross-National Study, supra note 41; Kleinfeld, Manifesto, supra note 41, at 1370–72 (summariz­ing symposium essays on “Democratizing Criminal Justice”). ... Close Whether seen as a problem of legitimacy or representa­tion, responses from scholars and state actors alike have fea­tured calls to include the “community” in the bureaucracy of criminal justice in new and novel ways, including through community policing and community prosecution. These methods of seeking input range from stakeholder meetings, 48 48 See, e.g., Community Court Stakeholders Meeting Tonight, City of Madison Police Dep’t (Nov. 5, 2014), http://www.cityofmadison.com/police/south/blotter.cfm?Id=6178 [https://perma.cc/79N5-BG7W] (inviting the community to a stakeholder input meet­ing). ... Close to listening sessions, 49 49 See, e.g., Cmty. Oriented Policing Servs., U.S. Dep’t of Justice, Listening Session, http://sanfranciscopolice.org/sites/default/files/USJusticeInitiative/SanFrancisco_Community%20Listening%20Session%20Flyer_%20Mission(1).pdf [https://perma.cc/BN7N-SXW9] (last visited Mar. 28, 2017) (advertising an open forum intended to improve the San Francisco Police Department). ... Close to online notice-and-com­ment procedures. 50 50 See, e.g., N.Y. Police Dep’t, NYPD Body-Worn Camera Community Survey, https:// static1.squarespace.com/static/58a33e881b631bc60d4f8b31/t/59fb52eb6c31948dfdecbe88/1509642990544/NYPD-BWC+Paper+Questionnaire.pdf [https://perma.cc/65LE-VEPN] (last visited Oct. 9, 2018) (describing an online survey designed to solicit comments from New York City residents on the NYPD’s body camera program). ... Close The goal of much “community justice” becomes to make the representation better   : to fix the politics of electing prosecutors or the internal checks and balances within the executive branch. 51 51 See Todd R. Clear & David R. Karp, The Community Justice Ideal 25 (1999) (“[The] central focus [of community justice] is community-level outcomes, shifting the emphasis from individual incidents to systemic patterns . . . .”). ... Close These “community justice” approaches prioritize consensus, with the goal of getting the entire “community” in agreement about prosecu­torial or policing priorities at the systemic level. 52 52 See Sklansky, Democracy, supra note 27, at 66–105 (2008) (describing the pri­macy of seeking consensus in the context of participation and policing); Sklansky, Unpacking the Relationship, supra note 41, at 282–83, 288–89 (describing the connection between conceptions of participatory democracy that seek consensus and efforts to pro­mote community prosecution). ... Close Newer approaches to improving public participation also tend to focus on sys­temic inputs—on facilitating ongoing communication between institu­tional players and the local public. The notable exception is scholars who call for the creation of juries in which citizens make decisions at moments other than a verdict, including at a suppression hearing, bail hearing, plea, or sentencing. 53 53 See, e.g., Appleman, supra note 40, at 91 (calling for lay juries throughout the adjudication process); Josh Bowers, Upside-Down Juries, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1655, 1671–74 (2017) (calling for “normative” juries at multiple stages of adjudication); Joshua Kleinfeld et al., White Paper of Democratic Criminal Justice, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1693, 1697 (2017) (“Juries should be included in the criminal justice process whenever reasonably possible, including at the investigative, charging, trial, and sentencing phases of criminal procedure.”). For specific proposals, see Bibas, Machinery of Criminal Justice, supra note 4, at 69–70 (plea juries); Laura I. Appleman, Justice in the Shadowlands: Pretrial Detention, Punishment, & the Sixth Amendment, 69 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1297, 1363–66 (2012) (bail juries); Laura I. Appleman, The Plea Jury, 85 Ind. L.J. 731, 750–59 (2010) (plea juries); Rachel E. Barkow, Recharging the Jury: The Criminal Jury’s Constitutional Role in an Era of Mandatory Sentencing, 152 U. Pa. L. Rev. 33, 102–16 (2003) (calling for juries to make some sentencing determinations); Josh Bowers, The Normative Case for Normative Grand Juries, 47 Wake Forest L. Rev. 319, 343–49 (2012) (grand juries); Roger A. Fairfax, Jr., Grand Jury Innovation: Toward a Functional Makeover of the Ancient Bulwark of Liberty, 19 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 339, 354–58 (2010) (grand juries that review pleas and sentencings); Jenia Iontcheva, Jury Sentencing as Democratic Practice, 89 Va. L. Rev. 311, 312–16 (2003) (sentencing juries ); Adriaan Lanni, The Future of Community Justice, 40 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 359, 394–99 (2005) (grand and petit juries that review charging, sentencing, and policymaking decisions); Jason Mazzone, The Waiver Paradox, 97 Nw. U. L. Rev. 801, 872–78 (2003) (“plea panels”); Meghan J. Ryan, Juries and the Criminal Constitution, 65 Ala. L. Rev. 849, 851–56 (2014) (proposing that juries make findings regarding constitutional questions in criminal cases). And, in a different vein, R.A. Duff and Russell Gold have each proposed on-the-record procedures that would require prosecutors to account for the impact of their choices on the public. See Antony Duff, Discretion and Accountability in a Democratic Criminal Law, in Prosecutors and Democracy: A Cross-National Study, supra note 41, at 9, 9–40 (proposing a new procedure in which prosecutors are called to account for the effects of their actions on the public); Russell M. Gold, “Clientless” Prosecutors, 51 Ga. L. Rev. 693, 733–35 (2017) [hereinafter Gold, Clientless Prosecutors] (proposing that courts appoint amici in individual criminal cases to represent the public). ... Close

But there is another way to approach public participation in the crimi­nal system. In contrast to the community-justice focus on building consensus stands a different ideal of public participation: one that pro­motes agonism rather than consensus as the ideal mode of engage­ment by members of the public. 54 54 See Simonson, Copwatching, supra note 25, at 435–37 (arguing for agonism as a mode of change through contestation that engages with formal democratic processes); Simonson, Democratizing Criminal Justice, supra note 25, at 1612–13 (arguing that bot­tom-up forms of participation in criminal justice are “crucial for democratic criminal jus­tice” and that such forms of “contestation are not antagonistic, but agonistic”). ... Close An agonistic stance toward public participa­tion in criminal legal institutions would allow groups to partici­pate in the processes of those institutions while still remaining opposed to the dominant priorities of the state actors in charge of them. 55 55 See Mouffe, Agonistics, supra note 25, at 8–9 (describing agonism as a “real confronta­tion [among groups with ideas in opposition to each other], but one that is played out under conditions regulated by a set of democratic procedures accepted by adver­saries”). ... Close If we can open up our institutions to the flow of agonistic contestation, we might arrive at a more nuanced account of what is in the best interests of “the People.” 56 56 Cf. Philip Goodman et al., Breaking the Pendulum: The Long Struggle over Criminal Justice 3, 123–40 (2017) (arguing that the fight over criminal justice in the United States has long been an agonistic one, in which “actors . . . with varying resources and differing visions of how to prevent and sanction crime continually contest punish­ment”); Marie Gottschalk, Caught: The Prison State and the Lockdown of American Politics 282 (2015) (calling for “convulsive politics from below that we need to dismantle the carceral state and ameliorate other gaping inequalities”); Lerman & Weaver, supra note 16, at 236, 236–60 (recommending policy changes to better include those who have contact with the criminal justice system in democratic processes so as to “walk back the substantial damage that the [criminal justice] system has done to democracy over the past fifty years”); Amna A. Akbar, Toward a Radical Imagination of Law, 93 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 405, 408–10 (2018) [hereinafter Akbar, Radical Imagination] (describing the importance of the critiques created by marginalized groups and emergent social movements); Allegra M. McLeod, Beyond the Carceral State, 95 Tex. L. Rev. 651, 657 (2017) (book review) [hereinaf­ter McLeod, Carceral State] (calling for a “broader public reckoning with our carceral state—informed by the critical insights of impacted communities and experts”). ... Close In order to do so productively, such paths of critique must include and even prioritize the voices of those marginalized populations who are most directly impacted by criminal procedural practices. For it is the peo­ple at the bottom of the “penal pyramid”—defendants, victims, and their families, friends, and neighbors who come from under-resourced neighbor­hoods 57 57 See Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid, supra note 29, at 75–90. ... Close —who are least likely to have the political power neces­sary to voice critiques of the system. 58 58 See Lerman & Weaver, supra note 16, at 139–56 (describing how interacting with the criminal process affects political engagement); Stuntz, Collapse of American Criminal Justice, supra note 16, at 255 (noting that “voters with the largest stake [in the process of building and filling prisons]—chiefly African American residents of high-crime city neighbor­hoods—had the smallest voice in the relevant decisions”); Monica C. Bell, Police Reform and the Dismantling of Legal Estrangement, 126 Yale L.J. 2054, 2067 (2017) (“[A]t both an interactional and structural level, current regimes can operate to effectively banish whole communities from the body politic.”); Capers, Good Citizen, supra note 25, at 654–57 (describ­ing how constitutional criminal procedure doctrine constitutes exclu­sionary mean­ings of who is a “good citizen”); Benjamin Justice & Tracey L. Meares, How the Crimi­nal Justice System Educates Citizens, 651 Annals Am. Acad. Pol. & Soc. Sci. 159, 161–73 (2014) (describing how the criminal justice system educates individuals in “anticiti­zenry”); Natapoff, Speechless, supra note 24, at 1452 (arguing that the silencing of defen­dants inside the courtroom is part of the “expressive disempowerment of those disadvan­taged groups who tend to become defendants”); Roberts, Constructing a Criminal Justice System, supra note 24, at 279–85 (describing the criminal justice system’s “anti-democratic function”). ... Close It is therefore especially important to pay attention to existing agonistic forms of public participation in the very place where people excluded from the political process interact with institutional players every day: the criminal courthouse. As the next sec­tion demonstrates, while debates over the ideology of criminal procedure and the ideal nature of public partici­pation in criminal adjudication take place, individuals at the bottom of the “penal pyramid” are taking public participation into their own hands by intervening collectively in individ­ual criminal cases. In doing so, they demonstrate how agonistic contestation can play out in everyday justice.

C. Communal Participation from Below

Bottom-up agonistic participation in individual criminal cases plays out in criminal courthouses every day, in phenomena as varied as commu­nity bail funds, courtwatching, and participatory defense. The tactic of community bail funds exemplifies this dynamic. With a commu­nity bail fund, groups come together to post bail for strangers and assert a communal interest in a defendant’s freedom, in contrast to the assumed communal interest in pretrial detention. 59 59 See Jocelyn Simonson, Bail Nullification, 115 Mich. L. Rev. 585, 599–611 (2017) [hereinafter Simonson, Bail Nullification] (discussing the rise of community bail funds); Pilar Weiss, Reflections on Year One of the National Bail Fund Network (2017) (on file with the Columbia Law Review ) (reviewing the history of community bail funds as well as lessons gleaned from the National Bail Fund Network’s coordination of new bail funds). ... Close Bail funds deliber­ately connect the fate of individual defendants with the fate of neighbor­hoods and communities, linking these relationships to larger visions of the (in)justice caused by seemingly neutral procedures. Bail funds express love and support for strangers—they are not on the side of defen­dants as friends or even acquaintances, but rather as members of a larger social movement in support of decarceration and reinvestment in poor communities of color. 60 60 Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 612–21. ... Close Community bail funds now exist in at least twenty-one states throughout the United States. 61 61 See National Bail Fund Network: Directory of Community Bail Funds, Brooklyn Cmty. Bail Fund, https://brooklynbailfund.org/nbfn-directory [https://perma.cc/R3AU-T5XY] (last visited Sept. 12, 2018) (listing thirty-two active local community bail funds across twenty-one states, as well as one national fund and a number of immigration bail or bond funds). ... Close Through the recurring, performative act of posting bail, these movement actors build power and shift dominant ideas about the legal meaning of “community” in every­day pretrial procedures, resulting in tangible political and legal change. 62 62 See Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 621–31 (describing how com­mu­nity bail funds have led to the reform of bail laws in New York state and have chal­lenged the assumptions underlying constitutional jurisprudence on bail). ... Close

Community bail funds, however, are often met with resistance from court clerks and other courthouse and jailhouse actors 63 63 See id. at 608–10 (describing judicial resistance to bail funds in New York City); Sells, supra note 20 (describing an advocacy group’s abandonment of efforts to set up a bail fund program after unnecessary delays by the county court clerk); Demond Fernandez, Group Working to Post Bail for Inmates Runs into Problems at Dallas Co. Jail, WFAA (Aug. 24, 2018), https://www.wfaa.com/article/news/group-working-to-post-bail-for-inmates-runs-into-problems-at-dallas-co-jail/287-587438482 [https://perma.cc/24FB-Y3T9] (recounting Community Bail Fund of North Texas’s complaints that court clerks gave the group the “run-around” when they attempted to post bail). ... Close —especially when they bail out large numbers of people in a short period of time. In May 2017, for example, nearly two dozen local organizations coordinated together to bail out more than 100 women and caregivers for Mother’s Day. 64 64 Jasmine Sanders, ‘If We Let Everybody Go, There’d Be Nobody in Prison’, N.Y. Times (May 13, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/05/13/style/mothers-day-bail-out.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review ); Jocelyn Simonson, Opinion, Bail Keeps These Moms in Jail on Mother’s Day. So Strangers Are Posting It for Them., Wash. Post (May 12, 2017), https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/bail-keeps-these-moms-in-jail-on-mothers-day-so-strangers-are-posting-it-for-them/2017/05/12/04524d7e-3678-11e7-b373-418f6849a004_story.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review ). ... Close In the words of Mary Hooks, codirector of Southerners on New Ground (SONG), who helped conceive, coordinate, and implement this mass action, this “Mama’s Bail Out Day” was a form of “abolition in the now” that brings both freedom to individuals and attention to “the slow deaths of our families and communities.” 65 65 Melissa Gira Grant, Abolition in the Now , Pac. Standard (May 10, 2017), https://psmag.com/social-justice/home-for-mothers-day [https://perma.cc/BS2F-9PCX]. ... Close Some local organizations involved in the effort, however, encountered resistance when they attempted to bail out more than one person for Mama’s Bail Out Day, finding that clerks, lawyers, wardens, and other corrections officials were “obstructionist to the farthest extent possible.” 66 66 See, e.g., A Labor of Love: Black Mama’s Bail Out Action + Reflection, Southerners on New Ground (May 16, 2017), http://southernersonnewground.org/2017/05/a-labor-of-love/ [https://perma.cc/W7MY-CHMU] (“Wardens, jailers, public defenders, and solicitors were in SOME sites . . . helpful, supportive and even bent and changed rules to help us. But in other places, they were completely obstructionist to the farthest extent possible.”). ... Close This on-the-ground resistance from state actors demonstrates the ways in which the system bristles when social-movement interventions disrupt the status quo, even when they do so via formally established procedures such as the posting of bail. 67 67 Local governments have sometimes embraced bail funds, for example in New York City, St. Louis, and Connecticut, all of which have proposed or implemented state- or city-funded bail funds. But these efforts, in shifting to a model of representation, have watered down both the participatory potential and the impact of the bail fund model. See Jocelyn Simonson, When the City Posts Bail 13–16 (July 2016) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with the Columbia Law Review ) [hereinafter Simonson, When the City Posts Bail]. ... Close Although state actors are accustomed to family members of defen­dants expressing support by posting bail, they resist the idea that a community group might support a defendant even though members of the group do not know him or her personally.

Community groups also use the procedural interventions known as “par­ticipatory defense” to intercede directly on behalf of defendants. With participatory defense, community groups join together with fami­lies, friends, neighbors, and allies of defendants to learn about the facts and procedures of individual cases, perform investigations, present biograph­ical videos to prosecutors and judges, and pack courtrooms in support of defendants. 68 68 See Janet Moore et al., Make Them Hear You: Participatory Defense and the Struggle for Criminal Justice Reform, 78 Alb. L. Rev. 1281, 1285–86 (2015) (describing the participatory defense movement and its power); Liana Pennington, An Empirical Study of One Participatory Defense Program Facilitated by a Public Defender Office, 14 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 603, 606–10 (2017) (documenting the recent growth of the participatory defense movement). ... Close Participatory defense hubs operate in at least eighteen jurisdictions throughout the United States. 69 69 ACJPDEBUG, Participatory Defense Launches in Philadelphia, Albert Cobarrubias Just. Project (Dec. 12, 2017), https://acjusticeproject.org/2017/12/12/participatory-defense-launches-in-philadelphia/ [https://perma.cc/GM2Q-ACQ5] (stating that, with the launch of the Philadelphia participa­tory defense project in 2017, there are now eighteen participatory defense sites in the National Network for Participatory Defense). ... Close At every step, they aim to connect the stories of individual defendants to larger systemic injus­tices, exposing the everyday violence of policing, prosecution, and incarceration. 70 70 Cf. Cover, Violence, supra note 22, at 1608 (connecting a recognition of the vio­lence of the law with a respect for the experience of defendants and prisoners). ... Close Although the goal of participatory defense at any one moment might be to help free an individual defendant, ultimately the aim of the practice is nothing less than an end to mass incarceration through “chang[ing] the landscape of power . . . in the criminal justice system.” 71 71 See Robin Yeamans, Fighting for Justice by Court Watching , People’s Trib., http://www.peoplestribune.org/PT.2012.05/PT.2012.05.11.shtml [https://perma.cc/52N3-NZ5D] (last visited Oct. 5, 2018). ... Close This means that a participatory defense group attending a “jus­tice hub meeting” will applaud and congratulate a teenager recently released from custody, even though they have never met him before; 72 72 Moore et al., supra note 68, at 1283–84. ... Close and a campaign to free an incarcerated black woman will work not only to humanize that particular woman but also “to challenge false and damaging binaries that we use to describe incarcerated people, like vio­lent/non-violent and innocent/guilty.” 73 73 Kaba, Free Us All, supra note 10. ... Close Although participatory defense campaigns may cooperate with public defenders or defense attorneys, lawyers are never the center of any one effort. 74 74 Moore et al., supra note 68, at 1283. ... Close Instead, the wisdom and energy of marginalized groups who do not ordinarily have a say in the justice process are centered in collective efforts to support defendants, shift power, and create new visions of community. 75 75 Id. ... Close But, like community bail funds, the tactics that make up participatory defense have met obsta­cles, both formal and cultural, at every step. 76 76 See Cynthia Godsoe, Participatory Defense: Humanizing the Accused and Ceding Control to the Client, 69 Mercer L. Rev. 715, 716–18 (2018) (describing the history of public defender resistance to participatory defense but noting that this is changing as the practice becomes more established). ... Close

Collective forms of intervention in everyday adjudication also hap­pen through observation inside the courtroom. Some community groups participate in efforts at courtwatching, not to support an individual defen­­dant but rather to voice opposition to larger prosecutorial policies and practices, or to collect information so as to hold prosecutors accounta­ble. 77 77 See generally Bryce Covert, The Court Watch Movement Wants to Expose the “House of Cards,” Appeal (July 16, 2018), https://theappeal.org/court-watch-accountability-movement/ [https://perma.cc/RJ9E-Z5VJ] (describing the recent rise of “mission-driven court watch”). ... Close Courtwatching groups affiliated with larger social move­ments, for example, gather volunteers to document everyday proceed­ings in local courts—bond hearings, arraignments, pleas—and report to the public the results of their observations. These community groups become self-appointed watchdogs who can present the results of their observations in their own words, on their own terms, and independent of official accounts of policies. 78 78 For examples of this at work, see, e.g., id.; 8 Week Court Watching Project!!, Cmty. Renewal Soc’y, http://www.communityrenewalsociety.org/calendar/8-week-court-watching-project [https://perma.cc/9MEF-LKMQ] (last visited Feb. 15, 2017). ... Close Courtwatchers not only hold courtroom actors accountable, they also shift the power dynamics within the court­room, reminding institutional players of the larger public dimensions of individual cases. 79 79 See Judith Resnik & Dennis Curtis, Representing Justice: Invention, Controversy, and Rights in City-States and Democratic Courtrooms 300–02 (2011) (describing how audience members in courtrooms help define the meaning of proceedings); Jocelyn Simonson, The Criminal Court Audience in a Post-Trial World, 127 Harv. L. Rev. 2173, 2184–90 (2014) [hereinafter Simonson, Audience] (describing the power shifts that occur through the act of observation inside a courtroom); Covert, supra note 77 (quoting a Court Watch NYC activist and describing the purpose of courtwatching as, in part, “shift­ing power”). ... Close

Activists engaging with criminal adjudication through participatory defense, community bail funds, courtwatching, or any number of other collective interventions into everyday justice see themselves as trying to move the criminal legal system toward something that is more responsive to the local communities it claims to serve . The exploration of the ideol­ogy of criminal procedure in this Essay is indebted to the work of these contemporary movement activists to shift the discourse surrounding the interactions of power, structure, and community in criminal law and policy reform. 80 80 Cf. Amna A. Akbar, Law’s Exposure: The Movement and the Legal Academy, 65 J. Legal Educ. 352, 355–56 (2015) (describing the importance of studying the visions and critiques created by marginalized groups and emergent social movements); Janet Moore, Decarceral Constitutionalism 39–43 (unpublished manuscript) (on file with the Columbia Law Review ) [hereinafter Moore, Decarceral Constitutionalism] (arguing that we should bring grassroots interventions in criminal justice into our analyses of popular constitutional­ism). ... Close In the remainder of this Essay, I examine the facets of our ideology of criminal procedure that cause the system to resist these bottom-up interventions into everyday criminal adjudication. In the next Part, I attempt to set out what I see as the reigning ideology of procedure with respect to popular participation: that the general public belongs on the side of the police and the prosecution, and not on the side of defen­dants. This ideology facilitates the resistance of state actors to forms of agonistic participation with the greatest potential to shift the status quo in criminal adjudication.

II. The People/Defendant Dichotomy in Criminal Procedure

In our dominant contemporary conception of criminal procedure, the place of the public—“the People”—is on the side of the police and the prosecution, in an act of communal condemnation. From there, the familiar approach to crafting criminal procedure depends on the idea that police officers and prosecutors, or “the People,” should act and speak as representatives of the local community. This ideal of communal representation, in turn, dictates how we approach procedural innova­tions. If the ideal of representation is undermined—if the state is not ade­quately channeling popular will—then procedures can shift to seek out ways of gathering input to make police and prosecutors more respon­sive to the community. This is the heart of many contemporary criminal adjudication reforms that seek to craft new procedures in the name of “community justice.” At the same time, each defendant is in need of protec­tion in the face of the communal suspicion that state actors person­ify. If the defendant does not have adequate protections against state power, the answer is to strengthen individual procedural protections through individual rights and resources. On each side, our channels of remedying injustices in the system strengthen the dichotomy between “the People” and the person whom the people suspect of wrongdoing. In this Part, I lay out the basic contours of this ideology and argue that it carries with it a distinct set of problems: one, an undue focus on prosecu­tors as representatives of the public will; and two, an illusory conception of a “neutral” public that is both disinterested and decorous. Taken together, the ideology of the people/defendant dichotomy serves to exclude marginalized populations from paths of participation in criminal procedure and legitimize overly punitive outcomes in individual cases.

A. The People v. the Defendant: Mapping the Dichotomy

Dominant conceptions of the criminal process largely presuppose a clean separation between the interests of the public and the interests of the defendant, which are assumed to be in direct opposition to each other. The people/defendant dichotomy is especially pronounced in the realm of adjudication, after a prosecutor decides to file charges, thereby designating a member of the public a “defendant.” This dichotomy plays out at multiple levels: in prosecutorial identity as representing “the People,” in the constitutional jurisprudence of individual procedural rights, and in the policies and cultures of local courthouses. And the dichot­omy is echoed in much of the scholarship that examines ideology and criminal procedure: Herbert Packer, for example, assumed an adversar­ial system in which the defendant stands alone, with only defense counsel and formal rules and requirements to help her along the way. 81 81 See supra notes 27–31 and accompanying text (describing this aspect of Packer’s ideas); see also Stuart A. Scheingold, The Politics of Street Crime 26–27 (1991) (arguing that both of Packer’s models center on the treatment of an individual and therefore direct attention “toward the fate of formally anonymous defendants and away from their broader social identities and circumstances”); Roach, supra note 29, at 672 (arguing that Packer’s models do not account for the different ways in which victims can intervene in the process). ... Close As John Griffiths explained in his critique of Packer nearly fifty years ago, this assumption continually sets things up as a battle, a “stylized war” between “the Individual (particularly the accused individual) and the State.” 82 82 Griffiths, supra note 29, at 367. ... Close On one side of the battle is a lone defendant, and on the other are “the People.” 83 83 This idealized battle certainly predated Herbert Packer, emerging as early as the nineteenth century. See Herman W. Chaplin, Reform in Criminal Procedure, 7 Harv. L. Rev. 189, 199–200 (1893) (describing a shift in the late nineteenth century toward an idea of a prosecution as “the contest . . . between the public and the accused”). Notably, Chaplin identified this as a problem: “We ought now to be ready for the theory that a crimi­nal prosecution is not a contest at all, but an investigation, conducted by the State, before a tribunal of its own appointment . . . .” Id. at 199. Thanks to Alice Ristroph for pointing me to Chaplin’s work. ... Close This theme recurs throughout the practices, rules, and jurisprudence structuring criminal procedure: The debate is over how to structure this battle between “the People,” represented by a prosecu­tor, and the defendant, rather than about whether the battle lines should be drawn in those ways at all. 84 84 One important exception to this trend is the theory and practices of restorative justice, which often try to bridge the gap between the defendant and the community by bringing the two into conversation. Even there, however, the defendant is assumed to have done wrong and prosecution is assumed to be the right approach. See generally John Braithwaite, Crime, Shame and Reintegration (1989) (laying out a comprehensive theory of restorative justice). ... Close

When the public is situated as a force opposed to the defendant, prose­cutors become the central representatives of the public in the court­house. Prosecutors are “ministers of justice,” 85 85 Lissa Griffin & Ellen Yaroshefsky, Ministers of Justice and Mass Incarceration, 30 Geo. J. Legal Ethics 301, 304 (2017) (“[I]t is well accepted that the prosecutor is a fidu­ciary who represents the sovereign and must make decisions for society at large . . . .”); see also Kate Levine, Who Shouldn’t Prosecute the Police, 101 Iowa L. Rev. 1447, 1451–53 (2016) [hereinafter Levine, Prosecuting Police] (“[P]rosecutors have the well-known duty to ‘seek justice’ . . . .” (quoting Standards for Criminal Justice § 3-1.1(c) (Am. Bar Ass’n 1986))). ... Close representing the sover­eign and its citizens, and must act in the interests of their client, the state. 86 86 Griffin & Yaroshefsky, supra note 85, at 311–15; see also Bruce A. Green, Why Should Prosecutors “Seek Justice”? , 26 Fordham Urb. L.J. 607, 634–37 (1999) (arguing that the best justification for the prosecutorial duty to seek justice is representing the sover­eign’s interest in “ensuring fairness of the process”). ... Close This aspect of the prosecutorial identity—as a servant of the public—is but one of the multifaceted identities that prosecutors possess; 87 87 One recent study of state prosecutors from nine different offices identified four principal career motivations for working state prosecutors: “reinforcing one’s core absolut­ist identity, gaining trial skills, performing a valuable public service, and sustaining a work-life balance.” See Ronald F. Wright & Kay L. Levine, Getting Beyond Superheroes Versus Trojan Horses: Career Motivations of State Court Prosecutors 4–5 (Aug. 17, 2017) (unpub­lished manuscript), https://ssrn.com/abstract=3021429 (on file with the Columbia Law Review ); see also Maximo Langer & David Alan Sklansky, Epilogue: Prosecutors and Democracy—Themes and Counterthemes, in Prosecutors and Democracy: A Cross-National Study, supra note 41, at 300, 302–08 (describing “prosecutors as agents of the popular will” as one of four main conceptions of the relationship between prosecutors and democracy). But even the demand of “neutrality” and obedience to the rule of law is guided by the wishes of the public. For instance, Bruce Green & Fred Zacharias have argued that the concept of prosecutorial neutrality is best described by the idea that “prosecu­tors should make decisions based on articulable principles or subprinciples that command broad societal acceptance.” Bruce A. Green & Fred C. Zacharias, Prosecutorial Neutrality, 2004 Wis. L. Rev. 837, 840. ... Close and the prosecutor’s duty to the public does not supplant her duty to the rule of law or even to an independent sense of justice. 88 88 See David Alan Sklansky, The Nature and Function of Prosecutorial Power, 106 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 473, 519 (2016) (describing how prosecutors must mediate between “democratic responsiveness” on the one hand and “detached objectivity” on the other). And, moreover, once the decision to prosecute has been made, the goal is to win the case via a plea or a guilty verdict at trial. See John Langbein, The Origins of Adversary Criminal Trial 332–34 (2003) (describing how during the ascendance of the adversary criminal trial, prosecutors became “partisans whose interest is in winning, not in truth”). ... Close But implicit in the prosecutorial identity as a public servant is the idea that they are the institutional actors who channel the will of the people into adjudication. This is how prosecutors are able to call themselves “the People” in many states. Although judges and even public defenders are sometimes elected, 89 89 See generally David E. Pozen, The Irony of Judicial Elections, 108 Colum. L. Rev. 265 (2008) (arguing that a rise in the legitimacy of judicial elections undermines the distinc­tive role of the judiciary); Ronald F. Wright, Public Defender Elections and Popular Control over Criminal Justice , 75 Mo. L. Rev. 803 (2010) (describing the three states that hold elections for public defenders). ... Close it is the prosecutors who represent the people. Not only that, they represent the community, in the sense of a local public with common concerns; they speak for us all. 90 90 See Michelle Madden Dempsey, Prosecuting Domestic Violence 48–52 (2009) (describing the difference between the prosecutorial claim to act on behalf of the state and the prosecutorial claim to act on behalf of the community). I return to this distinction in Part III. ... Close This leaves the other side—the defendant—as a solitary individual in need of the support of counsel and the protection of the Constitution. 91 91 See Paul D. Butler, Poor People Lose: Gideon and the Critique of Rights, 122 Yale L.J. 2176, 2195–96 (2013) [hereinafter Butler, Poor People Lose] (critiquing the “isolated individualism” of Gideon and the right to counsel); David Alan Sklansky, Autonomy and Agency in American Criminal Process 1 (Stanford Pub. Law Working Paper No. 2849226, 2016) [hereinafter Sklansky, Autonomy], https://ssrn.com/abstract=2849226 (on file with the Columbia Law Review ) (describing the assumption underlying American criminal proce­dure that “fairness is best advanced through a series of procedural rights that defen­dants can invoke or waive at their discretion”). ... Close

I do not mean to minimize the importance of the criminal jury as an insti­tution of public participation and representation. In the tiny subset of cases in which juries adjudicate guilt and innocence after a full-blown trial, 92 92 See Suja A. Thomas, What Happened to the American Jury? Proposals for Revamping Plea Bargaining and Summary Judgment, Litig., Spring 2017, at 25, 25 (“[J]uries today decide only 1–4 percent of criminal cases filed in federal and state court.”). ... Close members of the public do indeed have important roles as citizens and judges. 93 93 See generally Jeffrey Abramson, We, the Jury: The Jury System and the Ideal of Democracy 1–13 (1994) (“No other institution of government rivals the jury in placing power so directly in the hands of citizens.”); Harry Kalven, Jr. & Hans Zeisel, The American Jury 3–11 (Univ. of Chi. Press 1971) (1966) (“The jury . . . represents a deep commitment to the use of laymen in the administration of justice . . . .”). ... Close This is the top of the “penal pyramid,” where cases are either adjudicated before juries or plea bargains genuinely happen in the shadow of potential jury decisions. 94 94 See Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid, supra note 29, at 71–82. ... Close But this is not the reality for the vast majority of cases in criminal court, for which “[t]rials are nearly extinct and their shadows weak.” 95 95 Id. at 78; see also Stephanos Bibas, Plea Bargaining Outside the Shadow of Trial , 117 Harv. L. Rev. 2464, 2466–68 (2004) (questioning the impact of the “shadows of trial” on plea bargaining outcomes). ... Close Given this post-trial landscape, our contempo­rary ideology of criminal adjudication has internalized the reality that we have a “system of pleas, not a system of trials,” 96 96 Lafler v. Cooper, 566 U.S. 156, 170 (2012). ... Close such that prosecutors are able to assume their place as public representatives seeking justice on behalf of “the People.” Moreover, even when juries do deliberate and decide the fate of individual defendants, we select individual jurors amid an illusory ideal of neutrality that leans toward the exclusion of members of the public who might side with the interests of the defendant. 97 97 See infra notes 145–151 and accompanying text. ... Close

The dichotomy between “the People” and the defendant is echoed in constitutional jurisprudence as well. The emphasis on individual rights of defendants inside the courtroom is based, at its heart, on the classifica­tion of a lone defendant faced with communal suspicion. The reigning assumption is that protecting individual autonomy through constitu­tional rights and procedures can in turn protect fairness. 98 98 See Sklansky, Autonomy, supra note 91, at 1 (showing how these ideas are reflected in rules of waiver and effective assistance of counsel); Robert E. Toone, The Incoherence of Defendant Autonomy, 83 N.C. L. Rev. 621, 623–40 (2005) (arguing that the reliance on defendant autonomy in constitutional criminal procedure is incoherent and harmful); cf. Dolovich, supra note 27, at 264–65 (“The sustaining discourse of this penal system is a radically individualist one that locates the causes of crime exclusively in the free and conscious choice of the offenders themselves.”). ... Close On the one hand, protection of an autonomous defendant is said to reinforce fair­ness and due process, and on the other hand, the public is assumed to be a force of condemnation pushing against this autonomous defendant. This leads to a constitutional jurisprudence that assumes that the weight of the public interest is on the side of the prosecution. For example, in the leading Supreme Court case on pretrial detention, United States v. Salerno , the Court explicitly describes a defendant’s interest in liberty and the community’s interest in safety as two sides of a scale of justice that a judge must weigh against each other. 99 99 481 U.S. 739, 750 (1987) (“On the other side of the scale, of course, is the individ­ual’s strong interest in liberty.”). ... Close This theme recurs throughout constitutional criminal procedure, from the Sixth Amendment right to counsel, 100 100 Morris v. Slappy, 461 U.S. 1, 25 (1983) (Brennan, J., concurring) (“[T]he trial judge has an obligation to . . . balance the defendant’s interest against the public’s interest in the efficient and expeditious administration of criminal justice.”). ... Close to the Fifth Amendment right to not be subject to double jeop­ardy, 101 101 Oregon v. Kennedy, 456 U.S. 667, 672 (1982) (contrasting the “defendant’s inter­ests” with “the public’s interest in fair trials” (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Wade v. Hunter, 336 U.S. 684, 689 (1949))). ... Close to the Fourth Amendment protection against unreasonable seizure. 102 102 Tennessee v. Garner, 471 U.S. 1, 23 (1985) (O’Connor, J., dissenting) (describing the Court’s “balancing of the interests of the suspect and the public interest in effective law enforcement”). ... Close

The assumption that the public’s interest and the defendant’s inter­est are in direct opposition to each other in turn affects a central calculus that courts must often make in constitutional criminal procedure: a balanc­ing test between the prosecution’s interest in community safety (representing the interest of the public) and the defendant’s individual liberty interest (representing one lone defendant). 103 103 See Salerno , 481 U.S. at 750; see also T. Alexander Aleinikoff, Constitutional Law in the Age of Balancing, 96 Yale L.J. 943, 981 (1987) (describing how “[b]alancing opin­ions typically pit individual against governmental interests”); Shima Baradaran, Rebalancing the Fourth Amendment, 102 Geo. L.J. 1, 15–17 (2013) (describing a range of constitu­tional criminal doctrines in which courts balance the interests of the government in public safety against the interests of the defendant). ... Close When the interests of the community are assumed to be on the side of the prosecution, the court’s calculation of costs and benefits fails to include the interests of the community that align with defendants. There is no recognition, for example, that members of a community might have an interest in the defendant’s liberty or share the defendant’s understanding of what a fair trial entails; 104 104 For accounts of the harms to the public of pretrial detention, see Shima Baradaran Baughman, Costs of Pretrial Detention, 97 B.U. L. Rev. 1, 5–7 (2017) [hereinaf­ter Baughman, Pretrial Detention] (describing the social and communal harms of pretrial detention); Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 599–612 (describing how commu­nity bail funds demonstrate that incarcerating defendants before trial harms their families, neighborhoods, and communities); Crystal S. Yang, Toward an Optimal Bail System, 92 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1399, 1423–29 (2017) (describing harms to the public of pretrial detention). ... Close instead, the weight of the entire community is against the interests of the defendant. This skews the results of constitutional balanc­ing tests in favor of the prosecution. 105 105 See, e.g., Baradaran, supra note 103, at 14–19 (discussing these skewed results in the context of the Fourth Amendment balancing test). ... Close

To be sure, constitutional jurisprudence recognizes that enforcing some rights can benefit both a defendant and other members of the pub­lic. For example, enforcing the exclusionary rule for violations of the Fourth or Fifth Amendments in individual cases can deter police miscon­duct in other instances, 106 106 See id. at 15–17; Daniel J. Meltzer, Deterring Constitutional Violations by Law Enforcement Officials: Plaintiffs and Defendants as Private Attorneys General, 88 Colum. L. Rev. 247, 267–74 (1988) (“The fourth amendment’s exclusionary rule . . . serves only to deter the police from engaging in illegal searches in the future and thereby from violating the rights of others . . . .”); William J. Stuntz, Waiving Rights in Criminal Procedure, 75 Va. L. Rev. 761, 779–83 (1989) [hereinafter Stuntz, Waiving Rights] (describing when individ­ual rights in criminal procedure serve larger interests). ... Close and prohibiting the exclusion of jurors because of race or gender benefits potential jurors in addition to defen­dants. 107 107 See Batson v. Kentucky, 476 U.S. 79, 87 (1986) (“The harm from discriminatory jury selection extends beyond that inflicted on the defendant and the excluded juror to touch the entire community.”). ... Close The idea that one defendant may act as a kind of “private attor­ney general” in a suppression hearing squarely recognizes that the public and the defendant have shared interests in constitutional police con­duct. 108 108 See Meltzer, supra note 106, at 249 (describing how a defendant can function as a “private attorney general” when seeking suppression of evidence because she deters govern­ment misconduct on behalf of the public). ... Close The Fourth Amendment, in particular, explicitly protects “the people” rather than a single “person” or “accused” as in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments. 109 109 See United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259, 264–66 (1990) (declaring the significance of this distinction). ... Close The Supreme Court has stressed the significance of this distinction, which implies a common interest between all “the peo­ple,” including defendants, in protection from unnecessary state interference. 110 110 See id. But see District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 625–26 (2008) (limit­ing the operative meaning of “the People” to “law-abiding citizens”); see also Pratheepan Gulasekaram, “The People” of the Second Amendment: Citizenship and the Right to Bear Arms, 85 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1521, 1530–31 (2010) (discussing the implications of Heller ’s defi­nition of “the People”); Note, The Meaning(s) of “the People” in the Constitution, 126 Harv. L. Rev. 1078, 1078–86 (2013) (describing the conflict between inclusive and exclusive notions of “the People” in Verdugo-Urquidez and Heller ). ... Close

But while this strand of Fourth Amendment jurisprudence does indeed imply that defendants are part of a broader “people,” a “national community,” 111 111 Verdugo-Urquidez , 494 U.S. at 265. ... Close the context of adjudicatory procedure does not support the inverse idea, that the “people” support the defendant. In the court­room context—a suppression hearing for a Fourth or Fifth Amendment violation—the idea is that a defendant may help the larger public of peo­ple similarly situated, not that the national community stands on the side of the defendant. 112 112 Cf. Meltzer, supra note 106, at 280–81 (describing a suppression hearing as an “assertion of the rights of others”). ... Close Or, as Bill Stuntz describes it, the exclusionary rem­edy exists as “protection extended to the guilty primarily as a means of protecting the innocent.” 113 113 Stuntz, Waiving Rights, supra note 106, at 766. ... Close The public’s interest is not in the freedom of the defendant but in the constitutional treatment of other “law-abiding” members of the public. 114 114 Cf. Heller , 554 U.S. at 625. ... Close Indeed, the doctrines structuring interactions between the police and the public themselves construct a separation between “good” and “bad” members of the public. 115 115 See Paul Butler, The System Is Working the Way It Is Supposed to: The Limits of Criminal Justice Reform, 104 Geo. L.J. 1419, 1447 (2016) (“[T]he Supreme Court ha[s] established a set of police practices that, in theory, apply to everyone, but are principally directed against black men.”); Capers, Good Citizen, supra note 25, at 654–57 (detailing how the “good citizen” is one who is willing to cooperate with the police, at times willingly waiving his rights); Devon W. Carbado, (E)racing the Fourth Amendment, 100 Mich. L. Rev. 946, 1006–11 (2002) [hereinafter Carbado, Fourth Amendment] (critiquing a racial­ized concept of innocence in Fourth Amendment doctrine). ... Close The peo­ple/defendant dichotomy remains.

Even the constitutional doctrines that would seem to provide a place for public input beyond the prosecution—the jury-trial right and the right to a public trial—tend to reinforce the sense that the appropriate community input in adjudication is that which stands with the prosecu­tion, or at least is not “biased” against the prosecution. Although the Sixth Amendment guarantees that a jury be drawn from a fair cross-sec­tion of the local community, in practice the demand for neutral and disinter­ested jurors weeds out many jurors who might tend to side with defendants. For example, we comfortably exclude from juries not only potential jurors with criminal convictions 116 116 See Kalt, supra note 21, at 67 (describing how the majority of states and the fed­eral government exclude individuals with felony records from jury service); see also Anna Roberts, Casual Ostracism: Jury Exclusion on the Basis of Criminal Convictions, 98 Minn. L. Rev. 592, 605 (2013) (“To exclude from jury service those with criminal convictions is to remove a certain type of experience from the jury . . . .”). ... Close but also those who have a history of being arrested or charged with crimes, 117 117 See Roberts, Disparately Seeking, supra note 21, at 1403–07 (describing how peremp­tory strikes of potential jurors of color because of their experience with policing is generally a “safe haven” under Batson ). ... Close or whose family mem­bers have experience with the criminal legal system. 118 118 Id. at 1403–04. ... Close And although jury nullification is a powerful tool that juries can use to check prosecutorial power, it is a hidden power, and jurors who admit they might nullify are excluded from serving. 119 119 See United States v. Dougherty, 473 F.2d 1113, 1137 (D.C. Cir. 1972) (“[W]hat is tolerable or even desirable as an informal, self-initiated exception [of nullification], har­bors grave dangers to the system if it is . . . incorporat[ed] in the judge’s instruction.”); Paul Butler, Let’s Get Free: A Hip-Hop Theory of Justice 67–68 (2009) [hereinafter Butler, Hip-Hop Theory of Justice] (describing nullification as a “secret power of jurors”). ... Close Jury nullification, of course, may directly contro­vert some conceptions of the rule of law. 120 120 See Darryl K. Brown, Jury Nullification Within the Rule of Law, 81 Minn. L. Rev. 1149, 1150–52 (1997) (describing ways in which jury nullification may subvert the rule of law but is necessary to ensure justice); Jenny E. Carroll, Nullification as Law, 102 Geo. L.J. 579, 609–21 (2014) [hereinafter Carroll, Nullification] (discussing different conceptions of jury nullification in relation to the rule of law). ... Close So, too, might the elimination of another doctrine that epitomizes the idea of a jury primed to side with the prosecu­tion: the requirement that jurors in death penalty cases be “death-qualified.” 121 121 Jurors in death penalty cases must state that they would be willing to impose the death penalty, so as to weed out those who are “unable to decide a capital defendant’s guilt or innocence fairly and impartially.” See Lockhart v. McCree, 476 U.S. 162, 172 (1986); see also id. at 176 (“[T]hose who firmly believe that the death penalty is unjust may nevertheless serve as jurors in capital cases so long as they state clearly that they are willing to temporarily set aside their own beliefs in deference to the rule of law.”); Witherspoon v. Illinois, 391 U.S. 510, 516–18 (1968) (refusing to declare the practice of death-qualifying juries unconstitutional, despite evidence that death-qualified juries will be predisposed to favor the prosecution). A number of scholars have documented how this requirement of death-qualified juries biases juries in favor of the prosecution. See, e.g., Claudia L. Cowan et al., The Effects of Death Qualification on Jurors’ Predisposition to Convict and on the Quality of Deliberation, 8 Law & Hum. Behav. 53, 67–68 (1984); Samuel R. Gross, The Risks of Death: Why Erroneous Convictions Are Common in Capital Cases, 44 Buff. L. Rev. 469, 494–95 (1996); George L. Jurow, New Data on the Effect of a “Death Qualified” Jury on the Guilty Determination Process , 84 Harv. L. Rev. 567, 582–85 (1971). Moreover, death qualification skews the racial composition of juries. See Aliza Plener Cover, The Eighth Amendment’s Lost Jurors: Death Qualification and Evolving Standards of Decency, 92 Ind. L.J. 113, 118 (2016) (presenting evidence that in seven trials in Louisiana, more than one-third of African Americans were struck from capital juries on the basis of their opposition to the death penalty); J. Thomas Sullivan, The Demographic Dilemma in Death Qualification of Capital Jurors, 49 Wake Forest L. Rev. 1107, 1168–69 (2014) (“[T]he death-qualification process . . . serves to reduce the black presence in a symbolically important process in the criminal justice system.”). ... Close But these doctrines defining the composition of “unbi­ased” juries exemplify a conception of criminal procedure that defines “bias” as the tendency to side with defendants.

The separation between the people and the defendant is also at work in efforts to seek popular input into the criminal process in new ways outside of the courthouse, especially through methods of “commu­nity justice.” Community prosecution and community policing may be promising ways to expand the number of voices who have input into polic­ing and prosecution priorities. 122 122 For descriptions of how community prosecution works, see, e.g., Anthony V. Alfieri, Community Prosecutors, 90 Calif. L. Rev. 1465, 1466 (2002); Levine, Prosecuting Police, supra note 85, at 1492–93; Anthony Thompson, It Takes a Community to Prosecute, 77 Notre Dame L. Rev. 321, 360–71 (2002) [hereinafter Thompson, It Takes a Community]; Ronald F. Wright, Beyond Prosecutor Elections, 67 SMU L. Rev. 593, 609–10 (2014). ... Close But even when these processes expand to better capture communal sentiment in local criminal law, they continue to do so by assuming that the community (including victims) is on the side of policing or prosecution. They rarely encourage or incorpo­rate critique, and may instead have the tendency to mute any voices that seek to challenge the status quo. 123 123 See Sklansky, Democracy, supra note 27, at 114–32 (critiquing the community policing paradigm, in part for its tendency to mute critical or oppositional voices); Alschuler & Schulhofer, supra note 17, at 217 (“Far from serving the needs of the disad­van­taged, the concept of community can, in the wrong hands, become another weapon for perpetuating the disempowerment and discrimination that continue to haunt urban America.”); Stephen D. Mastrofski & Jack R. Greene, Community Policing and the Rule of Law, in Police Innovation and Control of the Police: Problems of Law, Order, and Community 80, 92–93 (David Weisburd & Craig Uchida eds., 1993) (discussing “the chal­lenge of stimulating actual community voice rather than achieving cooptation” that arises from community policing); M. Alexander Pearl, Of “Texans” and “Custers”: Maximizing Welfare and Efficiency Through Informal Norms, 19 Roger Williams U. L. Rev. 32, 47–48 (2014) (arguing that community policing imposes norms on the community that are “funda­mentally external and foreign to the community,” even if they are “executed by various members of the community”); Alice Ristroph, The Constitution of Police Violence, 64 UCLA L. Rev. 1182, 1223–25 (2017) [hereinafter Ristroph, Constitution of Police Violence] (describing the “scholarly veneration of compliance” in respect to community policing and procedural justice); Simonson, Copwatching, supra note 25, at 405 (describ­ing how the consensus-based efforts at community justice reinscribe existing power imbalances). ... Close They rarely ask how to facilitate commu­nal support of those subject to surveillance, arrest, prosecution, and punishment. 124 124 See James Forman, Jr., Community Policing and Youth as Assets, 95 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1, 14–16, 19–21 (2004) (describing studies of the uneven inclusion of popula­tions with little political power in community policing, especially poor people of color and young people); Wesley G. Skogan, Representing the Community in Community Policing, in Community Policing: Can It Work? 57, 57 (Wesley G. Skogan ed., 2004) (describing how attendance at beat meetings in Chicago represents “a strong middle-class bias” and “do[es] a better job at representing already established stakeholders in the community than [it] do[es] at integrating marginalized groups with fewer mechanisms for voicing their concerns”). Even well-meaning prosecutors and police officers will tend to hear the opinions with which they agree, moving toward a “consensus” that reflects more their starting point than a compromise position. See Steve Herbert, Citizens, Cops, and Power: Recognizing the Limits of Community 72–73 (2006) (finding that police constitute their own view of community and “recognize some and not other forms of input as legitimate”); Sklansky, Democracy, supra note 27, at 114–20 (describing how some forms of community policing mute “dissident values” that diverge from the status quo); id. at 289 (“‘Community prosecution’ and ‘neighborhood prosecution’ often wind up being . . . efforts to decentralize the location and focus of prosecutors, but not to decentralize political oversight.”). ... Close And they rarely look to the ways in which marginalized populations are already intervening at moments that are technically “procedural” but when added up constitute the heart of the criminal adjudication experience .

A conception of criminal procedure that places the public in direct oppo­sition to defendants and arrestees is problematic for a number of reasons. To begin with, it is descriptively inaccurate. Pairing “the People” with the people discounts the array of ways in which marginalized groups living in the shadow of the carceral state intervene in the criminal pro­cess on behalf of defendants and those targeted by the police. 125 125 See supra section I.C . ... Close Police and courts often meet these bottom-up participatory tactics with resis­tance, arguing that they undermine the rule of law and disrupt the deco­rum of everyday justice. For example, police arrest organized copwatch­ers for filming, administrators close courtrooms to spectators, and judges order the closure of community bail funds. 126 126 Simonson, Democratizing Criminal Justice, supra note 25, at 1622. For a descrip­tion of these forms of resistance by state actors, see id. at 1617–21. ... Close This state resistance to partici­pation on behalf of defendants is made possible by the peo­ple/defendant dichotomy, which limits the ways in which we balance and reform our current procedures. Below I flesh out two particular facets of the people/defendant dichotomy that serve to legitimize the exclusion of marginalized populations from everyday adjudication: the representation problem and the neutrality problem.

B. The Representation Problem

The idea that the public stands on the side of everyday prosecutions allows the criminal process to channel public participation in everyday adjudication through the public’s representatives, most prominently line prosecutors. The problem with the ideology of representation is not the concept that prosecutors represent the interests of some public—surely they do. Rather, the problematic assumption underlying the representa­tion ideal is that prosecutors represent the interests of the entire commu­nity. Describing prosecutors and police as representatives of “the People” as one entity assumes that our current methods of seeking public input into criminal justice are capable of accurately channeling public senti­ment. This assumption is not only false, it is harmful; it allows the process to exclude those who would try to participate in other ways. The result of the ideology of representation, then, is that marginalized groups are dou­bly excluded: They are excluded from the participation that does hap­pen, and their own bottom-up participation is discounted as illegitimate.

Prosecutors have deeply entrenched identities as conduits for the pub­lic will for justice—as representatives of the public. This prosecutorial identity as a representative of the local public is exemplified by a prosecu­tor calling herself “the People” in court, but it is not dependent on this label. Nor is it solely about being elected by the populace. As Attorney General Jeff Sessions, himself an appointed rather than elected prosecutor, told a room of state and local prosecutors: “As a prosecutor, you have the honor of representing your community in court. I will never forget the feeling of going before a judge and saying, ‘the United States is ready.’ I will never get over that feeling . . . . I’m sure you feel the same way.” 127 127 Jeff Sessions, Att’y Gen., U.S. Dep’t of Justice, Remarks to the National District Attorneys Association (July 17, 2017), https://www.justice.gov/opa/speech/attorney-general-jeff-sessions-delivers-remarks-national-district-attorneys-association [https://perma.cc/KAW4-3J5W]. But see Laurie L. Levenson, Conflicts over Conflicts: Challenges in Redrafting the ABA Standards for Criminal Justice on Conflicts of Interest, 38 Hastings Const. L.Q. 879, 885 (2011) (“Although most prosecutors appreciate on some intellectual level that they represent the ‘People’ or ‘Government’ or the community-at-large, on a day-to-day basis, they answer only to themselves or to a supervisor.” (footnote omitted)). ... Close With respect to prosecutions, the idea of representation can mean either that prosecutors are making decisions that reflect the priori­ties of the public (they are “descriptive” representatives), or that prosecu­tors have been fairly selected and given authority to make the decisions that they feel are just (they are “acting for” the public based on their own ideas of justice). 128 128 See generally Hanna Fenichel Pitkin, The Concept of Representation 60–92, 112–42 (1967) (describing these different concepts of representation and functions of representatives). ... Close Either way, the ideal of representation serves to cement the idea of the prosecutor as a conduit for the public interest. This concept of public prosecutors as representatives channeling public sentiment arose in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, as public prosecutors gradually supplanted private parties as initiators of criminal prosecutions in the United States, 129 129 For a summary of the history of public prosecution in the United States, see Joan E. Jacoby, The American Prosecutor: A Search for Identity 7–36 (1980); John D. Bessler, The Public Interest and the Unconstitutionality of Private Prosecutors, 47 Ark. L. Rev. 511, 516–21 (1994); Eric S. Fish, Against Adversary Prosecution, 103 Iowa L. Rev. 1419, 1435–40 (2018) . ... Close with the role of defending the “peace and dignity of the state” by publicly prosecuting wrongdoers. 130 130 Jacoby, supra note 129, at 10 (quoting the 1796 Vermont Constitution). ... Close The resulting concept of public prosecution was that “society as a whole [is] the ultimate victim” of crime, and the role of prosecutors is to repre­sent society in condemning that crime; in this sense, prosecutors are the people. 131 131 Id. at 10. Historians disagree as to whether this shift to prosecution by public representatives constituted an effort to democratize criminal justice by moving beyond private power, or an effort to expand the reach of the criminal law by allowing prosecution for victimless crimes. Compare, e.g., id. at 10–11 (describing the shift to public prosecu­tion as a reaction to inequities), with Allen Steinberg, The Transformation of Criminal Justice: Philadelphia, 1800–1880, at 119–49 (1989) (describing the rise of public prosecu­tion in Philadelphia as a reaction to disorder and a desire to prosecute victimless crimes). ... Close

The ideal of prosecutorial representation has a baseline faulty assump­­tion: that popular input happens, and happens well. The dichotomy between the people and the defendant assumes that because prosecutors and police chiefs are often elected, they are able to trans­form public sentiment into legal action. However, while prosecutorial and policing decisions surely reflect some popular sentiment, and possi­bly even the majority view of justice, 132 132 But see Jazmine Ulloa, ACLU Campaign Highlights the Positions of California District Attorneys on Crime and Punishment Ballot Measures, L.A. Times (Aug. 22, 2017), http://www.latimes.com/politics/essential/la-pol-ca-essential-politics-updates-aclu-targets-california-district-1503370121-htmlstory.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review ) (describ­­ing the disconnect between public opinion polls and opinions of elected district attorneys in California). ... Close studies have continually shown that they usually do not reflect the input of the most marginalized voices, who either are ineligible to vote or come from neighborhoods whose politi­cal power has been undermined by mass incarceration. 133 133 See Vanessa Barker, The Politics of Imprisonment: How the Democratic Process Shapes the Way America Punishes Offenders 12 (2009) (arguing that punitive policies coincide with electorates dominated by elite social groups); Traci Burch, supra note 16, at 75–77 (“People who live in high-imprisonment neighborhoods vote less than people who live in neighborhoods with fewer prisoners . . . [and] are less active in politics . . . .”); Lerman & Weaver, supra note 16, at 199–202 (explaining the impact of the stigma of imprison­ment on an individual’s likelihood to participate in political institutions); Lisa L. Miller, The Myth of Mob Rule: Violent Crime and Democratic Politics 9 (2016) [hereinaf­ter Miller, Mob Rule] (arguing that high levels of imprisonment can be explained in part by a “ democratic deficit that leaves lawmakers only marginally accountable for producing collective goods”); Stuntz, Collapse of American Criminal Justice, supra note 16, at 244–56 (tracing the decline of local democratic control over criminal justice, which has left those voters with the largest stake in the process with the smallest voice in relevant decisions); Richard A. Bierschbach & Stephanos Bibas, Rationing Criminal Justice, 116 Mich. L. Rev. 187, 239 (2017) (noting that it is the poor and disenfranchised “who overwhelmingly suf­fer the cost of criminal justice’s externalities and whose voices often go unheard”); Roberts, Social and Moral Cost, supra note 16, at 1291–98 (discussing the negative effects of mass imprisonment on the participation of black communities in elections and labor markets, and the resulting civic isolation in such communities). ... Close This is in large part a consequence of the broad reach of the criminal legal system itself, which not only disenfranchises large numbers of people with crimi­nal records or in state custody but also drains political power from entire neighborhoods 134 134 See, e.g., Lerman & Weaver, supra note 16, at 140 (describing how interacting with the criminal process affects political engagement); Roberts, Constructing a Criminal Justice System, supra note 24, at 279–83 (describing the criminal justice system’s “anti-demo­cratic function”). ... Close and teaches those who have contact with the criminal justice system that they are not deserving of full participation. 135 135 In the context of everyday policing, for example, Monica Bell has diagnosed the ways in which “African Americans and residents of high-poverty neighborhoods . . . are . . . structurally ostracized through law’s ideals and priorities.” Bell, supra note 58, at 2085–86. ... Close

Even if it were possible to perfect representation, to assume that the people speak through “the People” (or through any representatives) dis­counts more adversarial forms of participation that would challenge every­day institutional practices. In other words, the focus on perfecting public input into prosecution priorities ex ante facilitates the suppression of input on behalf of defendants in individual cases. Because we assume that the public should participate in criminal procedure through their representatives, the system can feel free to treat interventions on the side of the defendant as interference rather than participation. When we inter­pret the will of the people, we do not take into account the input of those who intervene on behalf of defendants: They are simply members of the defendant’s support team, rather than members of the larger pub­lic whose views should dictate policing and prosecution priorities. As the next section describes, running alongside this ideal of representation is a second ideal, of a “neutral” public, which brings with it a related set of limitations with respect to public participation in criminal justice.

C. The Neutrality Problem

The second problem with the ideology of the people/defendant dichot­omy is that it creates a misleading and exclusionary ideal of a “neu­tral” public that participates in the criminal justice process. 136 136 The problem of neutrality goes beyond the public—there is also an assumption of neutrality in the proceedings overall that Ion Meyn has argued distorts procedure in unfair ways. See Ion Meyn, The Unbearable Lightness of Criminal Procedure, 42 Am. J. Crim. L. 39, 56–60 (2014). ... Close The ideal of a neutral public—a public that is both disinterested and deco­rous—is problematic because in practice it defines a neutral public as a subset of the public that buys into the legitimacy of the current system and the general priorities of current policing and prosecutorial prac­tices. 137 137 As a number of scholars have shown, this ideal of a subservient, obedient public is echoed in constitutional jurisprudence as well. See, e.g., Capers, Good Citizen, supra note 25, at 654–57 (describing how criminal procedure doctrine conceives of the “good citizen” as one will­ing to waive his rights); Miller, Encountering Resistance, supra note 26, at 300–10 (argu­ing that challenging the police is “ the way in which we assert our legal rights against the government” while compliance vitiates protections provided by the Constitution); Ristroph, Constitution of Police Violence, supra note 123, at 1215–38 (describing how “constitutional doctrine expects and even demands suspects’ compliance across the board,” with a duty of compliance that is disparately aimed at black and brown suspects). ... Close Those assumed to be opposed to the dominant approach of the system are weeded out as biased, leaving us with a public predisposed to uphold the status quo. And those who take on more adversarial forms of participation are seen as disruptive, silencing counterviewpoints that might otherwise add balance to our conceptions of justice.

The concept of a “neutral” public in criminal procedure begins by exclud­ing from its definition of the public those with criminal records or prior contact with the criminal justice system, labeling them inherently “biased.” The formal exclusion of individuals with criminal records from participating in criminal justice as voters, jurors, and bail bond agents is based, in part, on a belief that people with criminal records are too biased to be neutral. One of the explicit justifications for disenfran­chising individuals with felony criminal records, for example, is that people with criminal records will be biased against sensible crime pol­icies. 138 138 See Jeff Manza & Christopher Uggen, Locked Out: Felon Disenfranchisement and American Democracy 12–13 (2006) (describing the fear that people with criminal records could “corrupt the ballot box” by loosening criminal laws as one of three central arguments in favor of felon disenfranchisement); Alec C. Ewald, An “Agenda for Demolition”: The Fallacy and the Danger of the “Subversive Voting” Argument for Felony Disenfranchisement, 36 Colum. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 109, 111–22 (2004) (describing the fear expressed by judges, politicians, academics, and advocates that individuals with criminal records will sway elections to be “anti-law enforcement”). ... Close Roger Clegg puts it this way: “If these laws did not exist there would be a real danger of creating an anti-law enforcement voting bloc in municipal elections, which is hardly in the interests of a neighborhood’s law-abiding citizens.” 139 139 Roger Clegg, Who Should Vote? , 6 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 159, 177 (2001). ... Close In congressional testimony, Senator Mitch McConnell similarly worries that giving individuals with criminal records the ability to vote would create a “vot­ing bloc” that would make it hard to be tough on crime. 140 140 Manza & Uggen, supra note 138, at 12. ... Close The idea that individuals with criminal records might side with people accused of crimes, and that this is a bad thing , also pervades the practices of everyday adjudication such as jury selection, 141 141 See Kalt, supra note 21, at 74–75 (noting that one “common basis offered for felon exclusion [from jury service] is that felons are inherently biased”); Roberts, Disparately Seeking, supra note 21, at 1403 (“The lack of inquiry into whether a connec­tion with law enforcement or the criminal justice system automatically validates a strike, whatever its disparate impact, suggests an assumption that a potential juror with such a connection would have a negative view of the prosecution’s case.”). ... Close bail, 142 142 See, e.g., Amber Widgery, Bail Bond Agent Licensure, Nat’l Conference of State Legislatures (Apr. 23, 2013), http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/bail-bond-agent-licensure.aspx [https://perma.cc/7H9D-T79A] (“[M]ost states will not issue nor renew a license to those who commit a felony, a crime of moral turpitude or offenses involving misappropriation of money or property.”). ... Close and the regulation of the courtroom audience. 143 143 See Simonson, Audience, supra note 79, at 2190–95 (describing the exclusion of audience members—defendants and their supporters—from criminal courtrooms). ... Close This idea, that people with criminal records or police con­tact are too biased to be included in public-facing procedures, furthers not only the isolation of individual defendants from public support but also the alienation of entire neighborhoods from the political processes that do happen. 144 144 Cf. Pamela S. Karlan, Convictions and Doubts: Retribution, Representation, and the Debate over Felon Disenfranchisement, 56 Stan. L. Rev. 1147, 1161 (2004) (“Criminal disenfranchisement laws . . . operate as a kind of collective sanction: They penalize not only actual wrongdoers, but also the communities from which incarcerated prisoners come and the communities to which ex-offenders return by reducing their relative politi­cal clout.”). ... Close The result is the legitimation of exclusionary rules and practices that maintain the antidemocratic nature of everyday criminal procedure.

The discourse surrounding the bias of individuals with criminal rec­ords is particularly strong in the realm of jury selection, where courts throughout the United States comfortably exclude individuals with crimi­nal records from juries, either under blanket policies or via individual voir dire. When defendants have challenged the blanket exclusions of individuals with criminal records from jury service, courts justify the prac­tice with the idea of neutrality, based on “promot[ing] the legitimate state goal of assuring impartiality of the verdict.” 145 145 Rubio v. Superior Court, 593 P.2d 595, 600 (Cal. 1979) (holding that a California statute excluding ex-felons from jury service did not violate the Equal Protection Clause); see also Kalt, supra note 21, at 73–75 (collecting cases justifying exclusion of people with felony records on the grounds of jury probity and inherent bias). Note though that there is another possible justification—that potential jurors with felony convictions have exhib­ited poor judgment or character through past acts and would not be upstanding jurors. Cf. United States v. Barry, 71 F.3d 1269, 1274 (7th Cir. 1995) (“[I]n most cases, by running afoul of the law, accused persons have shown poor judgment . . . . Theirs is hardly the com­mon-sense judgment of the community.”). ... Close Judicial decisions dis­cuss the “presumptively ‘shared attitudes’” of people with felony convic­tions 146 146 Carle v. United States, 705 A.2d 682, 686 (D.C. 1998) (“The presumptively ‘shared attitudes’ of convicted felons as they relate to the goal of juror impartiality are a primary reason for the exclusion . . . .”). ... Close and the “bias in favor of the defendant on trial, who is seen as a fellow underdog caught in [the system’s] toils.” 147 147 Rubio , 593 P.2d at 600 (“The Legislature could reasonably determine that a per­son who has suffered the most severe form of condemnation that can be inflicted by the state . . . might well harbor a continuing resentment . . . . [T]hese antisocial feelings would . . . risk . . . prejudice infecting the trial . . . .”). ... Close Whether or not it is correct to say that people with criminal records are more likely to acquit a defendant, 148 148 Recent research indicates that individuals with criminal records may actually not be predisposed to favor defendants. See James M. Binnall, A Field Study of the Presumptively Biased: Is There Empirical Support for Excluding Convicted Felons from Jury Service?, 36 Law & Pol’y 1 , 18 (2014) (conducting an empirical study that found “no significant difference between the group-level bias of convicted felons” and law students, suggesting that other groups without felony records “are likely to exhibit statistically simi­lar levels of prodefense/antiprosecution bias”). ... Close the underlying idea is clear: Empathy toward defendants as a general group of people accused by the state has no place in the court­room. This state interest in “impartiality” has been enough to uphold constitutional challenges to the practice of excluding individuals with felony records from juries. 149 149 See Kalt, supra note 21, at 73–75 (collecting cases). ... Close

Similarly, courts have created a safe haven for prosecutors to strike from juries individuals who hold negative views of police officers, even if prospective jurors say that they could be impartial in assessing the evi­dence in the case. 150 150 See Roberts, Disparately Seeking, supra note 21, at 1406–08 (describing Batson cases that hold it unacceptable to strike a white juror because they may have a positive view of law enforcement and contrasting those cases with those that allow prosecutors to strike jurors of color who have negative experiences with law enforcement). ... Close Rarely, if ever, do courts engage in the reverse analysis, asking whether people without criminal records might have a different kind of bias, of not understanding what it is like to go through the process of arrest or accusation. 151 151 Cf. Abramson, supra note 43, at 887–93 (describing how jury deliberation actually improves when the jury contains diverse points of view); Dov Fox, Neuro-Voir Dire and the Architecture of Bias, 65 Hastings L.J. 999, 1042 (2014) (“The conception of jury bias that much of impartiality doctrine takes for granted sweeps every source of outside influence under that vague concept. No such monolithic conception of bias can meaningfully distin­guish those outside sources of juror influence that inform a fair trial from those that infect it.”); Martha Minow, Stripped Down like a Runner or Enriched by Experience: Bias and Impartiality of Judges and Jurors, 33 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1201, 1208 (1992) (discussing “the danger of considering an initial appearance of bias without probing how others may be similarly but more subtly implicated in the issue of bias”). ... Close Indeed, Batson jurisprudence is gener­ally resistant to allowing defense attorneys to exclude white jurors because they may hold positive views of law enforcement. 152 152 Roberts, Disparately Seeking, supra note 21, at 1406–07. ... Close The assump­tion is that to be generally in favor of policing and prosecutorial policies is to be neutral.

The institutional practices of state courthouses also tend to push back against members of the general public who attempt to participate in everyday justice on the side of defendants, labelling them as biased med­dlers rather than healthy participants in everyday justice. Although the First and Sixth Amendments together guarantee the right to a public crimi­nal adjudication, in practice local audiences are often excluded from courtrooms, whether because courts create policies that explicitly forbid public attendance at nontrial proceedings, because courtrooms are too crowded, or because—in the case of courtwatching groups or other activists intervening on behalf of defendants—the presence of support­ers of defendants undermines the “neutrality” of the proceed­ings. 153 153 See generally Simonson, Audience, supra note 79 (describing these trends). ... Close Some court officers tell members of the public who are there to support a defendant but are not family members that they cannot enter courtrooms. 154 154 See, e.g., Sarah Geraghty & Melanie Velez, Bringing Transparency and Accountability to Criminal Justice Institutions in the South, 22 Stan. L. & Pol’y Rev. 455, 468–70 (2011) (describing the closing of courtrooms in Georgia as a means of blocking citizens from monitoring the criminal justice system). ... Close And it is not uncommon for courthouses to allow victims’ rights advocates to sit together and wear visible T-shirts or other indica­tions of prosecutorial support but to exclude groups who wish to sit in courtrooms visibly supporting defendants. 155 155 See supra note 19. ... Close The net result of these doc­trines and practices is a watered-down vision of lay participation in public adjudication in which to be “pro-defense,” “anti-police,” or “anti-prosecu­tion” is a state of mind in conflict with the rule of law or the process of a democratic criminal justice system.

Overall, then, the pervading sense that audiences and juries must not be pro-defense or biased against the prosecution helps explain how state actors meet direct communal participation on behalf of defendants with either resistance or silence. When court clerks tell community groups that they cannot post bail for strangers, for example, those clerks simply cannot conceive of “neutral” reasons for a group to bail out a stranger. The bail fund becomes a force infusing bias into a neutral sys­tem, rather than a community group articulating a broader vision of jus­tice that involves supporting defendants whom they do not know person­ally. 156 156 Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 599–612. ... Close In this way, the concept of a “neutral” public of which defendants are not a part makes it that much easier to automatically cast those accused or investigated as “other.” When we cannot imagine ourselves on the side of the defendant, then we construct rules and analyze doctrine in distinctly different ways than we might otherwise . 157 157 Cf. Cover, Violence, supra note 22, at 1608 (noting that the “violence of the act of sentenc­ing is most obvious when observed from the defendant’s perspective” while the communal meaning of the event “will tend to ignore the prisoner or defendant and focus upon the judge and the judicial interpre­tive act”); Griffiths, supra note 29, at 385 (“[W]e . . . persist in thinking of a con­victed person as a special sort of individual, one cut off in some mysterious way from the common bonds that unite the rest of us.”). ... Close The dominant ideology of criminal procedure simply cannot account for communal participation on behalf of defendants as anything other than “biased,” stifling the ability of these bottom-up visions to make their way into our everyday understandings of criminal procedure.

III. Putting the People on Both Sides: An Alternative Vision

In this Part, I put forth an alternative vision of criminal procedure that conceives of public participation as a valuable input on both sides of every criminal case. This vision centers on the notion that the public, or the “community,” does not always stand in opposition to a defendant who asserts an individual right or invokes a procedural rule. Instead, there is a facet of the local public that is on the side of many defendants—and poten­tial defendants—as part of their own visions of justice and commu­nity. 158 158 The idea that the public does not always stand against an individual defendant finds some resonance in scholarship that critiques individual constitutional rights as a legitimizing force in an unjust criminal justice system. See, e.g., Butler, Poor People Lose, supra note 91, at 2178 (“ Gideon  . . . stands in the way of the political mobilization that will be required to transform criminal justice.”); Louis Michael Seidman, Brown and Miranda , 80 Calif. L. Rev. 673, 680 (1992) (arguing that “the legislative character of Brown and Miranda actually allowed the Court to defuse the promise of radical transformation that was immanent in prior precedent”); Louis Michael Seidman, Criminal Procedure as the Servant of Politics, 12 Const. Comment. 207, 207 (1995) (“[T]he Fourth, Fifth and Sixth Amendments function mostly to make us satisfied with a state of affairs that should trouble us deeply.”); Stuntz, Uneasy Relationship, supra note 31, at 4 (describing the “perverse effects” of constitutional criminal procedure). ... Close The people are not just on the side of the prosecution, and so we should recognize the benefit of facilitating resistance to individual prosecu­tions by encouraging participation at multiple moments in the criminal process. I begin with two theoretical ideas: first, that democratic criminal processes benefit from facilitating communal, agonistic contes­ta­tion; and second, that such democratic contestation requires mov­ing beyond the idea of prosecutors as representatives of the entire “People” in the courtroom. I then flesh out what putting “the People” on both sides of a criminal case can look like on the ground.

A. Communal Contestation Through Criminal Procedure

Criminal adjudication involves the prosecution of individual defen­dants for alleged law-breaking; but it need not follow that individual defen­dants stand alone in the courtroom. If criminal justice is a public enterprise, then we might open up both sides of a criminal case to public participation and to contestation over the meanings of justice and fair­ness. Collective interventions on behalf of individual defendants allow members of the public to connect the fates of those defendants to the well-being of entire neighborhoods and communities. 159 159 Cf. Bell, supra note 58, at 2083–89 (describing how people living in African American and high-poverty neighborhoods experience at a communal level exclusion from the polity as a result of criminal justice practices). ... Close Groups of lay­peo­ple are able to demonstrate through action their disapproval of individual prosecutions while simultaneously contesting existing priori­ties in local criminal law more broadly. When laypeople join collec­tively to contest meanings of justice, they bring into the criminal court­house what Lani Guinier and Gerald Torres call “demosprudence”—the engage­ment of social movements with legal meaning. 160 160 Lani Guinier & Gerald Torres, Changing the Wind: Notes Toward a Demosprudence of Law and Social Movements, 123 Yale L.J. 2740, 2743, 2749 (2014); see also Moore, Decarceral Constitutionalism, supra note 80, at 30–40 (describing how social movements shift constitutional meaning on the ground through efforts such as participa­tory defense). Demosprudence does not only happen outside of formal legal spaces, in community meetings or protests; it can also happen inside courtrooms, when members of the public engage in contestation alongside state actors, co-creating legal meaning. Cf. Lani Guinier, Foreword: Demosprudence Through Dissent, 122 Harv. L. Rev. 4, 13–20 (2008) (describing how demosprudence can operate inside the Supreme Court court­room through oral dissents); Patel, supra note 25, at 867–77 (describing contestation within the courtroom in the context of police consent decrees). ... Close The criminal courthouse can become a site of democratic contestation in which ordi­nary people’s visions of justice are placed on equal ground with those of elected prose­cutors or judges. This communal resistance to prosecution can enrich the public arena of justice, expanding the possible legal mean­ings that we can attribute to any individual case or issue.

The conceptual shift I propose is intimately tied to the larger norma­tive belief that direct forms of contestation are crucial for democratic justice. Although this Essay does not aim to present a complete theory of democracy by any means, there are at least four important aspects to how I conceptualize democracy and political change that bear on this Essay’s vision of criminal procedure. First, I share with a republican criminal jus­tice ideal the view that giving officials too much power is dangerous; in the context of criminal justice we should prioritize popular interventions, including from social movements, that counter dominion. 161 161 See John Braithwaite & Philip Pettit, Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice 7–11 (1990) (arguing that criminal justice should favor republican ideals to maximize the “enjoyment of certain rights”); John Braithwaite, Criminal Justice that Revives Republican Democracy, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1507, 1519–21 (2017) [hereinafter Braithwaite, Criminal Justice] (arguing that the criminal justice system can be used to counteract the antidemocratic forces of electoral populism and money in politics); cf. Ekow N. Yankah, Republican Responsibility in Criminal Law, 9 Crim. L. & Phil. 457, 462–63 (2015) (contrasting the antidomination strand of republican criminal theory with Yankah’s concept of an Aristotelian or Athenian republican theory of criminal law). For further development of these arguments, see infra notes 177–178 and accompanying text. ... Close Second, mov­ing beyond a neorepublican ideal, 162 162 A neorepublican theory of criminal justice might prioritize restorative justice rather than agonistic confrontation. Philip Pettit, in his work with John Braithwaite, has connected his republican theory of democracy with a theory of criminal justice that cen­ters in part on restorative justice. See Braithwaite & Pettit, supra note 161, at 120–24; Braithwaite, Criminal Justice, supra note 161, at 1509–10. Similarly, John Griffiths, in his takedown of Herbert Packer, would have had us move away from adversarialism toward a “Family Model” of criminal procedure, a model that became an inspiration for John Braithwaite in his pathbreaking vision of restorative justice. See Griffiths, supra note 29, at 372–73. But restorative justice, or a “Family Model,” assumes that a wrong has been commit­ted against a community and works from there to seek common ground in fashion­ing a punishment. Id. It does not allow for adversarial or agonistic engagement with the criminal legal process. ... Close my vision centers on the importance of agonistic interventions in which people who participate can remain opposed to the actors who ordinarily dominate the process. With agonism, lay participation in the criminal legal system can take an adversar­ial stance toward practices and ideologies of institutions in power through engagement with those institutions, by acknowledging intracta­ble differences but respecting the adversary who disagrees. 163 163 See Mouffe, Agonistics, supra note 25, at 1–19 (arguing that democracy requires “confrontation of democratic political positions” but that adversaries in such confronta­tions should not “call into question the legitimacy of their opponent’s right to fight for the victory of their position”); Chantal Mouffe, The Democratic Paradox 80–105 (2000) (advocat­ing for an agnostic model of democracy in which people treat the opposition as “legitimate opponents”). ... Close Embedded in this second idea is a third: a pluralist conception of the demos in which there is no one “public,” “people,” or “community” to whom state actors are beholden, but rather multiple publics with contrasting ideas about justice that cannot be easily reconciled. 164 164 See, e.g., Robert A. Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory 134–45 (1956) (describ­ing American democracy as a political struggle among different groups); Sklansky, Democracy, supra note 27, at 23–28 (summarizing the ways in which the pluralists saw group conflict as the essence of politics). ... Close This is therefore not a populist vision of criminal adjudication, in the sense that I oppose the view that there is only one legitimate conception of who “the People” are. 165 165 See Jan-Werner Müller, What Is Populism? 3–4 (2016) (describing a core belief of populism that only some of the people are truly “the People”). ... Close The fourth important strand of this view of democratic criminal justice is that popular participation need not be mediated through repre­sent­atives, but can and should also spring up through direct forms of participation and contestation. 166 166 This view contrasts directly with the value in democratic pluralist theory placed on the political elite as a sign of a healthy democracy. See generally Robert A. Dahl, Who Governs?: Democracy and Power in an American City (1961) (describing the importance of political elites, or “homus politicus”). ... Close

Under these conceptions of democracy and political change, the answer to any disconnect between criminal processes and popular will is not to move away from or supplement the adversarial process but rather to bring into our debates over criminal procedure the merits of facilitat­ing direct popular intervention on both sides of the “v.” Indeed, this way of thinking about criminal procedure, in which the public has a part to play on both sides of any case, highlights a potential benefit of our adversar­ial system of criminal adjudication: that it can facilitate impor­tant forms of contestatory participation in everyday justice that would otherwise be muted in consensus-based methods of gathering popular input into criminal justice. 167 167 See generally Sklansky, Democracy, supra note 27, at 86–97 (describing the dan­gers of the rising preoccupation with consensus-based forms of participation in policing). This is not to say that consensus-based forms of participation do not have their place. Agonistic engagement should complement, not replace, representation and deliberative participation. Cf. Íñigo Errejón & Chantal Mouffe, Podemos: In the Name of the People 125 (2016) (describing the “synergy between electoral competition and the wide range of struggles that take place in the social arena”); Miller, Encountering Resistance, supra note 26, at 296 (“Mature democracies are both participatory and contestatory . . . .”). ... Close Moreover, these forms of contestatory participa­tion are more likely to come from marginalized populations with the least amount of power in the current system—the poor people of color who are most likely to be arrested and prosecuted, as well as to be victims of crime. Power can move through procedure: When a group posts bail for a stranger, sits together in a courtroom to support a defen­dant, or makes a biographical video for a sentencing hearing, the mem­bers of that group shift power and agency dynamics inside the court­house, destabilizing deeply entrenched legal and constitutional mean­ings. Dismantling the people/defendant dichotomy thus carries with it the potential to push back against the antidemocratic nature of current power relationships in criminal law and procedure. 168 168 See supra notes 59–79 and accompanying text; cf. Roberts, Constructing a Criminal Justice System, supra note 24, at 279–85 (describing the criminal justice system’s “anti-democratic function”). ... Close

B. Moving Beyond Representation

This vision of criminal procedure requires moving beyond representa­tion, particularly inside the courthouse. This does not require that we abandon the use of prosecutors as representatives on the side of prosecution or of jurors as occasional representatives during delibera­tions after a trial. But to rely only on these representatives results in an illusory sense of representation of the polity as a whole: in the case of prosecutors, because they cannot fully represent any one public; and in the case of juries, because they are so rarely sworn in.

Our dependence on public representatives inside the courthouse is not inevitable—the Constitution does not require that we engage in crimi­nal justice through representatives. Indeed, a structural reading of the Bill of Rights underscores the importance of the public as a constant presence, as jurors and as audiences, in the adjudication of criminal cases. 169 169 See Akhil Reed Amar, The Constitution and Criminal Procedure: First Principles 115–24 (1997) (describing the importance of public participation for constitutional crimi­nal procedure); Simonson, Audience, supra note 79, at 2195–205 (“[T]he Sixth and First Amendment rights to a public trial apply with full force to the protection of the audience in the post-trial world.”). ... Close And, historically, the concept of the “jury of the whole” impli­cated the interest of the entire public in participating in individual cases on all sides. 170 170 See Susan N. Herman, The Right to a Speedy and Public Trial 25 (2006) (describ­ing the concept of the “jury of the whole”). ... Close As Judith Resnik and Dennis Curtis have identified, one of the central purposes of keeping courtrooms open to the public today is that audience members can “deny[ ] the government and disputants unchecked authority to determine the social meanings of conflicts and their resolutions.” 171 171 Resnik & Curtis, supra note 79, at 302; see also Judith Resnik, Fairness in Numbers: A Comment on AT&T v. Concepcion , Wal-Mart v. Dukes , and Turner v. Rogers , 125 Harv. L. Rev. 78, 87 (2011) (“The presence of the public divests both the government and private litigants of control over the meanings of the claims made and the judgments ren­dered and enables popular debate about and means to seek revision of law’s content and application.”); cf. Kleinfeld, Three Principles, supra note 14, at 1483–88 (arguing that at the time of the Founding, there was an understanding of criminal justice as belonging to “We the People” and requiring the participation of the people). ... Close When we shift our understanding of public partici­pa­tion so that it runs through representatives such as prosecutors, however, we mute other forms of direct engagement in everyday justice.

Moving beyond representation begins with a recognition that prose­cu­tors do not fully represent “the People,” and therefore we should not label them that way. States such as California, Illinois, Michigan, and New York should abandon that label on case captions and when referring to individual prosecutors. Instead, it is more honest to designate prosecu­tors as “the State,” “the Commonwealth,” or “the Government”: They are state actors, wielding their state power to prosecute individual defen­dants. This distinction matters. The words that we use to describe prose­cu­tors make their way from courtroom dockets and Westlaw into court­house conversations and popular culture. When I was a public defender in New York City, it was common for judges, clerks, and other courtroom players to refer to individual Assistant District Attorneys as “the People,” as in, “Do the People have an offer?”; “Would the People like to request a lunch break?”; or, if an ADA was not visible in the court­room, “Are the People in the bathroom?” Calling an individual prosecu­tor “the People” sends a powerful message to courtrooms full of defen­dants waiting for their cases to be called: a message that those defendants are not part of “the People,” are not part of the public that matters. And to the public at large, it sends the message that the good public, the “neu­tral” public, cannot be on the side of the defendant.

This is not mere rhetoric; there is an important conceptual distinc­tion between claiming that a prosecutor acts on behalf of the state and claiming that a prosecutor acts on behalf of her community and is of the community. As Michelle Madden Dempsey has argued, “[W]hilst prosecu­tors necessarily represent their state, they may very well fail to represent their community.” 172 172 Dempsey, supra note 90, at 50. ... Close Dempsey follows R.A. Duff in arguing that for the prosecution to represent the community, the prosecution must meet conditions of political legitimacy by treating alleged wrongdoers with respect, as members of that very community. 173 173 Id. at 49–50 (citing R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishment 11 (1986)). ... Close Dempsey concludes that this ideal, of an inclusive community of which defendants are a part, is rarely if ever achieved in the United States. 174 174 Id. at 49 (“Typically, of course, these conditions are not met . . . .”). ... Close As a result, “[g]iven the radical disparity between the actual and the ideal in prosecutorial prac­tices and criminal justice systems more generally . . . it is unlikely that any prosecutor acts on behalf of (represents) every member of her political community.” 175 175 Id. at 52 n.24. ... Close

Prosecutors may therefore be legitimate agents of the state—they may be elected, a majority of the local citizenry may even have chosen them—but it does not follow that they have permission to speak as an agent of the community. Indeed, to speak of prosecutors as constitutive of communal sentiment runs counter to the very concept of adversarial prosecution by a public prosecutor. Paul Butler puts it this way: “In an adversarial system, the prosecutor who is too sympathetic toward the defen­dant’s plight or too suspicious of the police is not doing her job.” 176 176 Butler, Hip-Hop Theory of Justice, supra note 119, at 115; see also Fish, supra note 129, at 1420 n.4 (collecting similar sentiments from other sources). ... Close An honest accounting of how our criminal justice system operates must acknowledge that prosecutors engage not just in imperfect public repre­senta­tion but also in troublesome forms of power-wielding against rela­tively powerless people. In republican terms, prosecutors are sources of state domination as much as of popular representation. 177 177 See Braithwaite & Pettit, supra note 161, at 113–17 (arguing that, in light of the power wielded by prosecutors, community policing and accountability systems are neces­sary to maintain communities’ sense of security and peace of mind); Kleinfeld, Manifesto, supra note 41, at 1396 (“From Pettit, we can add to our mix of ideas the notion . . . that police and prosecutors in the contemporary operation of American criminal justice may enjoy a form of domination inconsistent with democratic freedom . . . .”); cf. John F. Pfaff, Locked In: The True Causes of Mass Incarceration—and How to Achieve Real Reform 127 (2017) (describing the outsized power of prosecutors in criminal justice and arguing that “[f]ew people in the criminal justice system are as powerful, or as central to prison growth, as the prosecutor”); Angela J. Davis, Prosecutors, Democracy, and Race, in Prosecutors and Democracy: A Cross-National Study, supra note 41, at 195, 195 (“Prosecutors are the most powerful officials in the American criminal justice system.”). ... Close To keep this domination in check, we must first acknowledge it. From there, we can then facilitate and even encourage forms of communal contestation that counter it. 178 178 See Philip Pettit, On the People’s Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy 187–293 (2012) (describing the need for popular contestation to counter domina­tion by public officials); K. Sabeel Rahman, Democracy Against Domination: Contesting Economic Power in Progressive and Neorepublican Political Theory, 16 Contemp. Pol. Theory 41, 46–56 (2017) (expanding the republican idea of popular contesta­tion to larger contestation against structural inequality); cf. Braithwaite & Pettit, supra note 161, at 114 (arguing that the overall security and well-being of the community “is frequently best served by not prosecuting”). ... Close

This contestation should not be mediated through representatives, either public defenders or a new form of communal representative in the courtroom. Public defenders are not in a position to provide an adequate counterweight to prosecutors as community representatives. Public defender offices are sometimes seen as representing communal interests, either because they check the power of the prosecutors on behalf of defen­dants in the aggregate, 179 179 See Laura I. Appleman, The Community Right to Counsel, 17 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 1, 60 (2012) [hereinafter Appleman, Community Right] (characterizing the defense counsel as offsetting the state’s power to initiate a process with potential “collateral conse­quences that result in death, life imprisonment, or deportation”); Nirej Sekhon, Mass Suppression: Aggregation and the Fourth Amendment, 51 Ga. L. Rev. 429, 474–77 (2017) (“Embracing a community-oriented ethos requires that defenders imagine their advocacy obligations beyond just obtaining favorable results in individual cases.”). ... Close or because they adopt institutional pos­tures of being “community-based” or of advocating for larger political change that benefits their clients. 180 180 See Kim Taylor-Thompson, Individual Actor v. Institutional Player: Alternating Visions of the Public Defender, 84 Geo. L.J. 2419, 2457–62 (1996) (describing a then-grow­ing trend of public defender offices becoming community-based institutional players). ... Close However, the beneficial roles of institu­tional public defenders are different from, and can even conflict with, the power of communal intervention on behalf of individual defen­dants. 181 181 This conflict manifests itself in two distinct ways. First, real conflicts of interest can emerge between a public defender’s duty to her client and the stated or perceived interests of local community groups; the interests may often be aligned, but sometimes they may not be. It would strain the ability of an attorney to fully represent her client if she also had to consider the interests of the neighborhood. And second, the acts of public defenders working on behalf of supporters of a defendant cannot shift power relationships in the way that bottom-up direct participation by marginalized populations can. See Criminal Justice Standards for the Def. Function Standard 4-1.7 (Am. Bar Ass’n 2018), https://www.americanbar.org/groups/criminal_justice/standards/DefenseFunctionFourthEdition.html [https://perma.cc/BMA6-X6BX] (describing how a defense attorney’s zealous advocacy of her client must come before other loyalties, opinions, or obligations); see also Godsoe, supra note 76 , at 724 (describing this potential conflict in the context of participatory defense); cf. Moore et al., supra note 68, at 1284–85 (describing the power differentials between public defenders and marginalized populations who engage in participa­tory defense). ... Close Although we might imagine a new kind of community representa­tive who could represent public interests in the courtroom, 182 182 See, e.g., Gold, Clientless Prosecutors, supra note 53, at 733–35 (proposing the appointment of amici on behalf of the public). ... Close this second problem would still remain: Such ombudsmen or public advo­cates would not facilitate the shifts in power that characterize direct forms of communal participation.

Instead of searching for perfect representatives of public will, then, our system of criminal procedure must also facilitate direct, contestatory forms of participation in criminal justice most often (but not exclusively) found on the defendant side of the “v.” To be sure, precinct and court­room actors should be democratically accountable. 183 183 For suggestions on how we might better do this, see generally, e.g., Appleman, Community Right, supra note 179 (public defenders); Friedman & Ponomarenko, supra note 47 (policing); Russell M. Gold, Promoting Democracy in Prosecution, 86 Wash. L. Rev. 69 (2011) (prosecutors); Sekhon, supra note 179 (public defenders); Thompson, It Takes a Community, supra note 122 (prosecutors). ... Close In recent years, some local prosecutorial elections have been genuinely contested, and a number of “progressive” prosecutors have won elections with promises of reform, racial justice, and decarceration. 184 184 See David Alan Sklansky, The Progressive Prosecutor’s Handbook, 50 U.C. Davis L. Rev. Online 25, 26 (2017) [hereinafter Sklansky, Progressive Prosecutor], https:// lawreview.law.ucdavis.edu/online/vol50/Sklansky.pdf [https://perma.cc/4CM5-SPEM] (describing the growing number of prosecutors who have won local elections based on a “more balanced approach to criminal justice”); Paige St. John & Abbie VanSickle, Prosecutor Elections Now a Front Line in the Justice Wars, Marshall Project (May 23, 2018), https://www.themarshallproject.org/2018/05/23/prosecutor-elections-now-a-front-line-in-the-justice-wars [https://perma.cc/VZV7-ZGW2]. ... Close These are promising develop­ments for anyone interested in decarceration. And yet, we should be care­ful not to let the high-profile wins of progressive prosecutors further re-entrench the notion that the public belongs only on the prosecution side of the “v.”; even when a progressive prosecutor wins, she does not represent the full community. As long as there are prosecutions against individual defendants, there will be members of the public who support defendants, and there will be interests of the public that coincide with the interests of defendants. The people will be on both sides.

C. When the People Are on Both Sides

What does this new vision of criminal procedure look like on the ground? There are examples all around us. Many existing forms of com­mu­nal contestation demonstrate how agonistic participation can be a powerful and productive force in local criminal justice, underscoring the place of “the People” on the side of the defendant. The tactics that make up participatory defense, for example, are powerful because they not only help mitigate an individual defendant’s sentence, they also con­nect the fate of that person to the public at large. A participatory defense team might produce a biographical video to be shown in court that tells an individual defendant’s personal story within the context of his neighbor­hood and local community. 185 185 See ACJPDEBUG, We Beat a 10 Year Sentence in New York with a Social Biography Video!, Albert Cobarrubias Just. Project (Jan. 7, 2015), https://acjusticeproject.org/2015/01/07/we-beat-a-10-year-sentence-in-new-york-by-sharing-a-family-story-through-video/ [https://perma.cc/55H4-JNRJ]. ... Close Doing so demonstrates to the court that, in the words of one participant, “there never is a sentence just for the ‘defendant’, but rather . . . all the time of incarceration is shared time.” 186 186 Id. ... Close Similarly, when a community bail fund posts bail for a stranger, or for multiple strangers in a mass bailout, they declare through their actions that they have a “shared destiny” with the people for whom they post bail. 187 187 Southerners on New Ground, supra note 66 (“This action allowed us to demon­strate our collective belief in a shared destiny with the dreams, demands and hopes of black women in all of our varieties at the center.”). ... Close And these actions, in the aggregate, build power within marginal­ized communities and push against established ideas of risk, pub­lic safety, and justice.

We can imagine an approach to criminal procedure that treats tac­tics of communal contestation, such as participatory defense or mass bailouts, as procedures worthy of consideration on an equal playing field with other mechanisms of generating public input. My argument is not that any of these interventions are always normatively good or procedur­ally just. Indeed, as I discuss below, there may be aspects of participatory defense or other movement tactics that make one pause to the extent that they bump up against an ideal of the rule of law. But to think about the popular thrust behind these interventions as being about communal or democratic input, rather than simply the enforcement of individual rights on behalf of one person, helps to situate their contribution and to analyze their relative worth. We need to make the crucial conceptual shift that movement actors have already made: that direct participation on the side of the defense is not just about individual defendants but is also about larger democratic engagement and pushing for responsive justice in a system that continues to ignore the input of marginalized popula­tions. 188 188 Cf. Akbar, Radical Imagination, supra note 56, at 479 (underscoring the impor­tance of taking movement visions seriously in thinking about criminal justice). ... Close

Imagining criminal procedure as a process of regulating popular inter­vention on both sides of the “v.” opens up procedure to new ways of thinking and acting. We can take account of the voices we include and exclude in proceedings and realize these are not inevitable choices. We can pay careful attention to the ways in which our current procedures facilitate or impede bottom-up resistance to local police actions and prosecu­tions from those who otherwise do not have a voice in the pro­cess. We can move beyond perfecting the community input into prosecu­tion and the police in recognition that prosecutors and police depart­ments can never truly represent a “community.” We can move toward a jurisprudence of constitutional criminal procedure that acknowledges communal harms and communal interests beyond the traditional idea of “public safety.” And we can hesitate before discounting messy forms of grassroots contestation in favor of the calm decorum of juries, elections, or community policing.

In the sphere of policy, for example, state actors might overcome their aversion to agonistic participation by enacting policies that allow for disruptive but nonviolent forms of protest and intervention. States might change their regulations for posting bail to allow community groups to post bail for multiple people, for any defendant, and in any amount, with­out taking a percentage of the money before returning bail at the end of the case. 189 189 See Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 634–36 (describing state poli­cies that limit the amounts that charitable bail funds can post, charge fees for posting bail, and otherwise make it difficult for community groups to post bail). ... Close Courtroom rules might shift to allow audiences to visibly support defendants. 190 190 See Simonson, Audience, supra note 79, at 2222–32 (describing how courtroom policies can change to be more inclusive of audiences, especially audience members who support defendants). ... Close States might change both the law and practice of excluding from juries individuals with criminal records or a history of contact with the police. 191 191 See Kalt, supra note 21, at 142–48 (suggesting a series of statutory and judicially driven reforms to implement this idea); see also Kleinfeld et al., supra note 53, at 1697 (“Practices of excluding citizens from juries based on their attitudes toward or histories with the criminal justice system, both as a matter of law and as a matter of practice, should be reduced in favor of a presumption of random selection and inclusion.”). ... Close State and local legislatures, courtroom rule-makers, police departments, and local prosecutors all have a role to play in reexamining these official policies. This does not mean that state actors should take control of these bottom-up interventions, for example through the creation of state-sponsored bail funds. 192 192 See Simonson, When the City Posts Bail , supra note 67, at 13–16 (arguing that city bail funds are dangerous because they co-opt social movement tactics that shift power relations). ... Close Rather, state actors should take the bold step of ceding power , of deliberately facilitating power shifts down to the marginalized populations who traditionally have the least input into everyday justice. 193 193 For a provocative account of the importance of power and control in criminal justice, see M Adams & Max Rameau, Black Community Control over Police , 2016 Wis. L. Rev. 515, 529 (arguing that race-based policing policies will change only by shifting the power dynamics between black communities and criminal justice system actors). ... Close

Although for the most part this Essay has focused on courthouse dynam­ics of contestation, these arguments hold with equal force in other domains of criminal justice, including interactions with police officers on the streets and roads, collective efforts to shift the policies of individual prosecutors, and collective resistance by people in custody in jails and prisons. In order to promote collective dissent against policing priorities, localities might enact policies that respect the right of the people to assem­ble, protest, record, and verbally dissent when observing police interact­ing with people in public. 194 194 See Simonson, Beyond Body Cameras, supra note 18, at 1574–78. ... Close And administrators of prisons and jails might allow incarcerated people to engage in hunger strikes and labor strikes, and to publicize their efforts beyond prison walls. 195 195 See Goodman et al., supra note 56, at 12 (“[C]ollective action, individual refusals, and other acts of contestation within penal institutions can have major effects on the devel­op­ment of criminal justice.”); cf. Lisa Guenther, Beyond Guilt and Innocence: The Creaturely Politics of Prisoner Resistance Movements, in Active Intolerance: Michel Foucault, the Prisons Information Group, and the Future of Abolition 225, 227, 232 (Perry Zurn & Andrew Dilts eds., 2016) (describing a “community of resistance” that emerged during hunger strikes at Pelican Bay); Dan Berger, Rattling the Cages, Jacobin (Nov. 18, 2016), https://www.jacobinmag.com/2016/11/prison-strike-slavery-attica-racism-incarcera­tion/ [https://perma.cc/8D8E-YT2P] (describing the labor strike by people in prisons through­out the United States in 2016). ... Close

A vision of criminal procedure that sees the “public interest” on both sides of each criminal case should inform constitutional procedural doctrines as well. This applies most directly to the doctrines structuring public participation in the courtroom: Courts might interpret the First and Sixth Amendments to give community members the right to dissent and intervene in individual cases, 196 196 See Simonson, Audience, supra note 79, at 2226–32. ... Close and recognize the asymmetry of Sixth Amendment rulings that sanction the exclusion of individuals with criminal records as “biased” but find no bias in those with pro-police or pro-prosecutorial attitudes. 197 197 See Roberts, Disparately Seeking, supra note 21, at 1403–04. ... Close Beyond these doctrines structuring public participation, constitutional jurisprudence along a range of individual rights would shift profoundly if it were to recognize the popular interest on the side of defendants via the communal harms of arrests, prosecutions, incarceration, and punishment. 198 198 See Baughman, Pretrial Detention, supra note 104, at 4–7 (describing the social and communal harms of pretrial detention); Bierschbach & Bibas, supra note 133, at 213–18 (describing the collective costs to the public of the punishment of individuals); Yang, supra note 104, at 1423–29 (same). Constitutional doctrine itself also has profound social harms. See, e.g., Capers, Good Citizen, supra note 25, at 663–79 (describing citizenship harms that come from Fourth Amendment doctrine); Carbado , Fourth Amendment, supra note 115, at 966 (describing the social harms of Fourth Amendment doctrines to black people in the United States). ... Close Recognizing communal harms of arrests and prosecutions would shift key constitutional calculations, such as with respect to substantive due process, 199 199 See Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 625–28 (discussing how substan­tive due process analysis shifts in the context of bail and pretrial detention when “the community” is recognized as a force on both sides of the constitutional calculus). ... Close the Eighth Amendment right against excessive bail, 200 200 Id. at 628–31 . ... Close and the Fourth Amendment right against unrea­sonable searches and seizures. 201 201 See Baradaran, supra note 103, at 3–4 (describing how judges making Fourth Amendment reasonableness determinations tend to defer to government interests without considering benefits to the public of ruling in favor of a defendant); Bierschbach, supra note 47, at 1451 (“[C]ourts applying the Fourth Amendment could fold the outlooks of victims of police abuse, innocent civilians, and communities of color into their reasonable­ness analysis.”); I. Bennett Capers, Rethinking the Fourth Amendment: Race, Citizenship, and the Equality Principle, 46 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 1, 37–48 (2011) (arguing that Fourth Amendment doctrine should take into account broader “citizenship harms,” particularly to African Americans). ... Close

These are just examples. But they demonstrate that overcoming the peo­ple/defendant dichotomy can have real on-the-ground consequences for how we design and enforce our procedures and how we interpret our constitutional rules. Envisioning the public intervening on both sides of individual criminal cases requires resetting our assumptions about who counts as democratic subjects in the administration of criminal law and how democratic participation happens in individual cases. By expand­ing our notions of participation, we might be able to move closer to a crim­inal legal system that is more inclusive and responsive to the public it claims to serve.

IV. Resistance, the Rule of the Law, and Decarceration

In this concluding Part, I flesh out some implications of putting the peo­ple on both sides of individual criminal cases for the moment that the United States finds itself in today: facing a carceral state that has ballooned out of control. 202 202 See generally Nat’l Research Council, The Growth of Incarceration in the United States: Exploring Causes and Consequences (Jeremy Travis et al. eds., 2014) (examining the massive increase in incarceration in the United States since the 1970s). ... Close Despite widespread, though not universal, acknowl­­edgement of the urgent need for large-scale criminal law reform, 203 203 Cf. Levin, supra note 37, at 260–65 (arguing that this “consensus” for criminal justice reform actually contains conflicting accounts of the problems and solutions to dismantle the carceral state). ... Close mainstream reforms have yet to truly change the fundamental aspects of a system that arrests, prosecutes, and imprisons vast swaths of its population, 204 204 Cf. Pfaff, supra note 177, at 1 (“The statistics are as simple as they are shocking: the United States is home to 5 percent of the world’s population but 25 percent of its prison­ers.”). ... Close with striking inequalities along lines of race, class, and gender. 205 205 See Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid, supra note 29, at 75 (“But there are at least five factors—classics, if you will—that capture much of the dynamic and explain how the law often works differently for different people under different circumstances. Those five phenom­ena are offense severity , race , gender , class , and defense counsel  . . . .”); Jonathan Simon, Racing Abnormality, Normalizing Race: The Origins of America’s Peculiar Carceral State and Its Prospects for Democratic Transformation Today, 111 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1625, 1627 (2017) (“With striking evidence of racial disproportionality in all aspects of its operations, the U.S. carceral state confronts an acute deficit, or even crisis, of legitimacy.”). ... Close The most marginalized populations in the country are stuck in a cycle of imprisonment and supervision; they are “Caught,” 206 206 Gottschalk, supra note 56. ... Close “Locked In,” 207 207 Pfaff, supra note 177. ... Close and suffocated in a “Chokehold” 208 208 Paul Butler, Chokehold: Policing Black Men (2017) [hereinafter Butler, Chokehold]. ... Close —to name the titles of three recent scholarly books analyzing the problem. Marie Gottschalk (author of Caught ) argues that the only way to achieve large-scale decarceration is to allow ourselves to be open to “convulsive politics from below” 209 209 Gottschalk, supra note 56, at 282 (calling for “convulsive politics from below that we need to dismantle the carceral state and ameliorate other gaping inequalities”). ... Close —to collective resistance that can open up political room for transforma­tion. 210 210 Id. at 2 (“For those seeking to dismantle the carceral state, . . . [t]he real chal­lenge is figuring out how to create a political environment that is more receptive to . . . reforms and how to make the far-reaching consequences of the carceral state into a lead­ing political and public policy issue.”). ... Close A number of other scholars, including Amna Akbar, Paul Butler, Allegra McLeod, Janet Moore, Dorothy Roberts, and Jonathan Simon, echo this idea: that our current moment demands extraor­dinary kinds of interventions into our modes of criminal justice, and that, today, the most inspiring visions for how to do this are found in on-the-ground movements for social and racial justice. 211 211 See, e.g., Paul Butler, Chokehold, supra note 208, at 247 (calling for a “more open-minded perspective on . . . resistance” within the Movement for Black Lives); Butler, Hip-Hop Theory of Justice, supra note 119, at 133 (“[T]he hip-hop nation, and especially its black and Latino citizens, are best situated to design a criminal justice system.”); Akbar, Radical Imagination, supra note 56, at 473 (arguing that we should study and listen to the “radical imagination” of movement actors and their visions for change); McLeod, Carceral State, supra note 56, at 705 (arguing that the “ambitious visions of decarceration [from movement actors] offer a set of transformative aspirational ideas which might orient current reform efforts, rescuing more moderate criminal-law reform from its weakest and most disappointing possible futures”); Roberts, Democratizing Criminal Law, supra note 47, at 1607 (calling for a vision of democracy in which “black communities have greater freedom to envision and create democratic approaches to social harms—for themselves and for the nation as a whole”); Simon, supra note 205, at 1650 (“Reconstructing the car­ceral state will require a democratic process that involves impacted communities first and foremost in re-norming the abnormality against which the carceral state operates.”); Moore, Decarceral Constitutionalism, supra note 80, at 57–73 (connecting participatory defense and other movement-led tactics to the possibility of decarceration). ... Close

But does “convulsive politics from below” really belong inside the crimi­nal courthouse? This Essay’s vision of criminal procedure would bring bottom-up contestation over criminal law and policy directly into courtrooms, and directly into individual cases, presenting a challenge to conventional understandings of the rule of law and procedural uni­formity. In this Part, I confront this tension, defending a conception of criminal procedure in which “the People” are on both sides against the charge that doing so presents an insurmountable problem for the rule of law. I argue that in our present historical moment the risk of partially undermining the dominant idea of the rule of law is, overall, worth the upside of facilitating popular engagement by marginalized populations into a criminal legal system characterized by mass incarceration and super­vision of those very populations. This is because popular interven­tions on behalf of defendants, and in opposition to a state claiming to represent “the People,” provide a method of opening up a closed and alienating criminal justice system to a set of beliefs in the need for decarcera­tion and even abolition held by subsets of the public that have for too long been excluded from public discourse.

A. Communal Resistance and the Rule of Law

There is not a neat relationship between opening up criminal adjudica­tion to direct participation on the side of defendants and protect­ing rule of law values. Many forms of direct participation in every­day adjudication operate squarely within established legal rules, for exam­ple when community bail funds post bail for strangers while follow­ing state and courthouse rules regarding the posting of bail, or courtwatch­ing groups exercise their First Amendment right to observe courtroom proceedings. 212 212 Indeed, one danger with communal interventions that promote the rule of law in this way is that they will legitimize an unjust system by giving it the appearance of fairness and regularity. See Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 635–37 (describing this danger in the context of community bail funds); cf. Robin West, From Choice to Reproductive Justice: De-Constitutionalizing Abortion Rights , 118 Yale L.J. 1394, 1406 (2009) (describing how some law reform can “legitimate a deeper or broader injustice with the legal institution so improved, thus further insulating the underlying or broader legal institution from critique”). ... Close And yet, structuring local courtrooms to facili­tate popular interventions on behalf of defendants may present dangers to the rule of law by facilitating unequal, irregular, or even oppressive forms of resistance to the ordinary criminal process. Here we might imag­ine, for instance, a version of white supremacist jurors nullifying extrale­gal lynchings of African Americans in the South: 213 213 See Michal R. Belknap, Federal Law and Southern Order: Racial Violence and Constitutional Conflict in the Post- Brown South 20, 25, 32, 54–55, 120–24 (1987) (detailing numerous cases in which Southern juries acquitted defendants of racial-violence charges despite significant evidence of guilt). ... Close A contem­porary group intervening in a criminal case and driven by preju­dice might promote rather than counter oppression and inequality. 214 214 Cf. Brown, supra note 120, at 1196 (“There is a class of nullification verdicts that violates the rule of law; decisions by southern white juries are one example of that class. Closely examined, however, those instances are likely to involve circumstances in which the rule of law would fail regardless of juries’ involvement.”). ... Close Or, if a group is not acting out of prejudice, the group may be acting with the knowledge that they are not contributing to the good of the greater commu­nity by supporting a defendant. And even with good intentions, a collective intervention in an individual case might still undermine broader goals of uniformity and regularity when social movement actors choose to intervene in some, but not other, courtrooms and cases.

Whether these communal interventions into individual cases seem prob­lematic will depend on one’s idea of the rule of law—a notoriously contested concept. 215 215 See, e.g., Fallon, supra note 42, at 10­–24 (describing four differing conceptions of the rule of law). ... Close For example, a traditional formalist conception of the rule of law, one insisting that judges must enforce all procedural rules in a neutral and uniform way, free of prejudice or popular med­dling, might clash with a vision of popular intervention on the side of defendants. 216 216 Compare id. at 18–19, 31­–32 (describing the Legal Process conception of the rule of law, which “attempt[s] to root law at least partly in a current normative consensus per­ceived as adequate to validate particular decisionmaking processes and their outcomes as lawful”), with supra notes 42–46 and accompanying text (describing a conception of the rule of law that focuses on systemic inputs during the lawmaking process and neutral applica­tion during the adjudication process). This formalist conception of the rule of law accords with what Philippe Nonet and Philip Selznick call “autonomous law,” in which “[r]egularity and fairness, not substantive justice, are the first ends and the main compe­tence of the legal order.” Nonet & Selznick, supra note 23, at 54. ... Close Opening up decisionmaking at the individual level to the impulsive or biased preferences of unelected groups would imperil the neutrality and generality of criminal justice on the ground. In contrast, a more “responsive” conception of the rule of law might welcome popular intervention when it allows members of the public to engage in the pro­cess of defining the contours of legal meaning in adjudication. 217 217 See, e.g., Nonet & Selznick, supra note 23, at 96 (defending the similar idea of legal pluralism, in which “legal action comes to serve as a vehicle by which groups and organizations may participate in the determination of public policy”); see also id. at 77 (describing responsive legal institutions as those which open themselves up to adaptation by “perceiv[ing] social pressures as sources of knowledge and opportunities for self-correc­tion”); Glen Staszewski, The Dumbing Down of Statutory Interpretation, 95 B.U. L. Rev. 209, 259 (2015) (“Responsive theories of law tend to be receptive to increased opportuni­ties for participation in the legal process and to relatively expansive notions of the role of law.”). ... Close This conception of the rule of law would welcome multiple sources of legal authority 218 218 See Brown, supra note 120, at 1161–66; see also id. at 1164 (“[T]he rule of law not only permits interpretation of rules through such sources [outside of the written law] in a manner that may yield results very different from literal rule application, but may require it.”); cf. Morton J. Horwitz, The Rule of Law: An Unqualified Human Good? , 86 Yale L.J. 561, 566 (1977) (book review) (“[The rule of law] creates formal equality—a not inconsiderable virtue—but it promotes substantive inequality by creating a consciousness that radically separates law from politics, means from ends, processes from outcomes.”). ... Close and might even welcome some ir regularity in the interest of promoting legal decisionmaking that is more responsive to social needs and local democratic inputs. Many communal interventions into every­day justice fit comfortably into an idea of the rule of law that encourages multiple sources of legal authority, including direct public participation. When community bail funds post bail, for example, they help shape legal and constitutional understandings of the institution of money bail and the meanings of concepts like “community” and “public safety.” 219 219 See Simonson, Bail Nullification, supra note 59, at 612–31 (describing how commu­nity bail funds contest the meaning of “community” and engage in legal and politi­cal change). ... Close Under a responsive ideal of the rule of law, such communal interventions on the side of defendants represent a desirable form of popular participation in the production of legal meaning.

One’s view of how communal resistance in the criminal courthouse fits within the rule of law will therefore go hand in hand with one’s concep­tion of how the contours of the rule of law interact with demo­cracy, participation, and lawmaking. Moreover, it will depend on how one views the potential of political engagement in individual criminal cases, a theme echoed in the scholarly debate over jury nullification. 220 220 Compare Brown, supra note 120, at 1169–71 (arguing that jury nullification falls within the rule of law), and Carroll, Nullification, supra note 120, at 621 (stating that jury nullification “creates a mechanism to lend predictability and knowability to the law when formal constructs have failed to align themselves with the citizen’s own expectations”), with Andrew D. Leipold, Rethinking Jury Nullification, 82 Va. L. Rev. 253, 299–300 (1996) (“There is some force to [the] arguments [for jury nullification], but not enough to justify the existing nullification doctrine.”), and Paul Butler, Racially Based Jury Nullification: Black Power in the Criminal Justice System , 105 Yale L.J. 677, 705 (1995) [hereinafter Butler, Black Power] (“The idea that jury nullification undermines the rule of law is the most common criticism of the doctrine.”). For a summary of this debate, see Kaimipono David Wenger & David A. Hoffman, Nullificatory Juries, 2003 Wis. L. Rev. 1115, 1131–33 (2003). ... Close Although beyond the scope of this Essay, this complex analysis will be an important job for future work: to parse through various mechanisms of facilitating popular participation, and to reject some while embracing others, along a range of conceptions of the rule of law and its relationship to substan­tive justice. For now, one might agree with the central argument of this Essay—that our methods of everyday adjudication would benefit from moving beyond a neat dichotomy between the interests of the public and the interests of the defendant—without endorsing all forms of communal resistance in the courthouse. And one could support changes in for­mal rules—for example, changing rules for posting bail that inhibit the work of community bail funds—in an effort to bring existing strategies of communal intervention in sync with formal ideals of the rule of law.

But this is not the end of the matter. Running alongside divergent con­ceptions of the rule of law is yet another idea: that we might need to set aside our complete fidelity to the rule of law (however conceived) in the face of widespread injustice. Carol Steiker’s writings on the relation­ship between mercy and the rule of law bring out this idea. Steiker argues that when institutional relationships result in overly harsh treatment and punishment of defendants, the idea of mercy can provide a “necessary counterbalance.” 221 221 Carol S. Steiker, Tempering or Tampering? Mercy and the Administration of Criminal Justice, in Forgiveness, Mercy, and Clemency 16, 31 (Austin Sarat & Nasser Hussain eds., 2007) [hereinafter Steiker, Tempering or Tampering]. ... Close In this account, opening up the processing of individ­ual criminal cases to mechanisms of discretionary mercy might be scary and unpredictable, and even run counter to the rule of law; and yet, the ideal of mercy may still be necessary to combat the harsh nature of everyday criminal justice. 222 222 Id. at 30–32; see also Carol S. Steiker, Sculpting the Shape of Nullification Through Jury Information and Instruction, in Criminal Law Conversations 553, 553–54 (Paul H. Robinson et al. eds., 2009) [hereinafter Steiker, Sculpting the Shape] (arguing that although jury nullification may be alarming in some instances, nullification is neces­sary to counteract the spread of mass incarceration). ... Close As Steiker writes of the alarming nature of some forms of jury nullification, “[I]n our time, the alternative—the unending spiral of mass incarceration—looks a lot worse.” 223 223 Steiker, Sculpting the Shape, supra note 222, at 554. ... Close In a similar vein, Paul Butler has written with respect to race-based jury nullification that “[i]f the rule of law is a myth, or at least is not applicable to African-Americans, the criticism that jury nullification undermines it loses force.” 224 224 Butler, Black Power, supra note 220, at 708. See generally Steiker, Tempering or Tampering, supra note 221 (arguing that mercy is a potentially appropriate way of mitigat­ing the “draconian harshness of our current penological regime”). ... Close Under this view of the relationship between justice and the rule of law, the importance of the rule of law bends in the face of widespread injustice such as that found in the American carceral state. If in the vast majority of cases we do not have a baseline of the rule of law, then our fidelity to it is misplaced.

This critique continues to resonate in the United States today, where we face an “unending spiral of mass incarceration,” in the context of a set of criminal procedures that lead people most impacted by everyday criminal adjudication to conclude that the rule of law is, indeed, a myth. This is especially true at the bottom of the “the penal pyramid,” where “rules hardly matter at all” as state actors rush poor people and people of color through the court system without careful attention, purpose-giving, or adjudication of guilt or innocence. 225 225 Natapoff, The Penal Pyramid, supra note 29, at 72. ... Close At the bottom of the penal pyramid, the rule of law begins to disappear. 226 226 Carroll, Nullification supra note 120, at 581 (“[A]dhering too closely to any particu­lar ideal of the rule of law leaves large swaths of the actual experience of govern­ance and lawmaking unaccounted for.”). ... Close This recognition might relax our idea of what kind of participation the system allows, up to when it clashes with due process concerns for individual defendants. 227 227 See Simonson, Audience, supra note 79, at 2204–05 (discussing how the individ­ual rights of a defendant to due process and a fair trial trump the rights of audience mem­bers to participate in everyday courtroom proceedings). ... Close Depend­ing on the “rules” governing any one mechanism of partici­pation, to open up the criminal courtroom to new forms of participation might require being comfortable undermining the rule of law in order to pro­mote larger ideals of substantive justice in an unequal or unfair system. Indeed, it may be that it is precisely these forms of popular participation that offer the greatest hope for pushing back against the “unending spi­ral[s]” of mass incarceration, supervision, and police vio­lence that make up the carceral state. Drawing inspiration from this conception of the place of the rule of law in a profoundly unjust system, in the next and last section of this Essay I gesture toward a direct connection between facilitat­ing communal interventions in criminal adjudication on behalf of defendants and the possibility of large-scale decarceration.

B. Procedure and the Possibility of Decarceration Today

We cannot separate out the intractability of mass incarceration from the powerlessness of those caught up in it. 228 228 See Walker, supra note 41, at 8 (“At every point in the history of [American] crimi­nal justice, the people arrested, prosecuted, and punished have been mainly the poor and powerless.”); Roberts, Constructing a Criminal Justice System, supra note 24, at 279–86; Moore, Decarceral Constitutionalism, supra note 80, at 9–11. ... Close Part of the path toward decar­ceration may therefore lie in opening up criminal justice institu­tions to the relatively powerless voices who have not played a large role in getting us to the place where we are. 229 229 Cf. Barker, supra note 133, at 2 (arguing that “increased democratization can support and sustain less coercive penal regimes” by bringing in less privileged political opinions); Miller, Mob Rule, supra note 133, at 8 (“The more non-elites can successfully influence government policy over collective securities— the more the mob rules —the more likely the political system will address security from violence as a collective good and will moderate its use of repressive practices.”); Sklansky, Democracy, supra note 27, at 191 (“[S]ensitivity to the oppositional side of democracy—the tradition of anti-inegalitarian­ism—can help to keep us focused on the ways in which policing can buttress, or alterna­tively can destabilize, entrenched patterns of illegitimate domination.”); Simon, supra note 205, at 1648–50 (arguing that the rising illegitimacy of the criminal justice system in the era of Black Lives Matter presents an opportunity for transformative change). ... Close There is reason to believe that if we open up criminal procedure to more popular input from below, the result would be a system that is profoundly skeptical of much of the status quo in criminal justice today. To be sure, not all bottom-up interventions on behalf of defendants will be interventions that we all can agree are good ones, but they will tend to be interventions that shift power imbalances: not just shifting power away from prosecution but also shifting power away from the dominant idea that the criminal legal system is the best and only way to contend with communal ills. In this way, opening up criminal procedure to allow “the People” to support defendants facili­tates discourses that are part of an “abolitionist ethic”—what Allegra McLeod describes as a “gradual project of decarceration,” changing how we think about the purposes of criminal law and proce­dures themselves. 230 230 Allegra M. McLeod, Prison Abolition and Grounded Justice, 62 UCLA L. Rev. 1156, 1161 (2015); see also Butler, Chokehold, supra note 208, at 229–47 (describing approaches to criminal justice reform that fit into an abolitionist ethic); Akbar, Radical Imagination, supra note 56, at 460–73 (describing the abolitionist ethic of the Movement for Black Lives). ... Close

Drawing a direct line between collective participation in individual cases and the larger project of decarceration surely requires more study. And perhaps recent electoral victories by “progressive” prosecutors, such as former civil rights lawyer Larry Krasner in Philadelphia, 231 231 See Harrison Jacobs, The Inside Story of How Trump United a City of Activists to Elect the Most Progressive District Attorney in a Generation, Bus. Insider (Nov. 12, 2017), https://www.businessinsider.com/larry-krasner-philadelphia-election-platform-trump-2017-11 [https://perma.cc/KL9U-9EPR]. ... Close undermine the notion that it is the only way to achieve decarceration. 232 232 See generally Sklansky, Progressive Prosecutor, supra note 184, at 26 (describing a growing number of prosecutors who have won local elections based on a “more balanced approach to criminal justice”). ... Close But, signifi­cantly, this is how movement actors engaging in collective practices on behalf of defendants understand their work: as a way to build the power necessary to truly transform criminal justice. When activists post bail for a stranger, or engage in a participatory defense campaign, they see them­selves as “practicing abolition every day” 233 233 Mariame Kaba, Take No Prisoners, Vice (Oct. 15, 2015), https://www.vice.com/en_us/article/mending-our-ways-0000775-v22n10 [https://perma.cc/X86N-FTEJ] (describ­­­ing how a number of activist organizations, includ­ing that of the author, “are practicing abolition every day . . . by creating local pro­jects and initiatives that offer alternative ideas and structures for mediating conflicts and addressing harms without relying on police or prisons”). ... Close and engaging in “abolition in the now” 234 234 Grant, supra note 65 (quoting Mary Hooks of SONG as describing Mama’s Bail Out Day as a form of “abolition in the now”). ... Close —moving away from the incarceration of poor people and people of color, and toward other ways of addressing wrongdoing and promoting public safety. These movement actors bring with them sophisti­cated understandings of the history and discourse surrounding seemingly neutral procedures—their intention is not simply to intervene using existing procedures but also to disrupt the normalcy of those proce­dures by laying bare the ways in which they function to perpetuate structural inequalities. 235 235 Cf. Akbar, Radical Imagination, supra note 56, at 421–60 (describing the nuanced legal thinking of social movement actors in the Movement for Black Lives). ... Close With bail, for example, the goal of community bail funds is rarely to become permanent fixtures of a local pretrial sys­tem, but rather to push for the abolition of bail and even pretrial detention altogether. 236 236 See Brian Sonenstein, As Abolition Becomes More Likely, Chicago Bond Fund Sees Future Where They Aren’t Needed, Shadowproof (May 9, 2017), https://shadowproof.com/2017/05/09/chicago-bond-fund-series-part-two/ [https://perma.cc/ 2MLF-UXC7]; see also Weiss, supra note 59 (describing the abolition­ist goals of many community bail funds, which aim to “create space to identify and then experiment with new structures that hold people in crisis in ways that are not punitive but instead account­able to communities and concerned with repair and prevention”). Bail funds demonstrate, for example, that “transformative” bail reform will require “a histori­cally grounded under­standing of the inherent anti-Blackness of our criminal punishment system and an exploration of how many proposed reforms continue to re-entrench oppres­sion and to prioritize profit over people.” Color of Change et al., Transformative Bail Reform: A Popular Education Curriculum 3 (2016), https://policy.m4bl.org/wp-con­tent/uploads/2016/07/Transformative-Bail-Reform-5.pdf [https://perma.cc/2NXA-XMZK]. ... Close These groups do not simply study or document widespread forms of inequality; rather, they practice the undoing of those forms of inequality through collective acts of intervention in individ­ual cases.

Communal support of a defendant can thus be disruptive in the sense that it can call into question basic assumptions about the operation of everyday justice. But such collective resistance is not mere protest or civil disobedience; it is a method of democratic contestation over the mean­ing of justice in a structured and civil setting. Agonistic participa­tion is a way to bring in collective viewpoints that call into question our modes of criminal law and procedure themselves and yet do so under regulated conditions that demand respect for both sides. 237 237 See Mouffe, Agonistics, supra note 25, at 9 (“In an agonistic politics, . . . what is at stake is the struggle between opposing hegemonic projects which can never be reconciled rationally, one of them needing to be defeated. It is a real confrontation . . . played out under conditions regulated by a set of democratic procedures accepted by the adver­saries.”). ... Close To allow the people in on both sides does not require that we abolish the police, end all prosecutions of misdemeanors, or close all jails and prisons, but it does demand that we be open to putting those options on the table. 238 238 Cf. Akbar, Radical Imagination, supra note 56, at 471 (“One might disagree with the argument to abolish police, but having the debate is itself productive, as it forces conversa­tions about the otherwise-taken-for-granted values of police and incarceration.”); Simon, supra note 205, at 1650 (describing the need “to lay the ground work for any seri­ous democratic discourse over how to reshape the carceral state”). ... Close In this way, constructing criminal procedures so that they allow participa­tion on the side of the defendant can help produce a more substantial public discourse over legal, political, and constitutional meaning in the realm of criminal law.

Maintaining an adversarial system with the people on both sides makes room for forms of popular intervention that either deny that a wrong has been committed at all, or, more provocatively, seek to unearth the ways in which the allegation of a wrong can serve as a cover for forms of social control and group domination. Our consensus-based methods of trying to facilitate discussions and deliberation around issues of local justice have not been up to the task of lifting up these ideas on their own. Moving beyond consensus, we can also create contestatory spaces in which the public can hash out competing perspectives on the meaning of justice in their communities, pushing us to consider new ways of thinking about and reacting to violent or undesirable conduct. If these voices, opin­ions, and visions are not a part of the discourse around criminal law and procedure, then we risk failing to ask ourselves the most difficult ques­tions about whether our dominant modes of processing criminal cases are right or just. Public participation on both sides of criminal cases therefore carries with it the potential to lead us not just to more demo­cratic criminal law but also to less criminal law. 239 239 It is no coincidence that Nonet and Selznick, in their typology of conceptions of the rule of law, identified “responsive law” with a decrease in the use of the criminal law and criminal sanctions overall. See Nonet & Selznick, supra note 23, at 89–92 (describing how responsive law involves a reduction in the use of criminal sanctions). ... Close

Herbert Packer believed that by theorizing competing models of crimi­nal procedure, he could in turn shift on-the-ground practices and understandings of why and what we punish. 240 240 In particular, Packer believed that the preferable model—the “due process model”—would provide enough roadblocks to “assembly-line justice” so as to make us realize the need to eliminate “the endless procession of look-alike cases, especially through the lower criminal courts.” Packer, Limits, supra note 28, at 292; cf. Aviram, supra note 29, at 238–45 (analyzing Herbert Packer’s models of criminal procedure within the context of the Warren Court’s criminal procedure jurisprudence). ... Close At the same time, Packer cautioned that there was a limit to due process, writing that “[w]e sorely need to . . . ask ‘what’ and ‘why’ [we punish] before we ask ‘how.’” 241 241 Packer, Limits, supra note 28, at 366. ... Close In this Essay, I have attempted to argue the inverse proposition: By expanding the “how”—by opening up our procedures to communal contesta­tion—we can facilitate more productive interchanges on “what” and “why” criminal adjudication should be. Without the voices of the most marginalized, that conversation—over the meaning of justice, over how to best respond to wrongdoing—will not truly reflect the full scope of the multiple publics who are a part of everyday justice.

We are in the throes of a new age of local criminal law and policy reform in the United States, reform that goes beyond changing substan­tive criminal law statutes and rewriting sentencing laws to include big-picture rethinking of our criminal processes. If we can value public participa­tion beyond representation by the police and prosecution, then we can open up our visions of how we craft criminal procedure and inter­pret doctrine in new and important ways, moving toward local criminal adjudication that is more responsive to the multidimensional demands of the popular will.

Library homepage

  • school Campus Bookshelves
  • menu_book Bookshelves
  • perm_media Learning Objects
  • login Login
  • how_to_reg Request Instructor Account
  • hub Instructor Commons
  • Download Page (PDF)
  • Download Full Book (PDF)
  • Periodic Table
  • Physics Constants
  • Scientific Calculator
  • Reference & Cite
  • Tools expand_more
  • Readability

selected template will load here

This action is not available.

Workforce LibreTexts

2: Why Is Criminal Procedure So Important?

  • Last updated
  • Save as PDF
  • Page ID 25584
  • 2.1: Introduction
  • 2.2: Brown v. Mississippi (1936)
  • 2.3: What to Look for When Reading Cases
  • 2.4: The Scope of the Criminal Justice System
  • 2.5: A Few Recent Cases
  • 0 Shopping Cart $ 0.00 -->

JD Advising

Did you fail the bar exam? We have lots of free resources to help you regroup for your next attempt! Check out our guide on what to do if you failed the bar exam , as well as our guide on hiring a bar exam tutor ! And be sure to register for our FREE Failed the Bar Exam Mastery Class (includes daily giveaways)!

Ace Your Law Finals! 🌟 Boost your GPA and class rank with expert private tutoring & premium Law School Study Aids . Elevate your legal mastery — Start Today!

Need a bar exam score boost? Looking for one-on-one attention in your bar prep? Our expert bar exam tutors are ready to help you pass! Sign up early before spots fill up!

Chapter 10: How to Conquer Criminal Law and Procedure on the California Bar Exam

Criminal law and procedure on the california bar exam.

Criminal Law and Procedure is regularly tested on the California Bar Exam (about once every other year).

Criminal Law and Procedure is somewhat predictable in terms of how it is tested. Further, the California State Bar tends not to test California distinctions on Criminal Law and Procedure questions, which makes studying for Criminal Law and Procedure a little easier than some of the other California Bar Exam subjects.

Below, we tell you how to approach Criminal Law and Procedure on the essay portion of the California Bar Exam.

1. First, know how Criminal Law and Procedure is tested.  

The California Bar Exam has virtually always tested general law (rather than California law) on Criminal Law and Procedure essay questions, as noted above.

Sometimes Criminal Law is tested. Other times, Criminal Procedure is tested. And often, they are combined together.

Criminal Law and Procedure has not been tested with another subject since 2008. Before 2008, it was tested with Constitutional Law and Evidence.

2. Be aware of the highly tested issues. 

The State Bar of California does not reinvent the wheel every time it writes a Criminal Law and Procedure question. Rather, there are certain issues that appear repeatedly in Criminal Law and Procedure questions on the California Bar Exam (We have a nice summary of these in our  California Bar Exam One-Sheets . Click on the link to see a sample!)

Some highly tested Criminal Law and Procedure issues on the essay portion of the California Bar Exam include the following:

  • First-degree murder: requires both  premeditation  and  deliberation.
  • Intent to cause  grievous bodily harm and the victim ends up dying.
  • Extreme recklessness regarding homicidal risk and someone dies (depraved-heart murder).
  • Intent to kill but without premeditation and deliberation and the victim dies.
  • Voluntary manslaughter : The  intentional killing of a human being  without malice aforethought committed in the  heat of passion due to  adequate provocation .
  • Involuntary manslaughter:  This is (1) the killing of another human being due to  recklessness or  gross negligence,  or (2) a killing during the commission of a misdemeanor or a felony that does not qualify for felony murder .

Homicide Chart

  • Theft crimes: These include larceny, robbery , burglary , and receiving stolen goods .

Larceny Burglary Robbery

  • Inchoate crimes: These include attempt (occasionally tested with kidnapping), conspiracy , and solicitation . Attempt is the most highly tested inchoate crime and requires that the defendant have the specific intent to commit the crime and that the defendant get dangerously close to completing the crime.
  • The Fourth Amendment: this expansive topic is the most highly tested Criminal Procedure topic on California Bar Exam essay questions!

The Fourth Amendment applies to

  • Fifth Amendment Miranda rights: this is the second most highly tested Criminal Procedure topic.

When Are Miranda Rights Required?

3. Make sure you have the rules and important legal terms memorized!

Memorize the rules.

Criminal Law is very rules-based. Oftentimes, if you memorize the elements of the law, applying them is pretty straightforward. This will help you on both the essay portion and the MBE portion of the California Bar Exam! Please read these tips on how to  memorize your bar exam outlines  if you are not sure where to begin.

Criminal Procedure is very case-based. So, you will be expected to know some terminology from cases and even references to case names (e.g., “ Miranda ,” “ Terry ,” etc.). By using the proper legal vocabulary, the grader will see that you know what you are talking about!

Some important Criminal Procedure rules

Below we list a few important Criminal Procedure terms. This is not a complete list. Rather, we hope it inspires you to make your own list of important legal terms, especially if you did not take Criminal Procedure in law school.

  • Fifth Amendment Miranda rights attach upon a  custodial interrogation .
  • To invoke the right to remain silent , the invocation must be  explicit, unambiguous, and unequivocal .

Invocation of the right to remain silent must be

  • The Fourth Amendment attaches when there is a  reasonable expectation of privacy .

Who has a reasonable expectation of privacy

  • Generally, a search or seizure under the Fourth Amendment requires  probable cause .
  • For a  Terry  stop , the police officer needs  reasonable suspicion   that  criminal activity is afoot .
  • For a  Terry  frisk , the police officer needs a  reasonable belief   that the suspect is  armed and dangerous .

Terry Stop and Frisk Cases

4. Practice! 

This is always our final tip because it is so important! The best way to become proficient at Criminal Law and Procedure essay questions is to practice writing answers to essay questions. This will help you become acquainted with how Criminal Law and Procedure is tested (including how it sometimes appears with other subjects, like Constitutional Law). And, it will help you master the highly tested issues.

Here are a few essay questions with student answers that we recommend you practice to get exposed to some highly tested topics in Criminal Law and Procedure essay questions:

  • October 2020 Criminal Law and Procedure essay: this essay covers Criminal Law, Criminal Procedure, accomplice liability, burglary, larceny, conspiracy, duress, lineups, and the Fourteenth Amendment Due Process Clause (see essay question #4 on the exam).
  • July 2019 Criminal Law and Procedure essay : this essay covers Criminal Law, Criminal Procedure, the Fourth Amendment, and robbery (see essay question #3 on the exam).
  • February 2018 Criminal Law and Procedure essay: this essay covers Criminal Law, Criminal Procedure, the Fourth Amendment, plain-view exception, exclusionary rule, inevitable discovery, attempt, and kidnapping (see essay question #4 on the exam).
  • February 2017 Criminal Law and Procedure essay: this essay covers Criminal Law, Criminal Procedure, the Fourth Amendment, search incident to lawful arrest, the Fifth Amendment, and solicitation (see essay question #6 on the exam).
  • July 2015 Criminal Law and Procedure essay: this essay covers Criminal Procedure, the Fourth Amendment, the exclusionary rule, the reasonable expectation of privacy, and the plain-view exception (see essay question #3 on the exam).

Good luck studying for the California Bar Exam!

Go to the next topic, Chapter 11: Evidence .

Looking to pass the california bar exam.

📚 Ready to Conquer the California Bar Exam?

  • Free Bar Exam Resource Center : Your gateway to handpicked guides, webinars, and articles.
  • Expert-Written Bar Exam Guides : Get a CA bar exam essay guide, strategies for passing, and advice on choosing the ideal tutor.  

Top Resources Recommended by our Students:

  • Bar Exam Outlines : Our comprehensive and condensed bar exam outlines present key information in an organized, easy-to-digest layout.
  • California One-Sheets and Baby Bar One-Sheets : Consistently 5-star rated by our students.
  • California Essay Exam Mastery Class : Target the most tested and challenging California bar segments.
  • California and Baby Bar Exam Private Tutoring : Get personalized tutoring by bar exam experts.
  • On Demand Bar Exam Course : 5-star rated for your comprehensive preparation. Free course preview available!
  • Real MBE Questions : Perfect your practice with the best of practice materials.

🔥 NEW! Check out our Repeat Taker Bar Exam Course and our unrivaled platinum Guarantee Pass Program !

Related posts

bar Exam as an LLM

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms of Use
  • Public Interest

By using this site, you allow the use of cookies, and you acknowledge that you have read and understand our Privacy Policy and Terms of Service .

Cookie and Privacy Settings

We may request cookies to be set on your device. We use cookies to let us know when you visit our websites, how you interact with us, to enrich your user experience, and to customize your relationship with our website.

Click on the different category headings to find out more. You can also change some of your preferences. Note that blocking some types of cookies may impact your experience on our websites and the services we are able to offer.

These cookies are strictly necessary to provide you with services available through our website and to use some of its features.

Because these cookies are strictly necessary to deliver the website, refusing them will have impact how our site functions. You always can block or delete cookies by changing your browser settings and force blocking all cookies on this website. But this will always prompt you to accept/refuse cookies when revisiting our site.

We fully respect if you want to refuse cookies but to avoid asking you again and again kindly allow us to store a cookie for that. You are free to opt out any time or opt in for other cookies to get a better experience. If you refuse cookies we will remove all set cookies in our domain.

We provide you with a list of stored cookies on your computer in our domain so you can check what we stored. Due to security reasons we are not able to show or modify cookies from other domains. You can check these in your browser security settings.

We also use different external services like Google Webfonts, Google Maps, and external Video providers. Since these providers may collect personal data like your IP address we allow you to block them here. Please be aware that this might heavily reduce the functionality and appearance of our site. Changes will take effect once you reload the page.

Google Webfont Settings:

Google Map Settings:

Google reCaptcha Settings:

Vimeo and Youtube video embeds:

You can read about our cookies and privacy settings in detail on our Privacy Policy Page.

Advertisement

Supported by

Behind the Journalism

How The Times Is Covering the Trump Hush-Money Trial

Our reporting team will be live at the courthouse in Manhattan every day.

  • Share full article

By The New York Times

The New York Times will provide comprehensive live coverage of the first criminal trial of former President Donald J. Trump, which is set to begin on Monday, April 15, and last six to eight weeks, including jury selection. Mr. Trump has been charged with making illegal hush-money payments to a porn star during the 2016 campaign.

Our Coverage

Starting with opening statements, we will be live every day the trial is in session, with reporters at the courthouse in Lower Manhattan. Proceedings will generally occur four days a week, with Wednesdays off, starting at 9:30 a.m. and going until 4:30 p.m. or later. The trial won’t be televised, but reporters will be able to post items from the courtroom and a nearby overflow room. Our photographers will be there too, but will be limited to just 45 seconds of access to the courtroom each day, before the proceedings begin.

We will provide daily takeaways and analysis, explanations of the criminal trial process, explanatory videos, profiles of the defense and prosecution teams, and answers to questions about the case.

You can find all our coverage here — and of course on our homepage and our app.

Sign up for our newsletter, Trump on Trial, to get the latest updates in your inbox.

Donald Trump stands in a courtroom hallway among security officers.

Our Reporting Team

A team of reporters, editors and photographers from across The Times’s Metro, Politics and Investigations departments has been deployed to cover this trial, the first criminal trial of an American president.

Our core courthouse team, which has been preparing for months for the trial, includes reporters with decades of criminal justice experience; deep knowledge of Mr. Trump’s financial, business and legal history; and a nuanced understanding of the political implications of what may be the only trial Mr. Trump faces before the November election, despite multiple indictments. The team includes:

Jonah E. Bromwich covers criminal justice in New York, with a focus on the Manhattan district attorney’s office and state criminal courts in Manhattan.

Kate Christobek became a reporter in 2020 after practicing law for close to a decade. She was an assistant district attorney in New York City and an assistant attorney general for the State of Ohio.

Susanne Craig , an investigative reporter, has spent years examining Mr. Trump’s finances, including the origins of his wealth and the legally questionable techniques he has used to avoid paying millions of dollars of income tax.

Alan Feuer has been writing about crime and criminal justice for The Times since 1999. In recent years, he has been closely tracking the hundreds of cases stemming from the attack on the Capitol by a pro-Trump mob.

Maggie Haberman , a senior political correspondent, has covered Mr. Trump since his days as a New York City real estate developer and wrote a biography of the former president.

Jesse McKinley , a reporter on the Metro desk, covers New York courts and politics.

Ben Protess , an investigative reporter, has been focused almost exclusively on Mr. Trump for the past six years, covering his family business, his administration and his legal problems.

William K. Rashbaum , who has been a reporter for 40 years, focuses on political and municipal corruption, the courts and law enforcement in New York City.

Jonathan Swan , a Times political reporter covering the former president’s 2024 campaign, has been reporting on Mr. Trump for more than eight years.

Your Questions

We’re asking readers what they’d like to know about the Trump trial — whether related to the charges, the procedure, the important players or anything else. Submit your questions below and we’ll take them to our reporters, who will answer some of them in the Trump on Trial newsletter .

Your questions about the Trump trials

Our coverage of the trump hush-money case, the manhattan district attorney has filed charges against former president donald trump over a hush-money payment to a porn star on the eve of the 2016 election..

Taking the Case to Trial: Trump is all but certain to become the first former U.S. president to stand trial on criminal charges after a judge denied his effort to delay the proceeding and confirmed it will begin on April 15 .

Implications for Trump: As the case goes to trial, the former president’s inner circle sees a silver lining in the timing. But Trump wouldn’t be able to pardon himself  should he become president again as he could if found guilty in the federal cases against him.

Michael Cohen: Trump’s former fixer was not an essential witness in the former president’s civil fraud trial in New York  that concluded in January. But he will be when he takes the stand in the hush-money case .

Stormy Daniels: The chain of events flowing from a 2006 encounter that the adult film star said she had with Trump has led to the brink of a historic trial. Here's a look inside the hush-money payout .

Political Wire

Matt Gaetz Is Winning But What’s the Prize?

April 11, 2024 at 8:34 am EDT By Taegan Goddard Leave a Comment

The Atlantic runs a great profile of Rep. Matt Gaetz (R-FL).

“Few items in Gaetz’s biography are more on the nose than the fact that his childhood vacation home—which his family still owns—was the pink-and-yellow-trimmed house along the Gulf of Mexico that was used to film the The Truman Show , the movie about a man whose entire life is a performance for public consumption.”

Favorite

Recent Posts

Obituary mixes up trump with o.j. simpson.

A Los Angeles Times obituary for O.J. Simpson accidentally used the name “Trump” in place of “Simpson” near the end of their obituary describing the former football star leaving prison….

Mike Johnson Pulled In More Than $20 Million Last Quarter

Politico: “The Louisiana Republican has worked aggressively to meet high expectations of him on the fundraising circuit, and his high intake during his first full quarter in the job indicates…

GOP Lawmaker Wanted to Allow First Cousins to Marry

The Tennessee House passed a bill on Thursday that would make it illegal to marry your first cousin in Tennessee, WSMV reports. But it only did so after state Rep….

Trump Takes Over Congressional GOP Agenda

“Donald Trump is tightening his stranglehold on the congressional GOP’s policy agenda as he reshapes Republican lawmakers’ party orthodoxy on national security and social issues,” Politico reports. “Trump’s sway was…

Trump to Push Bill to Prevent Non-Citizens from Voting

Speaker Mike Johnson (R-LA) will promote a bill with Donald Trump “aimed at preventing non-citizens from voting,” USA Today reports. “Johnson will hold a joint press conference with Trump on…

Georgia Lt. Governor Probed in Fake Elector Scheme

“State prosecutor Pete Skandalakis said Thursday that he will lead the investigation into Lt. Gov. Burt Jones’ (R) alleged role in trying to help former President Donald Trump overturn the…

How Voters Describe the Election in One Word

Nate Cohn: “About a third of voters gave responses indicating anger, disappointment or resignation. And nearly as many respondents — 30 percent — replied with words indicating that they were…

A Famine Has Begun in Gaza

New York Times: “The director of the U.S. Agency for International Development told lawmakers this week that a famine is underway in northern Gaza, which has been devastated by six…

Biden Launches Ad Buy on Abortion in Arizona

“President Biden’s campaign on Thursday launched a seven-figure ad buy in Arizona, focusing on abortion on as the state grapples with the fallout from a state Supreme Court decision earlier…

What Swing Voters Care About

The Economist: “Swing voters do not view this year’s election as Republicans would like them to: immigration is not the most important issue for them. Neither do they view it…

Biden Could Drop Charges Against Julian Assange

“Julian Assange’s supporters appeared energized Thursday by President Biden’s comment that the United States is ‘considering’ a request to drop its push to prosecute the WikiLeaks founder,” the Washington Post…

Wisconsin Supreme Court Liberal Won’t Run Again

“The longest-serving member of the Wisconsin Supreme Court’s 4-3 liberal majority announced Thursday she would not run for reelection next spring, shaking up a consequential race in a swing state…

Trump Flails on Abortion

After weeks of trying to come up with yet another position on abortion, Donald Trump thought he was clever to finally say on Monday that he would just leave it…

Trump Could Still Serve If Convicted

Washington Post: “Donald Trump is facing felony charges in four separate criminal indictments in three states and Washington, D.C., with a guilty verdict in any of the cases possibly meaning…

Conversation with Simon Rosenberg

I’m pleased to announced I’ll be holding a private video conversation with veteran Democratic strategist Simon Rosenberg on Tuesday, April 16 at 2 p.m. ET. I’ll be sending an invitation…

Trump Says States Could Punish Abortion Doctors

When asked whether doctors who provide abortions should be punished, Donald Trump said that certain states could do that, the Washington Post reports. Said Trump: “I’d let that be to…

Democrats See Abortion and Immigration as Top Issues

Punchbowl News: “A national DCCC-commissioned poll of more than 1,000 likely voters in 63 competitive House battleground districts found that immigration and abortion were the top two ‘dealbreaker’ issues for…

Navalny Wrote a Memoir Before He Died

“During the years leading up to his death in a Russian prison, Aleksei Navalny, the Russian opposition leader, was writing a memoir about his life and work as a pro-democracy…

Arizona Is Ground Zero for the 2024 Election

“Suddenly, Arizona is ground zero for the hottest political conflicts driving the 2024 campaign,” Axios reports. “It’s not just that its reinstated, Civil War-era abortion ban and its border crisis…

Plurality Back Abortion Rights Measure in Florida

A new Emerson College Polling survey in Florida finds 42% of voters plan to vote yes on the November ballot measure that will provide a constitutional right to abortion before…

About Political Wire

goddard-bw-snapshot

Goddard spent more than a decade as managing director and chief operating officer of a prominent investment firm in New York City. Previously, he was a policy adviser to a U.S. Senator and Governor.

Goddard is also co-author of You Won - Now What? (Scribner, 1998), a political management book hailed by prominent journalists and politicians from both parties. In addition, Goddard's essays on politics and public policy have appeared in dozens of newspapers across the country.

Goddard earned degrees from Vassar College and Harvard University. He lives in New York with his wife and three sons.

Goddard is the owner of Goddard Media LLC .

Praise for Political Wire

“There are a lot of blogs and news sites claiming to understand politics, but only a few actually do. Political Wire is one of them.”

— Chuck Todd, host of “Meet the Press”

“Concise. Relevant. To the point. Political Wire is the first site I check when I’m looking for the latest political nugget. That pretty much says it all.”

— Stuart Rothenberg, editor of the Rothenberg Political Report

“Political Wire is one of only four or five sites that I check every day and sometimes several times a day, for the latest political news and developments.”

— Charlie Cook, editor of the Cook Political Report

“The big news, delicious tidbits, pearls of wisdom — nicely packaged, constantly updated… What political junkie could ask for more?”

— Larry Sabato, Center for Politics, University of Virginia

“Political Wire is a great, great site.”

— Joe Scarborough, host of MSNBC’s “Morning Joe”

“Taegan Goddard has a knack for digging out political gems that too often get passed over by the mainstream press, and for delivering the latest electoral developments in a sharp, no frills style that makes his Political Wire an addictive blog habit you don’t want to kick.”

— Arianna Huffington, founder of The Huffington Post

“Political Wire is one of the absolute must-read sites in the blogosphere.”

— Glenn Reynolds, founder of Instapundit

“I rely on Taegan Goddard’s Political Wire for straight, fair political news, he gets right to the point. It’s an eagerly anticipated part of my news reading.”

— Craig Newmark, founder of Craigslist.

IMAGES

  1. PPT

    what is criminal procedure essay

  2. Criminal Investigation Process Essay

    what is criminal procedure essay

  3. PPT

    what is criminal procedure essay

  4. Criminal Investigation Process Essay

    what is criminal procedure essay

  5. The Law of Criminal Procedure

    what is criminal procedure essay

  6. Criminal Procedure

    what is criminal procedure essay

VIDEO

  1. criminal courts in pakistan

  2. Definition of Inquiry & Investigation

  3. Focusing During Your Final Weeks of Prep With Jonathan Grossman (Webinar recording)

  4. Criminal Procedure Code

  5. CA Bar Exam Essay Workshop with Criminal Law and Procedure Essay insight with BarMD

  6. Law School Explained: What is Criminal Law

COMMENTS

  1. 92 Criminal Procedure Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

    The view of the role of the judiciary and the rule of law in society is also provided in the paper. Steps of Criminal Procedure in US. If law-enforcing agents conducting the arrest violate any of the provisions, then the arrestees have the right to refuse all the prosecution evidences presented in court. Criminal Procedure Policy.

  2. 130 Criminal Procedure Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

    130 Criminal Procedure Essay Topic Ideas & Examples. Criminal procedure is a vital aspect of the legal system that ensures fairness and justice for all individuals involved in criminal cases. If you are a law student or a legal professional looking for essay topic ideas in criminal procedure, you have come to the right place. ...

  3. Criminal Procedure Assignment: [Essay Example], 785 words

    Criminal procedure is a vital aspect of the legal system that governs how criminal cases are handled from investigation to trial. In today's world, with the increasing complexities of crime and advancements in technology, understanding and analyzing criminal procedure is more important than ever. This essay will delve into the specific aspect ...

  4. criminal procedure

    Criminal procedure deals with the set of rules governing the series of proceedings through which the government enforces substantive criminal law. Municipalities, states, and the federal government each have their own criminal codes, defining types of conduct that constitute crimes . Title 18 of the U.S. Code outlines all federal crimes.

  5. PDF CRIMINAL PROCEDURE ESSAY WORKSHOP

    Then, discuss the search and seizure of items. A seizure occurs if under the totality of circumstances, a reasonable person would not feel free to leave. Types of seizure include arrest, stop and frisk, police checkpoints, and traffic stops. An arrest in the defendant's home generally requires an arrest warrant.

  6. PDF Scott Pearce's Master Essay Method Criminal Law & Procedure

    Scott Pearce's Master Essay Method - Criminal Law and Procedure Approach CRIMINAL LAW AND PROCEDURE APPROACH Minimalist Approach I. Criminal Procedure is more important and more complicated than Criminal Law. II. Criminal Procedure is the other way the Examiners test Constitutional Law: A. 4th Amendment: unreasonable searches or seizures

  7. Criminal Procedure: Arrest

    Criminal procedures help to protect suspected criminals from indiscriminate treatment and harassment from law enforcing agents, hence protect suspects' and defendants' constitutional rights. All law enforcing agents must follow these procedures from the original encounter with suspects, arrest, investigation, trial, sentencing, and appeal.

  8. PDF NYU School of Law Outline: Criminal Procedure, Erin Murphy

    The criminal justice system, however, is a system. It has more than just cops{legislators, prosecutors, district attorneys, judges...and a system can adjust. Most crimes are handled at the state level, because of federalism. About ten times as many people are incarcerated by the States as by the Federal government.

  9. 1.2 Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure

    This book focuses on criminal law, but it occasionally touches on issues of criminal procedure, so it is important to differentiate between the two.. Criminal law generally defines the rights and obligations of individuals in society. Some common issues in criminal law are the elements of specific crimes and the elements of various criminal defenses.

  10. The Yale Law Journal

    This Essay asks whether federal criminal defendants receive fairer process today than they did in 1963, when Gideon v. Wainwright was decided. It concludes that in many situations they do not; indeed, they often receive far worse. ... Criminal procedure largely ignores remorse and apology or, at most, uses them as proxies for an individual ...

  11. Research Guides: Study Aids & Exam Prep: Criminal Procedure

    Gilbert Law Summary on Criminal Procedure by Paul Marcus; Melanie Wilson A criminal procedure outline that highlights all of the key criminal procedure decisions from the U.S. Supreme Court in an easy-to-read and easy-to-understand format that includes check lists, visual aids, and practice exam questions (and answers) -- both essay and short ...

  12. Procedural Justice in the Criminal Justice System

    Here procedural justice is defined as "an individual's perception of the fairness of procedural components of the social system that regulate the allocative process" (Leventhal, 1980, p. 35). In other words, Leventhal was interested in the way fairness impacts on perceptions of decision-making processes.

  13. CRIMINAL PROCEDURE AND THE GOOD CITIZEN

    Criminal Procedure and the Good Citizen surfaces this aspect of the Court's criminal procedure decisions to explore a series of questions about the nature of power, ... This Essay addresses these concerns. And it takes a first step in imagining a space in which citizens would have the ability, without repercussions or recrimination, to talk ...

  14. Overview of Procedural Due Process in Criminal Cases

    Jump to essay-3 While the following essays focus primarily on Supreme Court litigation challenging state criminal procedures, some of the cases cited discuss federal criminal procedures. See also Amdt5.6.1 Overview of Due Process Procedural Requirements. The doctrine of incorporation applies only to state government action in criminal cases ...

  15. Criminal Law and Procedure on the Multistate Essay Exam: Highly Tested

    In both cases, a Miranda issue was tested with hearsay. 2. Be aware of the highly tested Criminal Law and Procedure issues. The examiners tend to test several of the same issues in Criminal Law and Procedure MEE questions. You can maximize your score by being aware of these highly tested issues.

  16. The Place of "The People" in Criminal Procedure

    This Essay puts forth a new, alternative approach to thinking about popular participa­tion in criminal procedure, an approach that recognizes that "the People" can and do appear on both sides of the scale of justice. This recogni­tion casts new light on the role of bottom-up resistance to local police actions and prosecutions—such as ...

  17. PDF Criminal Procedure

    Reasonable or articulable suspicion of criminal activity is needed for an investigatory stop. 3. A stop is less intrusive than an arrest. 4. A frisk is allowed if there is reasonable suspicion that a person is presently armed and dangerous. 5. The frisk is limited to a search for weapons. 6. The search of the wallet could not be justified as a ...

  18. What is the Purpose of the Criminal Procedure Code

    What is the Purpose of the Criminal Procedure Code. The basic purpose of the Criminal Procedure Code, among other things, is to ensure a fair trial where none of the rights of the accused are compromised nor are they unjustifiably favoured. Furthermore, to ensure that the judge concerned hears all parties who are relevant to the trial, their ...

  19. Criminal Procedure Essays (Examples)

    Criminal Procedure Law. This document outlines the proposed criminal justice system. Its aim is to prevent and control crime and criminal acts through punitive measures and penalties to those who violate the set laws. The paper is a suggested criminal justice system for a national jurisdiction, at the federal level.

  20. 2: Why Is Criminal Procedure So Important?

    Workbench. Criminal Procedure - Undergraduate Edition (Smith) 2: Why Is Criminal Procedure So Important? Expand/collapse global location.

  21. Chapter 10: How to Conquer Criminal Law and Procedure on the California

    1. First, know how Criminal Law and Procedure is tested. The California Bar Exam has virtually always tested general law (rather than California law) on Criminal Law and Procedure essay questions, as noted above. Sometimes Criminal Law is tested. Other times, Criminal Procedure is tested.

  22. Opinion

    Mr. Lat writes about the legal profession. Mr. Shemtob is a lawyer. For months now, the country has been riveted by the four criminal cases against Donald Trump: the New York state case involving ...

  23. Ghana: Criminal Procedure Law Amended to Introduce Broad Use of Plea

    On July 22, 2022, Ghana amended its Criminal and Other Offences (Procedure) Act, 1960 (Criminal Procedure Code, Act 30), to add sections on plea bargaining. Before the president's assent to the Criminal and Other Offences (Procedure) Amendment Act, 2022 (Act 1079), the laws of Ghana allowed plea bargaining only in limited instances. Section 35 of … Continue reading "Ghana ...

  24. How The Times Is Covering the Trump Hush-Money Trial

    We will provide daily takeaways and analysis, explanations of the criminal trial process, explanatory videos, profiles of the defense and prosecution teams, and answers to questions about the case.

  25. Matt Gaetz Is Winning But What's the Prize?

    The Atlantic runs a great profile of Rep. Matt Gaetz (R-FL). "Few items in Gaetz's biography are more on the nose than the fact that his childhood vacation home—which his family still owns—was the pink-and-yellow-trimmed house along the Gulf of Mexico that was used to film the The Truman Show, the movie about a man whose entire life is a performance for public consumption."

  26. Criminal Procedure Regulation 2017

    (Criminal Procedure Act 1986: section 265 (1) (b)) To [insert name of person charged] charged with the offence of [insert offence] before the [insert name of court]. You have a right to make an election The offence with which you have been charged is an indictable offence. That means that you may be dealt with by