Newest Articles

  • Exploring Aristotle's Four Causes
  • Exploring Infallibility, Verifiability, and the Coherence Theory of Truth
  • Exploring the Nature of Art
  • Understanding Normative Ethics
  • Metaphysics
  • Theory of Forms
  • Epistemology
  • Materialism
  • Moral relativism
  • Utilitarianism
  • Virtue ethics
  • Normative ethics
  • Applied ethics
  • Moral Psychology
  • Philosophy of art
  • Philosophy of language
  • Philosophy of beauty
  • Nature of Art
  • Philosophy of Film
  • Philosophy of Music
  • Deductive reasoning
  • Inductive reasoning
  • Justification
  • Perception and Knowledge
  • Beliefs and Truth
  • Modern philosophy
  • Romanticism
  • Analytic philosophy
  • Enlightenment philosophy
  • Existentialism
  • Enlightenment
  • Ancient philosophy
  • Classical Greek philosophy
  • Renaissance philosophy
  • Medieval philosophy
  • Pre-Socratic philosophy
  • Hellenistic philosophy
  • Presocratic philosophy
  • Rationalism
  • Scholasticism
  • Jewish philosophy
  • Early Islamic philosophy
  • Reasoning and Argumentation
  • Seeking Justice After a Tractor-Trailer Accident: Why You Need an Experienced Lawyer
  • Critical Thinking
  • Fallacies and logical errors
  • Skepticism and doubt
  • Creative Thinking
  • Lateral thinking
  • Thought experiments
  • Argumentation and Logic
  • Syllogisms and Deductive Reasoning
  • Fallacies and Rebuttals
  • Inductive Reasoning and Analogy
  • Reasoning and Problem-Solving
  • Critical Thinking and Decision Making
  • Creative Thinking and Problem Solving
  • Analytical Thinking and Reasoning
  • Philosophical Writing and Analysis
  • Argumentative Writing and Analysis
  • Interpreting Philosophical Texts
  • Writing Essays and Articles on Philosophy
  • Philosophical Research Methods
  • Qualitative Research Methods in Philosophy
  • Quantitative Research Methods in Philosophy
  • Research Design and Methodology
  • Ethics and Morality
  • Aesthetics and Beauty
  • Metaphysical terms
  • Ontological argument
  • Ethical terms
  • Aesthetic terms
  • Metaphysical theories
  • Kant's Categorical Imperative
  • Aristotle's Four Causes
  • Plato's Theory of Forms
  • Hegel's Dialectic
  • Ethical theories
  • Aesthetic theories
  • John Dewey's aesthetic theory
  • Immanuel Kant's aesthetic theory
  • Modern philosophical texts
  • Foucault's The Order of Things
  • Descartes' Meditations
  • Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil
  • Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
  • Ancient philosophical texts
  • Kant's Critique of Pure Reason
  • Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
  • Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
  • Plato's Republic
  • Ancient philosophers
  • Modern philosophers
  • Modern philosophical schools
  • German Idealism
  • British Empiricism
  • Ancient philosophical schools
  • The Skeptic school
  • The Cynic school
  • The Stoic school
  • The Epicurean school
  • The Socratic school
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Semantics and Pragmatics of Language Usage
  • Analytic-Synthetic Distinction
  • Meaning of Words and Phrases
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Scientific Realism and Rationalism
  • Induction and the Hypothetico-Deductive Model
  • Theory-Ladenness and Underdetermination
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Mind-Body Dualism and Emergentism
  • Materialism and Physicalism
  • Identity Theory and Personal Identity
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Religious Pluralism and Exclusivism
  • The Problem of Evil and Suffering
  • Religious Experience and Faith
  • Metaphysical Theories
  • Idealism and Realism
  • Determinism, Fatalism, and Libertarianism
  • Phenomenalism and Nominalism
  • Epistemological Theories
  • Intuitionism, Skepticism, and Agnosticism
  • Rationalism and Empiricism
  • Foundationalism and Coherentism
  • Aesthetic Theories
  • Formalist Aesthetics, Emotional Aesthetics, Experiential Aesthetics
  • Relational Aesthetics, Sociological Aesthetics, Historical Aesthetics
  • Naturalistic Aesthetics, Immanent Aesthetics, Transcendental Aesthetics
  • Ethical Theories
  • Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, Deontology
  • Subjectivism, Egoism, Hedonism
  • Social Contract Theory, Natural Law Theory, Care Ethics
  • Metaphysical Terms
  • Cause, Necessity, Possibility, Impossibility
  • Identity, Persistence, Time, Space
  • Substance, Attribute, Essence, Accident
  • Logic and Argumentation Terms
  • Analogy, Syllogism, Deduction, Induction
  • Inference, Validity, Soundness, Refutation
  • Premise, Conclusion, Entailment, Contradiction
  • Epistemological Terms
  • Perception and Knowledge Claims
  • Infallibility, Verifiability, Coherence Theory of Truth
  • Justification, Beliefs and Truths
  • Ethical Terms
  • Modern Texts
  • A Vindication of the Rights of Woman by Mary Wollstonecraft
  • Thus Spoke Zarathustra by Friedrich Nietzsche
  • The Critique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant
  • Medieval Texts
  • The Guide for the Perplexed by Moses Maimonides
  • The Summa Theologiae by Thomas Aquinas
  • The Incoherence of the Incoherence by Averroes
  • Ancient Texts
  • The Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle
  • The Art of Rhetoric by Cicero
  • The Republic by Plato
  • Hegel's Dialectic: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Philosophical theories

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's dialectic is one of the most influential philosophical theories of the modern era. It has been studied and debated for centuries, and its influence can be seen in many aspects of modern thought. Hegel's dialectic has been used to explain a wide range of topics from politics to art, from science to religion. In this comprehensive overview, we will explore the major tenets of Hegel's dialectic and its implications for our understanding of the world. Hegel's dialectic is based on the premise that all things have an inherent contradiction between their opposites.

It follows that any idea or concept can be understood through a synthesis of the two opposing forces. This synthesis creates a new and higher understanding, which then leads to further progress and development. Hegel's dialectic has been used in many different fields, from philosophy to economics, and it provides an important framework for understanding how our world works. In this article, we will explore the historical origins and development of Hegel's dialectic. We will also examine its application in various fields, from politics to art, from science to religion.

Finally, we will consider the implications of Hegel's dialectic for our understanding of the world today. Hegel's dialectic is a philosophical theory developed by German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel in the early 19th century. It is based on the concept of thesis, antithesis and synthesis , which are steps in the process of progress. The thesis is an idea or statement that is the starting point of an argument. The antithesis is a statement that contradicts or negates the thesis.

The synthesis is a combination of the two opposing ideas, which produces a new idea or statement. This process can be repeated multiple times, leading to an evolution of ideas. Hegel's dialectic has been used in many fields, such as politics and economics . It has been used to explain how ideas progress through debate and discussion.

In politics, it has been used to explain how different points of view can lead to compromise or resolution. In economics, it has been used to explain how different economic theories can lead to new solutions and strategies. Hegel's dialectic can also be applied to everyday life. For example, it can be used to resolve conflicts between people or groups.

Thesis, Antithesis and Synthesis

Thesis and antithesis are two conflicting ideas, while synthesis is the result of their interaction. The dialectic process is a way of understanding how the world works, as it helps to explain the constant flux of ideas and events. It also helps to explain how change and progress are possible. Thesis and antithesis can be thought of as two sides of a coin. One side represents an idea or opinion, while the other side represents its opposite.

When the two sides come together, they create a synthesis that incorporates both sides. This synthesis can then be used to create new ideas or opinions. The dialectic process can be applied in various contexts, such as politics and economics. In politics, it can be used to explain how different factions come together to create policies that are beneficial to all parties. In economics, it can be used to explain how supply and demand interact to create a stable market. Hegel's dialectic can also be used in everyday life.

Applications of Hegel's Dialectic

For example, in the political sphere, it can be used to explore how different ideologies can be reconciled or how compromises can be reached. In economics, Hegel's dialectic has been used to explain the process of economic growth and development. It can be seen as a way of understanding how different economic systems interact with each other and how different economic actors are affected by changes in the marketplace. For example, it can help to explain how different economic policies can lead to different outcomes. Hegel's dialectic has also been applied to other social sciences, such as sociology and anthropology. In particular, it has been used to explore how different social systems interact with each other and how different social groups are affected by changes in their environment.

Using Hegel's Dialectic in Everyday Life

This process can be used to explain how various aspects of life, such as career or relationships, evolve over time. Thesis represents an idea or concept, while antithesis represents the opposite of that idea or concept. Synthesis is the resolution between the two opposing forces. This process is repeated until a conclusion is reached.

For example, in a career conflict between two people, one might present an idea while the other presents the opposite idea. Through discussion and negotiation, the two parties can come to a synthesis that meets both their needs. Hegel's dialectic can also be used to resolve conflicts between groups of people. It involves each party presenting their ideas and opinions, then engaging in dialogue to reach a compromise or agreement.

This process can be applied to any area of life, from politics and economics to relationships and personal growth. It helps to create understanding and respect between different perspectives, allowing everyone to come together in a meaningful way. By understanding and applying Hegel's dialectic in everyday life, we can better navigate our relationships and interactions with others. Through dialogue, negotiation, and compromise we can work towards resolutions that benefit all parties involved.

In economics, it has been used to explain how market forces interact with each other and how different economic theories can be used to explain the same phenomenon. The dialectic has also been used in other fields such as philosophy, science, and psychology. In philosophy, it has been used to explain the relationship between theory and practice and how theories evolve over time. In science, it has been used to explain the relationship between empirical evidence and logical reasoning.

This theory can be applied to any area of life, from career to relationships. The core of Hegel's dialectic involves the concept of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, which is a way of understanding how ideas evolve over time. In this way, the dialectic helps to identify contradictions in a situation and find a resolution through synthesis. In terms of its application to everyday life, the dialectic can be used to find common ground between two opposing sides. For example, if two people are in disagreement, the dialectic can help them identify the underlying issues and then work to resolve them.

Additionally, it can help individuals and groups identify areas where they have common interests, which can lead to more productive conversations and outcomes. The dialectic is also useful in understanding how different perspectives can lead to different solutions. By recognizing different points of view, individuals and groups can gain insight into why certain solutions may not work for everyone involved. This can help to create a more productive environment for collaboration. Finally, the dialectic can be used as a tool for self-reflection. By understanding how different ideas evolve over time and how different perspectives interact, individuals can gain insight into their own views and values.

For example, it can be used to explain the development of a new policy proposal or a new form of government. In economics, Hegel's dialectic can be used to explain the dynamics of supply and demand, or the emergence of a new economic system. In addition, Hegel's dialectic has been applied in other areas, such as education and religion. In education, this theory can be used to explain the process of learning and understanding new concepts. In religion, it can be used to explain the evolution of religious beliefs and practices over time.

This is followed by a synthesis of the two, which creates a new, higher form of understanding. This new understanding then forms the basis for further analysis, which can lead to further synthesis and resolution. Hegel's dialectic can be applied to any area of life, such as career or relationships. For example, if two people have different approaches to a problem, they can use the dialectic to work together to find a solution that works for both of them.

This could involve identifying their respective points of view and then looking for common ground where they can agree. As the synthesis forms, it can provide a basis for further discussion, which may eventually lead to a resolution. The same process can be used to resolve conflicts between groups, such as political parties or countries. By recognizing each side's point of view and then looking for common ground, it is possible to find ways to bridge the divide between them.

This can help create an atmosphere of mutual understanding and respect, which can lead to constructive dialogue and positive outcomes. Hegel's dialectic is a valuable tool for helping people and groups come to agreement and harmony despite their differences. By recognizing both sides' points of view and then looking for common ground, it is possible to create a synthesis that can provide a basis for further discussion and resolution. Hegel's dialectic is a powerful philosophical tool that helps to explain how ideas evolve over time. Through the concept of thesis, antithesis and synthesis, it provides a framework for understanding how opposing forces interact and ultimately create new ideas and solutions.

This theory has been applied to many areas, such as politics and economics, and can be used in everyday life. The article has provided a comprehensive overview of Hegel's dialectic and its various applications.

Top Articles

Understanding the Meaning of Words and Phrases

  • Understanding the Meaning of Words and Phrases

A Comprehensive Look at Causality

  • A Comprehensive Look at Causality

Analytical Thinking and Reasoning

  • Deontology: An Introduction to an Ethical Theory
  • Exploring the Theory of Forms: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Exploring Moral Relativism: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Exploring Pragmatism: A Modern Philosophy
  • Medieval Philosophy: An Overview
  • Epistemology: Understanding the Nature of Knowledge
  • Existentialism: An Introduction
  • Exploring Idealism: The History and Concepts of a Modern Philosophy
  • Materialism: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Virtue Ethics: What it is and How it Works
  • Understanding Inference: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Philosophy of Language: Exploring the Ways We Communicate
  • Understanding Fallacies and Logical Errors

Exploring Deductive Reasoning

  • Exploring the Philosophy of Beauty
  • Exploring Inference: A Philosophical Thinking Primer
  • Lateral Thinking: An Overview
  • Understanding Utilitarianism: An Overview
  • Exploring the Principles of Virtue Ethics
  • Thought Experiments: Exploring Creative and Philosophical Thinking
  • Exploring Skepticism and Doubt: A Philosophical and Critical Thinking Perspective
  • Exploring Hellenistic Philosophy: An Introduction
  • Exploring the Ontological Argument
  • Exploring Egoism: What It Is and What It Means
  • Altruism: Exploring the Power of Selflessness
  • Exploring the Ethical Theory of Utilitarianism
  • Exploring Plato's Theory of Forms
  • Exploring Virtue Ethics: The Philosophical Theory
  • A Comprehensive Overview of Foucault's The Order of Things
  • Socrates: An In-Depth Exploration of the Ancient Philosopher
  • Exploring Immanuel Kant's Aesthetic Theory
  • Descartes' Meditations: An Introduction for None
  • Exploring Kant's Critique of Pure Reason
  • Aristotle: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Exploring Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
  • Exploring the Life and Legacy of Cicero: An Introduction
  • Exploring Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil
  • Exploring Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
  • Epicurus - An Introduction to His Philosophy
  • Descartes: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Sublime: An Introduction to Aesthetic and Philosophical Terms
  • Exploring Plato's Republic
  • Exploring Pragmatism: A Modern Philosophical School
  • Exploring Humanism: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Exploring the Life and Works of David Hume
  • Exploring the Skeptic School of Ancient Philosophy
  • The Cynic School: An In-depth Look
  • The Stoic School: An Overview
  • German Idealism: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Analytic Philosophy: A Primer
  • Exploring the Socratic School: An Overview

A Comprehensive Overview of Presocratic Philosophy

  • Exploring the Philosophy of Immanuel Kant
  • Exploring British Empiricism
  • Justification: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Exploring Beliefs and Truth: A Philosophical Guide
  • Exploring Syllogisms and Deductive Reasoning

Exploring Cosmology: What We Know and What We Don't

  • Understanding Fallacies and Rebuttals
  • Exploring Critical Thinking and Decision Making
  • Exploring Theology: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Philosophy of Film: Exploring Aesthetics and Types of Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Music: Exploring the Aesthetics of Sound
  • Exploring the Semantics and Pragmatics of Language Usage
  • Materialism and Physicalism: Exploring the Philosophical Concepts
  • Exploring Identity Theory and Personal Identity
  • Exploring Quantitative Research Methods in Philosophy
  • The Problem of Evil and Suffering: A Philosophical Exploration
  • Exploring Theory-Ladenness and Underdetermination
  • Exploring the Interplay between Religious Experience and Faith
  • Exploring the Concepts of Cause, Necessity, Possibility, and Impossibility
  • Intuitionism, Skepticism, and Agnosticism: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Perception and Knowledge Claims: Understanding Epistemological Terms
  • Exploring Naturalistic, Immanent and Transcendental Aesthetics
  • Exploring Rationalism and Empiricism
  • Exploring Identity, Persistence, Time, and Space
  • Understanding Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism and Deontology
  • Exploring Phenomenalism and Nominalism
  • Exploring Subjectivism, Egoism, and Hedonism
  • Understanding Social Contract Theory, Natural Law Theory, and Care Ethics
  • Exploring Mary Wollstonecraft's A Vindication of the Rights of Woman
  • Exploring Subjectivism, Egoism and Hedonism
  • The Art of Rhetoric by Cicero: A Comprehensive Overview
  • The Critique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant: A Comprehensive Overview
  • Exploring 'The Summa Theologiae' by Thomas Aquinas

New Articles

Exploring Deductive Reasoning

Which cookies do you want to accept?

Encyclopedia

  • Scholarly Community Encyclopedia
  • Log in/Sign up

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

Video Upload Options

  • MDPI and ACS Style
  • Chicago Style

In philosophy, the triad of thesis, antithesis, synthesis (German: These, Antithese, Synthese; originally: Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis) is a progression of three ideas or propositions. The first idea, the thesis, is a formal statement illustrating a point; it is followed by the second idea, the antithesis, that contradicts or negates the first; and lastly, the third idea, the synthesis, resolves the conflict between the thesis and antithesis. It is often used to explain the dialectical method of German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, but Hegel never used the terms himself; instead his triad was concrete, abstract, absolute. The thesis, antithesis, synthesis triad actually originated with Johann Fichte.

1. History of the Idea

Thomas McFarland (2002), in his Prolegomena to Coleridge's Opus Maximum , [ 1 ] identifies Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781) as the genesis of the thesis/antithesis dyad. Kant concretises his ideas into:

  • Thesis: "The world has a beginning in time, and is limited with regard to space."
  • Antithesis: "The world has no beginning and no limits in space, but is infinite, in respect to both time and space."

Inasmuch as conjectures like these can be said to be resolvable, Fichte's Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre ( Foundations of the Science of Knowledge , 1794) resolved Kant's dyad by synthesis, posing the question thus: [ 1 ]

  • No synthesis is possible without a preceding antithesis. As little as antithesis without synthesis, or synthesis without antithesis, is possible; just as little possible are both without thesis.

Fichte employed the triadic idea "thesis–antithesis–synthesis" as a formula for the explanation of change. [ 2 ] Fichte was the first to use the trilogy of words together, [ 3 ] in his Grundriss des Eigentümlichen der Wissenschaftslehre, in Rücksicht auf das theoretische Vermögen (1795, Outline of the Distinctive Character of the Wissenschaftslehre with respect to the Theoretical Faculty ): "Die jetzt aufgezeigte Handlung ist thetisch, antithetisch und synthetisch zugleich." ["The action here described is simultaneously thetic, antithetic, and synthetic." [ 4 ] ]

Still according to McFarland, Schelling then, in his Vom Ich als Prinzip der Philosophie (1795), arranged the terms schematically in pyramidal form.

According to Walter Kaufmann (1966), although the triad is often thought to form part of an analysis of historical and philosophical progress called the Hegelian dialectic, the assumption is erroneous: [ 5 ]

Whoever looks for the stereotype of the allegedly Hegelian dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology will not find it. What one does find on looking at the table of contents is a very decided preference for triadic arrangements. ... But these many triads are not presented or deduced by Hegel as so many theses, antitheses, and syntheses. It is not by means of any dialectic of that sort that his thought moves up the ladder to absolute knowledge.

Gustav E. Mueller (1958) concurs that Hegel was not a proponent of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, and clarifies what the concept of dialectic might have meant in Hegel's thought. [ 6 ]

"Dialectic" does not for Hegel mean "thesis, antithesis, and synthesis." Dialectic means that any "ism" – which has a polar opposite, or is a special viewpoint leaving "the rest" to itself – must be criticized by the logic of philosophical thought, whose problem is reality as such, the "World-itself".

According to Mueller, the attribution of this tripartite dialectic to Hegel is the result of "inept reading" and simplistic translations which do not take into account the genesis of Hegel's terms:

Hegel's greatness is as indisputable as his obscurity. The matter is due to his peculiar terminology and style; they are undoubtedly involved and complicated, and seem excessively abstract. These linguistic troubles, in turn, have given rise to legends which are like perverse and magic spectacles – once you wear them, the text simply vanishes. Theodor Haering's monumental and standard work has for the first time cleared up the linguistic problem. By carefully analyzing every sentence from his early writings, which were published only in this century, he has shown how Hegel's terminology evolved – though it was complete when he began to publish. Hegel's contemporaries were immediately baffled, because what was clear to him was not clear to his readers, who were not initiated into the genesis of his terms. An example of how a legend can grow on inept reading is this: Translate "Begriff" by "concept," "Vernunft" by "reason" and "Wissenschaft" by "science" – and they are all good dictionary translations – and you have transformed the great critic of rationalism and irrationalism into a ridiculous champion of an absurd pan-logistic rationalism and scientism. The most vexing and devastating Hegel legend is that everything is thought in "thesis, antithesis, and synthesis." [ 7 ]

Karl Marx (1818–1883) and Friedrich Engels (1820–1895) adopted and extended the triad, especially in Marx's The Poverty of Philosophy (1847). Here, in Chapter 2, Marx is obsessed by the word "thesis"; [ 8 ] it forms an important part of the basis for the Marxist theory of history. [ 9 ]

2. Writing Pedagogy

In modern times, the dialectic of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis has been implemented across the world as a strategy for organizing expositional writing. For example, this technique is taught as a basic organizing principle in French schools: [ 10 ]

The French learn to value and practice eloquence from a young age. Almost from day one, students are taught to produce plans for their compositions, and are graded on them. The structures change with fashions. Youngsters were once taught to express a progression of ideas. Now they follow a dialectic model of thesis-antithesis-synthesis. If you listen carefully to the French arguing about any topic they all follow this model closely: they present an idea, explain possible objections to it, and then sum up their conclusions. ... This analytical mode of reasoning is integrated into the entire school corpus.

Thesis, Antithesis, and Synthesis has also been used as a basic scheme to organize writing in the English language. For example, the website WikiPreMed.com advocates the use of this scheme in writing timed essays for the MCAT standardized test: [ 11 ]

For the purposes of writing MCAT essays, the dialectic describes the progression of ideas in a critical thought process that is the force driving your argument. A good dialectical progression propels your arguments in a way that is satisfying to the reader. The thesis is an intellectual proposition. The antithesis is a critical perspective on the thesis. The synthesis solves the conflict between the thesis and antithesis by reconciling their common truths, and forming a new proposition.
  • Samuel Taylor Coleridge: Opus Maximum. Princeton University Press, 2002, p. 89.
  • Harry Ritter, Dictionary of Concepts in History. Greenwood Publishing Group (1986), p.114
  • Williams, Robert R. (1992). Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on the Other. SUNY Press. p. 46, note 37. 
  • Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Breazeale, Daniel (1993). Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings. Cornell University Press. p. 249. 
  • Walter Kaufmann (1966). "§ 37". Hegel: A Reinterpretation. Anchor Books. ISBN 978-0-268-01068-3. OCLC 3168016. https://archive.org/details/hegelreinterpret00kauf. 
  • Mueller, Gustav (1958). "The Hegel Legend of "Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis"". Journal of the History of Ideas 19 (4): 411–414. doi:10.2307/2708045.  https://dx.doi.org/10.2307%2F2708045
  • Mueller 1958, p. 411.
  • marxists.org: Chapter 2 of "The Poverty of Philosophy", by Karl Marx https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1847/poverty-philosophy/ch02.htm
  • Shrimp, Kaleb (2009). "The Validity of Karl Marx's Theory of Historical Materialism". Major Themes in Economics 11 (1): 35–56. https://scholarworks.uni.edu/mtie/vol11/iss1/5/. Retrieved 13 September 2018. 
  • Nadeau, Jean-Benoit; Barlow, Julie (2003). Sixty Million Frenchmen Can't Be Wrong: Why We Love France But Not The French. Sourcebooks, Inc.. p. 62. https://archive.org/details/sixtymillionfren00nade_041. 
  • "The MCAT writing assignment.". Wisebridge Learning Systems, LLC. http://www.wikipremed.com/mcat_essay.php. Retrieved 1 November 2015. 

encyclopedia

  • Terms and Conditions
  • Privacy Policy
  • Advisory Board

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Contradiction

Do I contradict myself? Very well, then, I contradict myself. (I am large, I contain multitudes.)    —Walt Whitman, “Song of Myself”
Vorrei e non vorrei.    —Zerlina, “Là ci darem la mano”, Don Giovanni

This entry outlines the role of the Law of Non-Contradiction (LNC), or Principle of Non-Contradiction (PNC), as the foremost among the first (indemonstrable) principles of Aristotelian philosophy and its heirs, and depicts the relation between LNC and LEM (the law of excluded middle) in establishing the nature of contradictory and contrary opposition. §1 presents the classical treatment of LNC as an axiom in Aristotle’s “First Philosophy” and reviews the status of contradictory and contrary opposition as schematized on the Square of Opposition. §2 explores in further detail the possible characterizations of LNC and LEM, including the relevance of future contingent statements in which LEM (but not LNC) is sometimes held to fail. §3 addresses the mismatch between the logical status of contradictory negation as a propositional operator and the diverse realizations of contradictory negation within natural language. §4 deals with several challenges to LNC within Western philosophy, including the paradoxes, and the relation between systems with truth-value gaps (violating LEM) and those with truth-value gluts (violating LNC). In §5, the tetralemma of Buddhist logic is discussed within the context of gaps and gluts; it is suggested that apparent violations of LNC in this tradition (and others) can be attributed to either differing viewpoints of evaluation, as foreseen by Aristotle, or to intervening modal and epistemic operators. §6 focuses on the problem of “borderline contradictions”: the range of acceptability judgments for apparently contradictory sentences with vague predicates as surveyed in empirical studies, and the theoretical implications of these studies. Finally, §7 surveys the ways of contradiction and its exploitation in literature and popular culture from Shakespeare to social media.

1. LNC as Indemonstrable

2. lem and lnc, 3. contradictory negation in term and propositional logic, 4. gaps and gluts: lnc and its discontents, 5. lnc and the buddhist tetralemma, 6. vagueness and borderline contradictions, 7. contradiction in everyday life, other internet resources, related entries.

The twin foundations of Aristotle’s logic are the law of non-contradiction (LNC) (also known as the law of contradiction, LC) and the law of excluded middle (LEM). In Metaphysics Book \(\Gamma\), LNC—“the firmest of all principles”—is defined as follows:

For the same thing to hold good and not to hold good simultanously of the same thing and in the same respect is impossible (given any further specifications which might be added against the dialectical difficulties). (Met. 1005b19–23, Kirwan translation).

It will be noted that this statement of the LNC is an explicitly modal claim about the incompatibility of opposed properties applying to the same object (with the appropriate provisos). Since Łukasiewicz (1910), this ontological version of the principle has been recognized as distinct from, and for Aristotle arguably prior to, the logical formulation (“The opinion that opposite assertions are not simultaneously true is the firmest of all”—Met. 1011b13–14) and the psychological formulation (“It is impossible for anyone to believe that the same thing is and is not, as some consider Heraclitus said”—Met. 1005b23–25) offered elsewhere in Book \(\Gamma\); we return to Heraclitus below. Wedin (2004a), who argues for the primacy of the ontological version (see also Meyer 2008, Other Internet Resources), formalizes it as \(\neg \Diamond(\exists x)(Fx \wedge \neg Fx)\). These three formulations of LNC differ in important respects, in particular as to whether the law is explicitly modal in character, whether it applies to propositions or to properties and objects, and whether it requires the invocation of a metalinguistic truth predicate. (See also the entry Aristotle on non-contradiction .)

For Aristotle, the status of LNC as a first, indemonstrable principle is obvious. Those who mulishly demand a proof of LNC clearly “lack education”: since “a demonstration of everything is impossible”, resulting in infinite regress. At least some principles must be taken as primitive axiomata rather than derived from other propositions—and what principle more merits this status than LNC? (1006a6–12). In first philosophy, as in mathematics, an axiom is both indemonstrable and indispensable; without LNC, Aristotle argues, “\(a\) is \(F\)” and “\(a\) is not \(F\)” are indistinguishable and no argumentation is possible. While Sophists and “even many physicists” may claim that it is possible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time and in the same respect, such a position self-destructs “if only our opponent says something”, since as soon as he opens his mouth to make an assertion, any assertion, he must accept LNC. But what if he does not open his mouth? Against such an individual “it is ridiculous to seek an argument” for he is no more than a vegetable (1006a1–15). (See also Cohen 1986 and Clay 2019 for more on the indemonstrability of LNC and Coren 2018 on why Aristotle defends LNC against its contrary [“All contradictions are true”] rather than its contradictory [“Some contradictions are true”].)

The celebrated Arab commentator Avicenna (ibn Sīnā, 980–1037) confronts the LNC skeptic with a more severe outcome than Aristotle’s vegetable reduction: “As for the obstinate, he must be plunged into fire, since fire and non-fire are identical. Let him be beaten, since suffering and not suffering are the same. Let him be deprived of food and drink, since eating and drinking are identical to abstaining” ( Metaphysics I.8, 53.13–15).

The role of LNC as the basic, indemonstrable “first principle” is affirmed by Leibniz, for whom LNC is taken as interdefinable with the Law of Identity that states that everything is identical to itself: “Nothing should be taken as first principles but experiences and the axiom of identity or (what is the same thing) contradiction, which is primitive, since otherwise there would be no difference between truth and falsehood, and all investigation would cease at once, if to say yes or no were a matter of indifference” (Leibniz 1696/Langley 1916: 13–14). For Leibniz, everybody—even “barbarians”—must tacitly assume LNC as part of innate knowledge implicitly called upon at every moment, thus demonstrating the insufficiency of Locke’s empiricism (ibid., 77). [ 1 ]

In accounting for the incompatibility of truth and falsity, LNC lies at the heart of Aristotle’s theory of opposition, governing both contradictories and contraries. (See traditional square of opposition .) Contradictory opposites (“She is sitting”/“She is not sitting”) are mutually exhaustive as well as mutually inconsistent; one member of the pair must be true and the other false, assuming with Aristotle that singular statements with vacuous subjects are always false. As it was put by the medievals, contradictory opposites divide the true and the false between them; for Aristotle, this is the primary form of opposition. [ 2 ] Contrary opposites (“He is happy”/“He is sad”) are mutually inconsistent but not necessarily exhaustive; they may be simultaneously false, though not simultaneously true. LNC applies to both forms of opposition in that neither contradictories nor contraries may belong to the same object at the same time and in the same respect ( Metaphysics 1011b17–19). What distinguishes the two forms of opposition is a second indemonstrable principle, the law of excluded middle (LEM): “Of any one subject, one thing must be either asserted or denied” ( Metaphysics 1011b24). Both laws pertain to contradictories, as in a paired affirmation (“\(S\) is \(P\)”) and denial (“\(S\) isn’t \(P\)”): the negation is true whenever the affirmation is false, and the affirmation is true when the negation is false. Thus, a corresponding affirmation and negation cannot both be true , by LNC, but neither can they both be false , by LEM. But while LNC applies both to contradictory and contrary oppositions, LEM holds only for contradictories: “Nothing can exist between two contradictories, but something may exist between contraries” ( Metaphysics 1055b2): a dog cannot be both black and white, but it may be neither.

As Aristotle explains in the Categories, the opposition between contradictories—“statements opposed to each other as affirmation and negation”—is defined in two ways. First, unlike contrariety, contradiction is restricted to statements or propositions; terms are never related as contradictories. Second, “in this case, and in this case only, it is necessary for the one to be true and the other false” (13b2–3).

Opposition between terms cannot be contradictory in nature, both because only statements (subject-predicate combinations) can be true or false ( Categories 13b3–12) and because any two terms may simultaneously fail to apply to a given subject. [ 3 ] But two statements may be members of either a contradictory or a contrary opposition. Such statements may be simultaneously false, although (as with contradictories) they may not be simultaneously true. The most striking aspect of the exposition for a modern reader lies in Aristotle’s selection of illustrative material. Rather than choosing an uncontroversial example involving mediate contraries, those allowing an unexcluded middle (e.g. “This dog is white”/“This dog is black”; “Socrates is good”/“Socrates is bad”), Aristotle offers a pair of sentences containing immediate contraries, “Socrates is sick”/“Socrates is well”. These propositions may both be false, even though every person is either ill or well: “For if Socrates exists, one will be true and the other false, but if he does not exist, both will be false; for neither ‘Socrates is sick’ nor ‘Socrates is well’ will be true, if Socrates does not exist at all” (13b17–19). But given a corresponding affirmation and negation, one will always be true and the other false; the negation “Socrates is not sick” is true whether the snub-nosed philosopher is healthy or non-existent: “for if he does not exist, ‘he is sick’ is false but ‘he is not sick’ true” (13b26–35).

Members of a canonical pair of contradictories are formally identical except for the negative particle:

An affirmation is a statement affirming something of something, a negation is a statement denying something of something…It is clear that for every affirmation there is an opposite negation, and for every negation there is an opposite affirmation…Let us call an affirmation and a negation which are opposite a contradiction ( De Interpretatione 17a25–35).

But this criterion, satisfied simply enough in the case of singular expressions, must be recast in the case of quantified expressions, both those which “signify universally” (“every cat”, “no cat”) and those which do not (“some cat”, “not every cat”).

For such cases, Aristotle shifts from a formal to a semantically based criterion of opposition (17b16–25). Members of an \(A/O\) pair (“Every man is white”/“Not every man is white”) or \(I/E\) pair (“Some man is white”/“No man is white”) are contradictories because in any state of affairs one member of each pair must be true and the other false. Members of an \(A/E\) pair—“Every man is just”/“No man is just”—constitute contraries, since these cannot both be true simultaneously but can both be false. The contradictories of these contraries (“Not every man is just”/“Some man is just”) can be simultaneously true with reference to the same subject (17b23–25). This last opposition of \(I\) and \(O\) statements, later to be dubbed subcontraries because they appear below the contraries on the traditional square, is a peculiar opposition indeed; Aristotle elsewhere ( Prior Analytics 63b21–30) sees \(I\) and \(O\) as “only verbally opposed”, given the consistency of the \(I\) statement, e.g. “Some Greeks are bald”, with the corresponding \(O\) statement, “Some Greeks aren’t bald” (or “Not all Greeks are bald”, which doesn’t necessarily amount to the same thing, given existential import; see traditional square of opposition ).

The same relations obtain for modal propositions, for propositions involving binary connectives like “and” and “or”, for quantificational adverbs, and for a range of other operators that can be mapped onto the square in analogous ways utilizing the same notions of contradictory and contrary opposition and with unilateral entailment definable on duals (see Horn 1989). Thus for example we have the modal square below, based on De Interpretatione 21b10ff. and Prior Analytics 32a18–28, where the box and diamond symbols denote necessity and possibility, respectively. As with universal affirmatives and universal negatives, necessity and impossibility constitute contraries: “A priest must marry” and “A priest can’t marry” can both be (and, on the Episcopalian reading, are) false but cannot both be true. “A priest can marry” and “A priest can (if he wants) not marry” are subcontraries; these can be simultaneously true but not simultaneously false. And necessity, as in “A priest must marry”, unilaterally entails its possibility dual counterpart, “A priest may marry”.

A square with the upper-left point A labeled 'a must F'/Box-Phi, the upper-right point E labeled 'a cant F'/Box-Not-Phi-iff-Not-Diamond-Phi, the lower-left point I labeled 'a may F'/Diamond-Phi, and the lower-right point O labeled 'a neednt F'/Not-Box-Phi-iff-Diamond-Not-Phi. A bidirectional arrow between A and E is labeled 'contraries'; a bidirectional arrow between I and O is labeled 'subcontraries'. An arrow down from A to I is labeled 'entails'; and arrow down from E to O is labeled 'entails'. Undirected line segments from A to O and from E to I cross in the center of the square and are labeled 'contradictories'.

Figure 1. Modal Square

In the twelfth century, Peter of Spain (1972: 7) offers a particularly elegant formulation in his Tractatus ; it will be seen that these apply to the modal propositions in Figure 1 as well as to the quantificational statements in the original square:

  • Each contradictory is equivalent to (entails and is entailed by) the negation of the other.
  • Each contrary statement entails the negation of the other but not vice versa. [E.g. “I am happy” unilaterally entails “I am not unhappy”; “It is necessary that \(\Phi\)” unilaterally entails “It is not impossible that \(\Phi\)”.]
  • The law of subcontraries is such that if one is false the other is true but not vice versa.

By these definitions, the three central species of opposition—contradiction, contrariety, and subcontrariety—are mutually inconsistent.

The law of excluded middle, LEM, is another of Aristotle’s first principles, if perhaps not as first a principle as LNC. Just as Heraclitus’s anti-LNC position, “that everything is and is not, seems to make everything true”, so too Anaxagoras’s anti-LEM stance, “that an intermediate exists between two contradictories, makes everything false” ( Metaphysics 1012a25–29). Of any two contradictories \(p\) and \(\neg p\), LNC entails that at most one be true while LEM entails that at least one be true. A logic validates LEM if \(p \vee \neg p\) is a theorem in that logic. LEM thus imposes a constraint on logical syntax and is distinct from the Principle of Bivalence, the purely semantic property dictating that any given proposition is either true or false. The latter principle is rejected in some multivalued and supervaluationist logics that validate LEM, a point to which we return in §6 (see also many-valued logics , Sorites Paradox , truth values ). Despite the logical distinction between these two principles, in practice they are often conflated.

For Aristotle, the status of LEM and bivalence comes down to the problem of future contingents. In a passage that has launched a thousand treatises, Aristotle ( De Interpretatione , Chapter 9) addresses the difficulties posed by apparently contradictory contingent statements about future events, e.g. (1a, b).

Clearly, (1a) and (1b) cannot both be true; LNC applies to future contingents as straightforwardly as to any other pair of contradictories. But what of LEM? Here is where the difficulties begin, culminating in the passage with which Aristotle concludes and (apparently) summarizes his account:

It is necessary for there to be or not to be a sea-battle tomorrow; but it not necessary for a sea-battle to take place tomorrow, nor for one not to take place—though it is necessary for one to take place or not to take place. So, since statements are true according to how the actual things are, it is clear that wherever these are such as to allow of contraries as chance has it, the same necessarily holds for the contradictories also. This happens with things that are not always so or are not always not so. With these it is necessary for one or the other of the contradictories to be true or false—not, however, this one or that one, but as chance has it; or for one to be true rather than the other, yet not already true or false. Clearly, then it is not necessary that of every affirmation and opposite negation one should be true and the other false. For what holds for things that are does not hold for things that are not but may possibly be or not be; with these it is as we have said. ( De Interpretatione 19a30-b4)

Unfortunately, given the systematic ambiguity and textual variations in the Greek text, the difficulty of telling when Aristotle is speaking with his own voice or characterizing an opponent’s argument, and the lack of formal devices for the essential scopal distinctions at issue, it has never been clear exactly just what has been said here and in the chapter more generally. Some, including Boethius and Lukasiewicz, have seen in this text an argument for rejecting LEM for future contingent statements, which are therefore to be assigned a non-classical value (e.g. “Indeterminate”) or no truth-value at all. [ 4 ] Their reasoning is based in part on the premise that the alternative position seems to require the acceptance of determinism. Others, however, read Aristotle as rejecting not simple bivalence for future contingents but rather determinacy itself. This interpretive tradition, endorsed by al-Fārābi, Saint Thomas, and Ockham, is crystallized in this passage from Abelard’s Dialectica (210–22) cited by Kneale and Kneale (1962: 214):

No proposition de contingenti futuro can be determinately true or determinately false…, but this is not to say that no such proposition can be true or false. On the contrary, any such proposition is true if the outcome is to be true as it states, even though this is unknown to us.

Even if we accept the view that Aristotle is uncomfortable with assigning truth (or falsity) to (1a) and (1b), their disjunction in (2a) is clearly seen as true, and indeed as necessarily true. But the modal operator must be taken to apply to the disjunction as a whole as in (2b) and not to each disjunct as in (2c).

For Aristotle, LNC is understood primarily not as the principle that no proposition can be true simultaneously with its negation, but as a prima facie rejection of the possibility that any predicate \(F\) could both hold and not hold of a given subject (at the same time, and in the same respect). A full rendering of the version of LNC appearing at Metaphysics 1006b33–34—“It is not possible to truly say at the same time of a thing that it is a man and that it is not a man”—would require a representation involving operators for modality and truth and allowing quantification over times. [ 5 ] In the same way, LEM is not actually the principle that every statement is either true or has a true negation, but the law that for any predicate \(F\) and any entity \(x\), \( x\) either is \(F\) or isn’t \(F\).

But these conceptualizations of LNC and LEM must be generalized, since the principle that it is impossible for a to be \(F\) and not to be \(F\) will not apply to statements of arbitrary complexity. We can translate the Aristotelian language, with some loss of faithfulness, into the standard modern propositional versions in (3) and (4) respectively, ignoring the understood modal and temporal modifications:

Taking LNC and LEM together, we obtain the result that exactly one proposition of the pair \(\{\Phi , \neg \Phi \}\) holds, where \(\neg\) represents contradictory negation.

Not every natural language negation is a contradictory operator, or even a logical operator. A statement may be rejected as false, as unwarranted, or as inappropriate—misleading, badly pronounced, wrongly focused, likely to induce unwanted implicatures or presuppositions, overly or insufficiently formal in register. Only in the first of these cases, as a toggle between truth and falsity, is it clear that contradictory negation is involved (Horn 1989, Smiley 1993). Sainsbury (2004) takes truth-functional contradictory negation to be a special case of a generalized option negation as a deselection operator: If there are two mutually exhaustive and exclusive options A and B, to select A is to deselect B. But the relevant options may involve not truth, but some other aspect of utterance form or meaning as in the standard examples of metalinguistic negation (Horn 1989; see the entry on negation ). In such cases, a speaker uses negation metalinguistically or echoically to object to a previous or envisaged utterance on any grounds whatsoever, including its phonetic or grammatical form, register, or associated presuppositions or implicatures: “That’s not a car, it’s a Volkswagen”, “Cancer selection is not a but the major force in the emergence of complex animal life”, “He’s not your old man, he’s your father”, “We didn’t call the POlice, we called the poLICE”. In such cases, the relevant target for deselection is what the right thing is to say in a particular context, where “truth is not sufficient for being right, and may not even be necessary” (Sainsbury 2004: 87). Thus the apparent LNC violation (if it’s a Volkswagen, it both is and isn’t a car) is not a real one.

Given that not every apparent sentential negation is contradictory, is every contradictory negation sentential? Within propositional logic, contradictory negation is a self-annihilating operator: \(\neg(\neg \Phi)\) is equivalent to \(\Phi\). This is explicitly recognized in the proto-Fregean Stoic logic of Alexander of Aphrodisias: “‘Not: not: it is day’ differs from ‘it is day’ only in manner of speech” (Mates 1953: 126). The Stoics’ apophatikon directly prefigures the iterating and self-cancelling propositional negation of Frege and Russell. As Frege puts it (1919: 130), “Wrapping up a thought in double negation does not alter its truth value.” The corresponding linguistic principle is expressed in the grammarians’ bromide, “Duplex negatio affirmat.”

Not all systems of propositional logic accept a biconditional law of double negation (LDN), \(\neg(\neg \Phi) \equiv \Phi\). In particular, LDN, along with LEM, is not valid for the Intuitionists, who reject \(\neg(\neg \Phi) \rightarrow \Phi\) while accepting its converse, \(\Phi \rightarrow \neg(\neg \Phi)\). But the very possibility of applying negation to a negated statement presupposes the analysis of contradictory negation as an iterative operator (one capable of applying to its own output), or as a function whose range is identical to (or a subset of) its domain. Within the categorical term-based logic of Aristotle and his Peripatetic successors, every statement—whether singular or general—is of subject-predicate form. Contradictory negation is not a one-place operator taking propositions into propositions, but rather a mode of predication , a way of combining subjects with predicates: a given predicate can be either affirmed or denied of a given subject. Unlike the apophatikon or propositional negation connective introduced by the Stoics and formalized in Fregean and Russellian logic, Aristotelian predicate denial, while toggling truth and falsity and yielding the semantics of contradictory opposition, does not apply to its own output and hence does not syntactically iterate. In this respect, predicate denial both anticipates the form of negation in Montague Grammar (see the entry on Montague semantics ) and provides a more plausible representation of contradictory negation in natural language, whether Ancient Greek or English, where reflexes of the iterating one-place connective of the Stoics and Fregeans (“Not: not: the sun is shining”) are hard to find outside of artificial constructs like the “it is not the case” construction (Horn 1989, §7.2). In a given natural language, contradictory negation may be expressed as a particle associated with a copula or a verb, as an inflected auxiliary verb, as a verb of negation, or as a negative suffix or prefix.

In addition, there is a widespread pragmatically motivated tendency for a formal contradictory negation to be strengthened to a semantic or virtual contrary through such processes as litotes (“I don’t like prunes” conveying that I dislike prunes) and so-called neg(ative) raising (“I don’t think that \(\Phi\)” conveying “I think that \(\neg \Phi\)”). Similarly, the prefixal negation in such adjectives as “unhappy” or “unfair” is understood as a contrary rather than contradictory (not-Adj) of its base. These phenomena have been much discussed by rhetoricians, logicians, and linguists (see the entry on negation and Horn 1989: Chap. 5).

In addition to predicate denial, in which a predicate \(F\) is denied of a subject \(a\), Aristotelian logic allows for narrow-scope predicate term negation , in which a negative predicate not-F is affirmed of \(a\). The relations of predicate denial and predicate term negation to a simple affirmative proposition (and to each other) can be schematized on a generalized square of opposition for singular (non-quantified) expressions ( De Interpretatione 19b19–30, Prior Analytics Chapter 46):

A square with the upper-left point A labeled 'S is P', the upper-right point E labeled 'S is not-P', the lower-left point I labeled 'S isnt not-P', and the lower-right point O labeled 'S isnt P'. A bidirectional arrow between A and E is labeled 'contraries'; a bidirectional arrow between I and O is labeled 'subcontraries'. An arrow down from A to I is labeled 'entails'; and arrow down from E to O is labeled 'entails'. Undirected line segments from A to O and from E to I cross in the center of the square and are labeled 'contradictories'.

Figure 2. Negation Square

If Socrates doesn’t exist, “Socrates is wise” \((A)\) and its contrary “Socrates is not-wise” \((E)\) are both automatically false (since nothing—positive or negative—can be truly affirmed of a non-existent subject), while their respective contradictories “Socrates is not wise” \((O)\) and “Socrates is not not-wise” \((I)\) are both true. Similarly, for any object \(x\), either \(x\) is red or \(x\) is not red—but \(x\) may be neither red nor not-red; if, for instance, \(x\) is a unicorn or a prime number.

While Russell (1905) echoed (without acknowledgment) Aristotle’s ambiguist analysis of negation as either contradictory (“external”) or contrary (“internal”), by virtue of the two logical forms assigned to “The king of France is not bald” (see descriptions ), such propositionalized accounts are bought at a cost of naturalness, as singular sentences of subject-predicate grammatical form are assigned the logical form of an existentially quantified conjunction and as names are transmuted into predicates.

The difference between denying \(P\) of \(S\) and affirming not-P of \(S\) is realized in Ancient Greek as a scopal distinction reflected in word order: S P [not is] (Socrates healthy not-is) vs. S [not P] is (Socrates not-healthy is) . As indicated in Figure 2, for Aristotle only sentences can be in contradictory opposition. \(P\) and not-P both yield falsity when predicated of a non-existent subject but one or the other of the two terms is truthfully predicable of any existent subject in the relevant domain. \(P\) and not-P are “logical contraries” that exclude a true middle, an existent entity which is neither \(P\) nor not-P . But naturally occurring cases of prefixal adjectives, those marked by \(a(n)\)- in Greek, may involve an unexcluded middle, as do polar contraries or antonym pairs. Modern grammatical discourse departs from Aristotle in allowing for contradictory terms: middle-allowing contrary adjectives ( white / black , happy / unhappy ) are distinguished from middle-excluding contradictory adjectives ( transitive / intransitive , alive / dead ).

Jespersen (1917: 144) describes the logical status of negatively prefixed adjectives in English:

The modification in sense brought about by the addition of the prefix [ un- ] is generally that of a simple negative: unworthy = ‘not worthy’, etc. The two terms [P, unP] are thus contradictory terms. But very often the prefix produces a “contrary” term…: unjust (and injustice ) generally imply the opposite of just ( justice ); unwise means more than not wise and approaches foolish , unhappy is not far from miserable, etc.

Like Aristotle, Jespersen predicts that the negation of true contraries like unhappy , unjust , or unwise will be semantically distinct from their positive bases. Thus, not unhappy fails to reduce to happy by virtue of allowing an unexcluded middle: one can be neither happy nor unhappy but just blaah, in the same way that something can be neither black nor white but one of the fifty-plus shades of gray. At the same time, even those adjectives that are semantic contradictories, e.g. impossible , may be coerced under negation into virtual contraries. While technically any action or event must be either possible or impossible, to assess something as not impossible is often to portray its occurrence as a more remote possibility than to assess it as possible simpliciter, as reflected in attestations of “It’s possible, or at least not impossible”. Similar instances of virtual contrariety are readily attested with negated verb phrases (“I don’t NOT love the dog” \(\ne\) I love the dog) or predicate nominals (“We’re not NOT friends” \(\ne\) We’re friends); see Horn 2017.

Drawing on an epistemic theory of vagueness, Krifka (2007) argues that prefixal negation always yields semantic contradictories. On this view, unhappy is literally just ‘not happy’, with the characteristic stronger understanding derived pragmatically. The incomplete cancellation of the two negators in not unhappy is taken to be a purely pragmatic phenomenon, conflating this case with that of not impossible . But the classical theory has its advantages. On that approach, un-Adj antonyms (like their morphologically simplex classmates, sad or bad ) are lexical items that can constitute contraries vis-à-vis the corresponding positive. By virtue of their lexical status, they are candidates to undergo further semantic drift, unlike not Adj sequences (or non-Adj forms), as evidenced in the semantic and phonological opacity of infamous or impious . Note too that many un - and in - adjectives ( unkempt , inchoate , incorrigible ) lack corresponding simple bases. Furthermore, the prefix non- yields staunch contradictories (typically with objective and/or technical senses) often contrasting minimally with un-Adj or in-Adj contraries favoring gradable and evaluative contexts:

  • non-American vs. un-American; non-professional vs. unprofessional
  • non-Christian vs. un-Christian; non-rational vs. irrational
  • non-moral vs. immoral; non-realistic vs. unrealistic
  • non-natural vs. unnatural; non-scientific vs. unscientific

Even more problematically for a unified treatment, the treatment of all negatively prefixed adjectives as semantic contradictories would seem naturally to extend from unhappy or unwise to simplex antonymic pairs like happy / sad or wise / foolish , where the evidence for semantic contrariety appears to be incontrovertible. While Krifka (2007: 174) supports the analysis of e.g. happy and unhappy as “literally contradictories that receive their interpretations as contraries only via pragmatic strengthening”, Horn (2017) argues that a traditional (neo-Aristotelian) approach invoking parallel but distinct semantic and pragmatic strengthening processes is on sounder empirical footing.

In addition to the future contingent statements discussed in §2, vacuous subjects like those in (5a, b) have sometimes been taken to yield a violation of LEM through the emergence of a truth-value gap.

While Aristotle would see a republican France as rendering (5a) false and (5b) automatically true, Frege (1892) and Strawson (1950) reject the notion that either of these sentences can be used to make a true or false assertion. Instead, both statements presuppose the existence of a referent for the singular term; if the presupposition fails, so does the possibility of classical truth assignment. Note, however, that such analyses present a challenge to LEM only if (5b) is taken as the true contradictory of (5a), an assumption not universally shared. Russell, for example, allows for one reading of (5b) on which it is, like (5a), false in the absence of a referent or denotatum for the subject term; on that reading, on which the description has primary occurrence, the two sentences are not contradictories. In this way, Russell (1905: 485) seeks to guide the French monarch out of the apparent trap without recourse to wigs or truth value gaps:

By the law of the excluded middle, either ‘A is B’ or ‘A is not B’ must be true. Hence either ‘the present king of France is bald’ or ‘the present king of France is not bald’ must be true. Yet if we enumerated the things that are bald and the things that are not bald, we should not find the king of France on either list. Hegelians, who love a synthesis, will probably conclude that he wears a wig.

In those systems that do embrace truth value gaps (Strawson, arguably Frege) or non-classically-valued systems (Łukasiewicz, Bochvar, Kleene), some sentences or statements are not assigned a (classical) truth value; in Strawson’s famous dictum, the question of the truth value of “The king of France is wise”, in a world in which France is a republic, simply fails to arise. The negative form of such vacuous statements, e.g. “The king of France is not wise”, is similarly neither true nor false. This amounts to a rejection of LEM, as noted by Russell 1905. In addition to vacuous singular expressions, gap-based analyses have been proposed for future contingents (following one reading of Aristotle’s exposition of the sea-battle; cf. §2 above) and category mistakes (e.g. “The number 7 likes/doesn’t like to dance”).

While LNC has traditionally remained more sacrosanct, reflecting its position as the primus inter pares of the indemonstrables, transgressing this final taboo has become increasingly alluring in recent years. The move here involves embracing not gaps but truth value gluts , cases in which a given sentence and its negation are taken to be both true, or alternatively cases in which a sentence may be assigned more than one (classical) truth value, i.e. both True and False. Parsons (1990) observes that the two non-classical theories are provably logically equivalent, as gluts arise within one class of theories precisely where gaps do in the other; others, however, have argued that gaps (as in Intuitionist non-bivalent logics) are easier to swallow than gluts (see papers in the Priest et al. 2004 collection for further debate). Dialetheists reject the charge of incoherence by noting that to accept some contradictions is not to accept them all; in particular, they seek to defuse the threat of logical armageddon or “explosion” posed by Ex Contradictione Quodlibet, the inference in (6):

Far from reduced to the silence of a vegetable, as Aristotle ordained, the proponents of true contradictions, including self-avowed dialetheists following the lead of Sylvan (né Routley) and Priest have been eloquent.

Is the status of Aristotle’s “first principle” as obvious as he believed? Adherents of the dialetheist view that there are true contradictories (Priest 1987, 1998, 2002; see also the entries on dialetheism and paraconsistent logic ) would answer firmly in the negative. [ 6 ] In the Western tradition, the countenancing of true contradictions is typically—although not exclusively—motivated on the basis of such classic logical paradoxes as “This sentence is not true” and its analogues; such a statement is evidently true if and only if it is not true. The Liar, or really the family of Liar’s paradoxes (see Liar Paradox ), and Russell’s paradox, its set-theoretic analogue (a set that is not a member of itself both is and is not a member of itself—see the entry on Russell’s Paradox ), would no longer constitute immediate threats to logical coherence in the absence of LNC (see papers in Priest et al. for extended discussion). If we are indeed prepared to jettison LNC, we can regard “This sentence is not true” (or “This statement is false”) as simultaneously true and not true without deriving the resultant absurdity taken by Aristotle and his heirs to result from such a contradiction. As Smiley (1993: 19) has remarked, “Dialetheism stands to the classical idea of negation like special relativity to Newtonian mechanics: they agree in the familiar areas but diverge at the margins (notably the paradoxes).” Others have remained unpersuaded, among them Lewis (1982: 434): “No truth does have and no truth could have, a true negation. Nothing is, and nothing could be, literally both true and false. This we know for certain, and a priori, an without any exception for especially perplexing subject matters”.

Related to the classic paradoxes of logic and set theory is the Paradox of the Stone. One begins by granting the basic dilemma, as an evident instance of LEM: either God is omnipotent or God is not omnipotent. With omnipotence, He can do anything, and in particular He can create a stone, call it \(s\), that is so heavy even He cannot lift it. But then there is something He cannot do, viz. (ex hypothesi) lift \(s\). But this is a violation of LNC: God can lift \(s\) and God cannot lift \(s\). This paradox, and the potential challenge it offers to either LNC or the possibility of omnipotence, has been recognized since Aquinas, who opted for retaining the Aristotelian law by understanding omnipotence as the capacity to do only what is not logically impossible. (Others, including Augustine and Maimonides, have noted that in any case God is “unable” to do what is inconsistent with His nature, e.g. commit sin.) For Descartes, on the other hand, an omnipotent God is by definition capable of any task, even those yielding contradictions. Mavrodes (1963), Kenny, and others have sided with St. Thomas in taking omnipotence to extend only to those powers it is possible to possess; Frankfurt (1964), on the other hand, essentially adopts the Cartesian line: Yes, of course God can indeed construct a stone such that He cannot lift it—and what’s more, He can lift it! (See also Savage 1967 for a related solution.)

As we have seen, the target of Aristotle’s psychological (doxastic) version of LNC was Heraclitus: “It is impossible for anyone to believe that the same thing is and is not, as some consider Heraclitus said—for it is not necessary that the things one says one also believes” (Met. 1005b23–26). But as Aristotle acknowledges here (even if he is less politic elsewhere), there is considerable uncertainty over exactly what Heraclitus said and what he believed. Heraclitus could not have literally rejected LNC, as he is often accused of (or praised for) doing, as his writings preceded the statement of that principle in Metaphysics \(\Gamma\) by well over a century. But the question remains: do his words, as represented in the extant fragments, anticipate the Dialetheists and other rejectionists? Yes and no. To be sure, Heraclitus was proud to wear the mantle of “paradoxographer” (Barnes 1982: 80) and enjoyed nothing more than to épater les bourgeois of his day. But the key fragments supporting his proclamation of the Unity of Opposites can be taken in more than one way. He points out that sea water is salutary (if you’re a fish) and unhealthy (if you’re a human), just as garbage is preferable to gold (for a donkey) but then again it isn’t (for a person). And given the inevitability of flux (as Heraclitus memorably illustrated by his river into which one cannot step twice), what is true (today) is also false (tomorrow). But these astute observations do not so much refute the LNC as much as demonstrate (through what Barnes calls the Fallacy of the Dropped Qualification) the need for Aristotle’s crucial codicil: sea water, for example, cannot be both healthful and unhealthful for the same experiencer at the same time and in the same respect. (In a similar way, “It is raining” may of course be deemed true at this moment in Seattle and false in Palo Alto; we need admit no contradiction here, whether we deal with the issue by endorsing unarticulated constituents or in some other manner; cf. Recanati 2002 inter alia.) Ultimately, whether one follows Kirk (Heraclitus [1954]) in charging Aristotle with misrepresenting Heraclitus as an LNC-denier or sides with Barnes (1982) and Wedin (2004b) in sustaining Aristotle’s accusation, it is hard to see in what respect the evidence presented by Heraclitus, however subtle a guide he may be for our travels on that path on which up and down is one and the same, threatens the viability of LNC. (See also Heraclitus .)

Within the modern philosophical canon, Hegel has often been seen as the echt LNC-skeptic, well before his reputed deathbed lament, “Only one man ever understood me, and he didn’t understand me.” Hegel saw himself as picking up where Heraclitus left off—“There is no proposition of Heraclitus which I have not adopted in my logic” (Barnes 1982: 57)—and indeed the Heraclitean view of a world shaped by the unity of opposites through strife and resolution does seem to foreshadow Hegelian dialectic. In fact, however, an unresolved contradiction was a sign of error for Hegel. The contradiction between thesis and antithesis results in the dialectical resolution or superseding of the contradiction between opposites as a higher-level synthesis through the process of Aufhebung (from aufheben, a verb simultaneously interpretable as ‘preserve, cancel, lift up’). Rather than repudiating LNC, Hegel’s dialectic rests upon it. In Marxist theory, too, contradictories do not simply cancel out but are dynamically resolved ( aufgehoben ) at a higher level in a way that both preserves and supersedes the contradiction, motivating the historical dialectic. (See Horn 1989: §1.3.2.)

For Freud, there is a realm in which LNC is not so much superseded but dissolved. On the primary, infantile level, reflected in dreams and neuroses, there is no not : “‘No’ seems not to exist as far as dreams are concerned. Anything in a dream can mean its contrary” (Freud 1910: 155). When the analysand insists of a dream character “It’s not my mother”, the analyst knowingly translates, “So it is his mother!” Freud sought to ground this pre-logical, LNC-free (and negation-free) realm not just in the primal realm of the dreamer’s unconscious but also in the phenomenon of Gegensinn , words (especially Urwörte , primal words) with two opposed meanings purported attested widely in ancient and modern languages. The empirical basis for this latter claim, however, has been widely discredited; see Benveniste 1956.

Given Aristotle’s observation ( Metaphysics 1006a2) that “even some physicists” deny LNC and affirm that it is indeed possible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time and in the same respect, he might not have been surprised to learn that quantum mechanics has brought such challenges once more into play. Thus, we have Schrödinger’s celebrated imaginary cat, placed (within the context of a thought experiment) inside a sealed box along with radioactive material and a vial of poison gas that will be released if and only if that material decays. Given quantum uncertainty, an atom potentially inhabits both states—decayed and non-—simultaneously, seeming to render the cat (in the absence of an observer outside the system) both alive and dead. But most physicists would argue that while quantum mechanics may challenge some aspects of classical logic it does not threaten LNC. If we could in fact observe a cat, or a particle, as A and not-A at the same time, then there would be a violation of the Law of Non-Contradiction; the mere potential for an entity to be in either of two mutually inconsistent states does not in itself violate the LNC.

As we have seen, Aristotle himself anticipated many of the challenges that have since been raised against LNC. One more such challenge is posed by the ubiquity of doxastic inconsistency. Take the desires of Oedipus, for example. In seeking Jocasta as his mate, did he wish to marry his mother? Certainly he did on the de re reading: Oedipus’s mother (Jocasta) is such that he wanted to marry her, although he would not have assented to the claim that he wanted to marry his mother. In a sense, then, “Oedipus wanted to marry his mother” is true (de re) and false (de dicto), but no violation of LNC is incurred, since these represent different propositions, the semantic distinction neutralized within the sentential form. But what of the de dicto reading itself: it is really false? After all, as a young boy Oedipus can be assumed (by some) to have exhibited the eponymous complex, according to which the falsity of the (de dicto) proposition that he wanted to marry his mother on a conscious level belies the truth of this proposition on an unconscious level. But this does not entail that he both wished and did not wish to “marry” his mother at the same time and in the same respect . Whether it concerns the unacknowledged incestuous conflict of the Theban king, the indecision of Zerlina’s “Vorrei e non vorrei” response to Don Giovanni’s invitation, or the unspecified ambivalence of the respondent in Strawson’s exchange (1952: 7)

—Were you pleased? —Well, I was and I wasn’t.

we have ample opportunity to reflect on the foresight of Aristotle’s rider: “a is \(F\)” and “a is not \(F\)” cannot both hold in the same sense, at the same time, and in the same respect .

Beyond the Western canon, the brunt of the battle over LNC has been largely borne by the Buddhists, particularly in the exposition by Nāgārjuna of the catuṣkoṭi or tetralemma (c. 200 A.D.; cf. Bochenski 1961: Part VI, Raju 1954, Garfield 1995, Tillemans 1999, Garfield & Priest 2002), also known as the four-cornered or fourfold negation. Consider the following four possible truth outcomes for any statement and its (apparent) contradictory:

For instances of the positive tetralemma, on Nāgārjuna’s account, all four statement types can or must be accepted:

Everything is real and not real. Both real and not real. Neither real nor not real. That is Lord Buddha’s teaching. — Mūla-madhyamaka-kārikā 18:8, quoted in Garfield (1995: 102)

Such cases arise only when we are beyond the realm to which ordinary logic applies, when “the sphere of thought has ceased.” On the other hand, more use is made of the negative tetralemma, in which all four of the statements in (7) can or must be rejected, and thus one cannot assert either \(\Phi , \neg \Phi\), both \(\Phi\) and \(\neg \Phi\), or neither \(\Phi\) nor \(\neg \Phi\). Is this tantamount, as it appears, to the renunciation of LEM and LNC, the countenancing of both gaps and gluts, and thus—in Aristotle’s view—the overthrow of all bounds of rational argument?

It should first be noted that the axiomatic status of LNC and LEM is as well-established within the logical traditions of India as it is for the Greeks and their epigones. [ 7 ] Garfield (1995) and Tillemans (1999) convincingly refute the claim that Nāgārjuna was simply an “irrationalist”. [ 8 ] In the first place, if Nāgārjuna simply rejected LNC, there would be no possibility of reductio arguments, which hinge on the establishment of untenable contradictions, yet such arguments are standardly employed in his logic. In fact, he explicitly prohibits virodha (contradiction). Crucially, it is only in the realm of the Absolute or Transcendent, where we are contemplating the nature of the ultimate, that contradictions are embraced; in the realm of ordinary reality, LNC operates and classical logic holds. (Recall Freud’s dichotomy between the LNC-observant conscious mind and the LNC-free unconscious.) In this sense, the logic of Nāgārjuna and of the Buddhist tradition more generally can be seen not as inconsistent but paraconsistent. Indeed, just as Aristotle ridiculed LNC-skeptical sophists as no better than vegetables (see §1), the Buddhists dismissed the arch-skeptic Sanjaya and his followers, who refused to commit themselves to a definite position on any issue, as “eel-wrigglers” (amarāvikkhepa) . Sanjaya himself was notorious for his periodic lapses into the extended silence Aristotle described as the last refuge of the LNC-skeptic (see Raju 1954).

One aspect of the apparent paradox is precisely parallel to that arising with some of the potential counterexamples to the LNC arising in Western thought. In various Buddhist and Jainist systems of thought, the apparent endorsement of \(Fa \amp \neg Fa\) (or, in propositional terms, \(\Phi \wedge \neg \Phi)\) is upon closer examination qualified in precisely the way foreseen by the codicils in Aristotle’s statement of the law: From a certain viewpoint, \(\Phi\) (e.g. Nirvana exists); from a certain viewpoint, \(\neg \Phi\) (e.g. Nirvana does not exist). (Compare the observation of Jainists two millennia ago that “\(S\) is \(P\)” and “\(S\) is not \(P\)” can both be true from different standpoints; cf. Raju 1954: 698–701; Balcerowicz 2003. Rahlwes 2022 offers another look at the catuṣkoṭi and Rahlwes 2023 provides a detailed analysis of the Jainists’ saptabhangī or seven-valued logic based on distinguishing the dimension of truth/falsity from that of (in)expressibility or (un)assertibility, leveraged as a way to dissolve contradictions\(.)\)

To further explore the status of truth-value gluts, in which both classical values are simultaneously assigned to a given proposition (e.g. “\(x\) is real”), let us consider the analogous cases involving gaps. Recall, for example, the case of future contingents as in (1a, b) above: we need not maintain that “Machines will surpass human-level cognition” is neither true nor false when uttered today, but only that neither this statement nor its contradictory ““Machines will not surpass human-level cognition”” is assertible today in the absence of foreknowledge. Similarly for past unknowables, such as (to adapt an example from Quine) the proposition that the number of blades of grass on the Old Campus lawn during the 2005 Yale commencement exercises was odd. This is again more plausibly viewed as unassertable than as truth-valueless, even though its truth-value will never be known. To take a third example, we can argue, with Grice (1989: 80ff.), that a negation outside the scope of a conditional is generally intended as a refusal (or hesitation) to assert “if \(p\) then \(q\)” rather than as the contradictory negation of a conditional, whose truth value is determined in accord with the standard material equivalence:

Thus, in denying your conditional “If you give her penicillin, she will get better”, I am allowing for the possibility that giving her penicillin might have no effect on her, but I am not predicting that you will administer the penicillin and she will fail to recover. Nor does denying the apothegm (typically though inaccurately attributed to Dostoyevsky or Nietzsche) that if God is dead everything is permitted commit one to the conjoined proposition that God is dead and something is forbidden. As Dummett (1973: 328–30) puts the point, we must distinguish negation outside the scope of a Fregean assertion operator, not \((\vdash p)\), from the assertion of a negative proposition, \(\vdash\)(not \(p)\). The former interpretation “might be taken to be a means of expressing an unwillingness to assert” \(p\), in particular when \(p\) is a conditional:

\(Y\)’s contribution here does not constitute a negation of \(X\)’s content; rather, we can paraphrase \(Y\) as conveying \((9'\)a) or \((9'\)b):

Dummett observes, “We have no negation of the conditional of natural language, that is, no negation of its sense: we have only a form for expressing refusal to assent to its assertion.”

Similarly with disjunction. Consider the exchange in (10) preceding the 2000 election, updated from an example of Grice:

\(Y\)’s rejoinder cannot be a contradictory of the content of \(X\)’s claim, since the (de jure) election of Bush rendered both \(X\)’s and \(Y\)’s statements true. Rather, \(Y\) objects on the grounds that \(X\) is not in an epistemic position to assert the binary disjunction.

Unassertability can be read as the key to the apparent paradox of the catuṣkoṭi as well. The venerable text in Majjhima-nikāya 72, relating the teachings of the historical Buddha, offers a precursor for Nāgārjuna’s doctrine of the negative tetralemma. Gotama is responding to a monk’s question concerning the doctrine of rebirth (quoted in Robinson 1967: 54):

Gotama, where is the monk reborn whose mind is thus freed?    Vaccha, it is not true to say that he is reborn. Then, Gotama, he is not reborn.    Vaccha, it is not true to say that he is not reborn. Then, Gotama, he is both reborn and not reborn.    Vaccha, it is not true to say that he is both reborn and not reborn. Then, Gotama, he is neither reborn nor not reborn.    Vaccha, it is not true to say that he is neither reborn nor not reborn.

Note the form of the translation here, or similarly that of the standard rendering of the negative catuṣkoṭi that “it profits not” to assert \(\Phi\), to assert \(\neg \Phi\), to assert both \(\Phi\) and \(\neg \Phi\), or to assert neither \(\Phi\) nor \(\neg \Phi\): the relevant negation can be taken to operate over an implicit modal, in particular an epistemic or assertability operator. If so, neither LEM nor LNC is directly at stake in the tetralemma: you can have your Aristotle and Buddha too.

We tend to recalibrate apparent violations of LNC as conforming to a version of the law that incorporates the Aristotelian qualifications: a sincere defense of “\(p\) and not-\(p\)” plausibly involves a change in the context of evaluation or a shift in viewpoint, or alternatively a suppression of modal or epistemic operators. This practice can be seen as an instance of a general methodological principle associated with Davidson and Quine that has come to be called the principle of charity (or, alternately, the principle of rational accommodation ): when it is unclear how to interpret another’s argument, interpret it in a way that makes the most sense. At the same time, this procedure evokes the standard Gricean mode of explanation (Grice 1989; see the entry on implicature ): granted the operation of the Cooperative Principle and, more broadly, the shared premise of rationality, we reinterpret apparent violations of valid principles or maxims so as to conserve the assumption that one’s interlocutor is a rational and cooperative agent. And as Aristotle would remind us, no principle is more worthy of conservation than the Law of Non-Contradiction.

We have seen that two of the more significant threats to the unchallengeable status of LNC tend to dissolve under closer scrutiny. Heraclitus-type contradictions (Sea water is healthy and sea water is not healthy) are rendered LNC-compatible by the Aristotelian rider designed for that purpose (“a is \(F\)” and “a is not \(F\)” cannot both hold in the same sense, at the same time, and in the same respect ) once the “dropped qualification” or contextual specification is restored (§4). Buddhist-type contradictions (Nirvana exists and Nirvana does not exist) can be understood as modalized, embedded under an epistemic modal or assertability operator.

We are left with two significant challenges for LNC: (i) the case of the Liar and related paradoxes of self-reference as touched on in §3 and work cited therein (see the entries on Liar Paradox, Russell’s Paradox, Dialetheism, Paraconsistent Logic) and (ii) the case of vagueness and its implications for borderline truth, discussed in this section. As we have seen, the admission of truth-value gaps (exceptions to LEM) is mirrored by the admission of truth-value gluts (exceptions to LNC). As intellectual heirs of the Hegelian tradition, Marxists have willing to accept paradox, and indeed the pre-Revolutionary theorist Plekanov (1909) suggests that Sorites (in the form of the bald man; see sorites entry) can be resolved by rejecting LNC. Hyde (1997) traces the history of vagueness-based arguments for paraconsistency from Plekhanov through Jaśkowski, McGill, and Parry in the 1940s to the dialetheist logics of today. Pointing out the parallels between treatments of vagueness via truth-value gap theories (including the supervaluation theory of van Fraassen 1969) and their truth-value glut counterparts, Hyde laments the unwarranted neglect of the latter option: “The thought that an adequate response might require the recognition of cases of overdetermination and and truth-value gluts has few supporters” (Hyde 1997: 641). In the two decades since the publication of his important paper, that neglect has been largely rectified, especially with the accretion of empirical support for glut-oriented approaches endorsing the acceptability of a range of true contradictions of the form a is P and a is not P, in particular when P is a vague predicate like tall , vague , or red .

Supervaluation theory utilizes the concept of admissible sharpening or precisification of vague predication (see the entry on vagueness ). I may be unable to assert truthfully of a given color chip in the red-orange range that it is red, while also being unable to assert that it is not red. Once the notion of red is sharpened or precisified to a particular interval of wave-lengths, I am in a position to assert either the positive proposition “a is red” or its negation “a is not red”, but which one depends on the details of the sharpening. A sentence \(S\) is supertrue iff it is true on every sharpening and superfalse if it is false on every sharpening; if is true on some sharpenings and false on others, it is neither supertrue nor superfalse, thus corresponding to a truth-value gap. One salutary result of this approach is that LEM can be retained: P or not P is supertrue since it is true on every sharpening. Hyde (1997) draws on the dual status of gaps and gluts to define a paraconsistent “subvaluation” theory: \(S\) is subtrue iff is true on at least one sharpening, subfalse iff it is false on at least one sharpening, and neither subtrue nor subfalse if it is true on some sharpenings and false on others. Given the status of supervaluation and subvaluation as duals, each is equally defensible and applicable to the semantics of vagueness. Crucially, it is the notion of supertruth, or subtruth as the case may be, that tracks our natural language intuitions of truth, and similarly for falsity. In this sense, the logic of supervaluation is paracomplete (allowing for violations of LEM) and the logic of subvaluation paraconsistent (allowing for violations of LNC). In the tradition of paraconsistent logics, Hyde stresses the need for “quarantining the gluts” to avoid the explosive consequences of ex contradictione quodlibet (see §4).

Where supervaluation theory allows a is not tall or a is not bald to be neither (super)true nor (super)false if \(a\) represents a borderline instance of tallness, subvaluation theory would characterize such an assessment as both (sub)true and (sub)false. But since tautologies are preserved if validity is defined in terms of truth and not subtruth (or supertruth)—an assumption that some might challenge— a is tall and a is not tall can never be true, even when a is tall and a is not tall are both true:

A vague sentence ‘\(A\)’ and its negation might both be true (since they each have some true disambiguation—i.e. the sentence ‘\(A\)’ itself as some true and some false disambiguation—but their conjunction can never be. ‘\(A \amp\neg A\)’ has only false disambiguations; LNC is retained. (Hyde 1997: 654)

For Akiba (1999), however, paraconsistent subvaluation theories, like paracomplete supervaluation theories, should be recast in a modal light, by supplying an epistemic possibility operator Pos in the former case (reminiscent of the modalized accounts of the tetralemma explored in §5) and its dual, an abstract modal concept Akiba defines as \(\textit{Def}\) (corresponding to necessary truth) in the latter. Thus, while \(P \amp \neg P\) remainsafull-fledged contradiction, its modalizedcounterpart\(\textit{Pos}(P) \amp \textit{Pos}(\neg P)\) is coherent, and while \(P\vee \neg P\) is a valid instance of LEM, \(\textit{Def}(P) \vee\textit{Def}(\neg P)\) is not: “Super- and subvaluation systems can be considered not really alternatives to classical logic but in fact just modal extensions of it.” Akiba’s key departure from Hyde’s approach is in rejecting the move to identify truth simpliciter with subtruth (or supertruth).

Confronted with the task of applying semantically vague predicates like tall and red to borderline cases, the intuitions of respondents in psycholinguistic studies often tend to become uncertain. Subjects produce varying responses for the crucial data, and the framers of the studies have produced varying explanations for the data. In one of the earlier studies, Bonini et al. point to the asymmetries in judgments of truth and falsity for borderline cases of a is red/tall and ultimately reject truth-gap and truth-glut accounts in favor of an LEM- and LNC-compatible epistemic theory of “vagueness as ignorance”. That is, the subject \(S\) “mentally represents vague predicates in the same way as other predicates with sharp true/false boundaries of whose location \(S\) is uncertain” (Bonini et al. 1999: 387).

Kyburg (2000) offers a pragmatic explanation for why a is tall might be judged neither true nor false in a case of borderline tallness, or why a is tall and a is not tall might be judged true in the same circumstance. Without conceding gaps or gluts, she points to a disconnect between truth-value intuitions and assertability intuitions for a cooperative speaker aiming to be maximally informative. Of course, in some cases, the felicity of a is tall and a isn’t tall might simply reflect the awareness that different cut-off points apply depending on the relevant comparative class of entities (children vs. adults, male adults vs. male professional basketball players, etc.)—the instances foreseen by the Aristotelian rider. But in other cases, such a statement would indeed convey that a possesses a borderline degree of tallness, while simply affirming or denying the vague predicate— a is tall or a is not tall— would communicate too high or too low a degree. Just as speakers might refrain from uttering a sentence, or classifying as true, a perfectly and “sharply” true sentence whose use would mislead the hearer— Snow is white or snow is purple— so too the assertion of a conjunction of opposites in borderline cases— a is tall and he’s not tall— might be preferred, despite its contradictory nature, to the misleading assertion of either a is tall or a is not tall in the same circumstance.

For Sorensen (2001), an individual’s acceptance of the truth of certain false claims, including those necessarily false claims of the form a is tall and a is not tall, reflect not the inadequacy of our semantic and logical analyses but the tendency for speakers to be wrong, confused, or ignorant about the truth conditions of given sentences or about their own beliefs, especially those involving vagueness, similarly to the way in which perceptions can mislead in the case of visual illusions.

The vagueness-as-ignorance theory of Bonini et al. (1999), the modal theory of Akiba (1999), the assertability theory of Kyburg (2000), and the error theory of Sorensen (2001) are all semantically classical in their preservation of LNC (along with LEM and bivalence). In essence, each of these approaches to the assessment of vague predications reflects a wariness about jettisoning the classical account of truth and contradiction in favor of an approach endorsing either supervaluations (and gaps) or subvaluations (and gluts). Despite the difficulties posed by vagueness, these theorists would thus adopt the philosophical corollary to the familiar legal adage: “Hard cases make bad laws.” One particularly significant hard case is that of the culturally problematic binaries of gender and race whose rejection can take the form of two contradictories or two contraries that are singly denied but jointly affirmed, as when a character on the Grey’s Anatomy TV medical drama (S15E24, 2019) declares “I’m not a woman. I’m not a man. I’m both.”

In two recent papers the reconciliatory approach is rejected in favor of defenses of paraconsistency, although not precisely along the lines laid out by Hyde. On Hyde’s account, a is tall and \(a\) is not tall can both be true when \(a\) is borderline tall (say, \(5'11'')\) while the full or reduced conjunction of these statements, a is tall and (a is) not tall, will be false, given the standard supervaluationist approach. Alxatib & Pelletier, however, find the opposite judgments among a majority of the subjects of their study, who accept the conjunction while rejecting the individual ascriptions of truth. In addition to reinforcing the view of gappy and glutty theories as mirror images, Alxatib & Pelletier present their results as evidence against the neo-classical vagueness-as-ignorance position of Bonini et al. (1999), a position which also has difficulty accounting for the paucity of subjects choosing the “can’t tell” option in the surveys. Like the assertability-based pragmatic theory of borderline contradictions proposed by Kyburg, Alxatib & Pelletier (2011: 321) offer a Gricean explanation for subjects’ endorsement of the truth of apparent contradictory statements— a is tall and not tall when a is just short of 6 feet tall—which yields (in just this case) a subvaluationary interpretation on which the speaker is taken to convey the borderline status of \(a\)’s height. Their central finding (2011: 298–9) is that theories admitting truth-value gaps like that of Hyde (1997) or the paraconsistent logic of Priest 2006 fare better in accounting for the full range of interesting data presented in their experiments—and those of Ripley 2011.

Like Alxatib & Pelletier, Ripley (2011: §2) conducts his own survey of reactions to apparent contradictions involving vague predications (e.g., “The circle is both is and isn’t near the square”; “The circle neither is nor isn’t near the square”). He leverages the results of his study to argue against error (or epistemic) theories on which borderline contradictions are always false even when believed true; he also refutes fuzzy theories of vagueness, which fail to predict why subjects are so willing to accept the truth of borderline contradictions rather than assigning them an intermediate acceptability ranking. Ripley also finds pragmatic or contextualist theories not insufficiently fleshed out to yield the correct predictions. He adopts a dialetheist account that enables him to line up with a majority of his subjects in finding both “\(a\) is \(F\) and \(a\) is not \(F\)” and “\(a\) is neither \(F\) nor not \(F\)” true for borderline applications of \(F\). Supporting this view, he notes (2011: 186–7) that there may be variation with respect to the “cultural aversion to contradictions”; there is evidence tending to suggest that Asian subjects are less likely than Westerners (specifically, as it happens, Canadians) to object to contradictions like “It’s raining and it’s not raining.” But as Ripley concedes, more research is needed on this point.

The logical incoherence of contradictions is the ground both for indecision (as with Zerlina’s ambivalent Vorrei e non vorrei in our epigraph) and for the pragmatic exploitation of apparent contradictions for communicative ends. One locus is the oxymoron, a phrasal contradiction exploited for millennia as a figure of speech. The dramatic effect of yoking contradictories is as old as the classical festina lente (‘make haste slowly’) adopted as a motto by Augustine and the Medicis. The German counterpart, deployed by Goethe and others, adds rhyme: Eile mit Weile . In the Catholic tradition, the fall of man is regarded as felix culpa, a happy fault or sin, leading as it does to redemption. On a more mundane level we have such one-word oxymorons as agathokakological, ‘both good and evil’, and more colloquially the humblebrag, in which an intended instance of self-promotion is concealed within false modesty or self-deprecation. Perhaps the most interesting instance is the sophomore, reconstructed as a partial folk etymology from sophos (‘wise’, as in philosophy ) + moros (‘fool’, as in moron— or oxymoron ).

The use of actual or apparent contradiction to generate meanings via reconstrual may convey advice to seek the middle way, reminiscent of the function of borderline contradictions surveyed in §6, or may, in the case of an apparently incoherent phrasal structure, serve as a signal that the modifier constrains the denotation of the head. Thus bittersweet is not taken as a self-contradictory property, while a tragicomedy is a work or production that spans the two normally opposed genres—recall Walt Whitman’s “I am large; I contain multitudes”. Classic modifier–head oxymorons include cruel kindness, living death, and true lies; jocular ones are regularly proposed, from military intelligence and congressional ethics to airplane food and open secrets . A particularly transparent form is offered by those promoting undesign design or the non-concept concept.

The oxymoron, and in particular the bard’s catalogue of oxymorons, may also be rcruited to signal the breakdown of logical coherence, given the explosive effect of ex contradictione quodlibet . In Romeo and Juliet, we ascend from the former’s risible inventory of battling binaries to the latter’s ardent valediction on her balcony:

Why, then, O brawling love! O loving hate! O anything, of nothing first create! O heavy lightness! Serious vanity! Misshapen chaos of well-seeming forms! Feather of lead, bright smoke, cold fire, sick health!    — Romeo and Juliet , I.i Good night, good night. Parting is such sweet sorrow That I should say good night till it be morrow.    — Romeo and Juliet , II.ii

Expanding from the phrasal to the sentential level, we find self-contradictory propositions, whether in full or elliptical form, functioning in forums from high culture to social media to generate a variety of implicatures. In her recent study of the phenomenology of ambivalence, Razinsky takes the affirmation of conjoined contradictories “a is \(v\) and a is not \(v\)” for a given value judgment \(v,\) or the affirmation of “a is \(v\) and a is v´ ” where v, v´ are contraries (e.g. a is good and a is bad ), to be “central to the logic of value and of value judgment” (2017: 229). Some apparent instances of ambivalence (and of any underlying violation of LNC) can be explained away. Citing Mill, Razinsky (2017: 201) accepts that there are instances in which a is just and a is unjust reflects only an apparent opposition, to be understood essentially as a is just in some respects and a is unjust in other respects . Such cases illustrate the prescience of the Aristotelian rider: “a is \(F\)” and “a is not \(F\)” cannot both hold in the same sense, at the same time, and in the same respect . Similarly, the imposition of the edict \(a\) ought to F and a ought not to F results in difficulty for the unfortunate \(a\), to be sure, but not necessarily in an LNC violation, given the availability of distinct sources of obligation. But other cases involve true ambivalence: “Meaningful contradictions are moored in the possibility of conceptual ambivalence” (Razinsky 2017: 44). The analysis of such cases must preserve the dynamic tension in affirming that a is \(v\) and a is not-v and at the same time acknowledge the speaker’s awareness of the violation of LNC, not an easy task: “Do people believe contradictions when it comes to value? I do not think there is a good answer to give here” (Razinsky 2017: 228)—they believe them and do not believe them.

Perhaps as a reflection of this tension, the A-not-A meme has widely proliferated in popular entertainment, advertisements, and social media. “Sorry not sorry” has become a standard device for a sarcastic or insincere apology (also known as a “non-apology apology”), while #SorryNotSorry is a trending Twitter hashtag as well as a Demi Lovato song title (see Carey 2014 in Other Internet Resources). The category of “Christmas-not-Christmas movies” makes its perennial appearance on the web during holiday season, and the #worknotwork has been adopted as the house meme of Samsonite luggage. Of more immediate philosophical relevance is Nikhil Krishnan’s take on queerness and philosophers in his New Yorker piece “How Queer Was Ludwig Wittgenstein?”: “[Socrates] was seen, even in his time, to be—using the word advisedly—queer. Undoubtedly, that was the case in the modern, pejorative-not-pejorative sense: he was attracted to men. But he was also queer in ways that are harder to define.” A related meme is “I’m not saying, I’m just saying”, a notorious “get out of jail free” discourse ploy showing up in hundreds of google hits, as the subject of several online commentaries by linguists (cf. Siegel 2005), and as the title of a 2012 flash fiction paperback by Matthew Salesses.

A relatively new means for expressing ambivalence in colloquial U.S. and Australian English is the “Yeah no” (or, less frequently, “No yeah”) response, which has been analyzed as conveying a variety of possible discourse functions (see Burridge & Florey 2002, Lee-Goldman 2011, and Liberman 2008 in Other Internet Resources).

The conjunction of contradictory predicates of the form not A and/but not NOT A is used to indicate the borderline status of an entity with respect to a category and its complement:

  • They not brown but they not NOT brown . [faux commercial for Levi’s Wokes on Saturday Night Live, Nov. 30, 2017; see Saturday Night Live, 2017 in Other Internet Resources]
  • Karl Mitze, Geoff Manyin, Nick Montopoli, and Zachariah Matteson redefine what it means to be a string quartet. Described as “ not classical…but not not classical ”, bowed and fretted Invoke continues to successfully dodge even the most valiant attempts at genre classification. [comment on YouTube video for Invoke Sound, TEDxYouth@Austin; see Invoke Sound, 2022 in Other Internet Resources]
  • Strayed and I are heading out for a stroll in Portland, Oregon, in the kind of weather for which that city is famous: not raining, but not not-raining . [journalist’s piece on Cheryl Strayed, author of Wild; see Schulz, 2014 in Other Internet Resources]
  • Mozzarella sticks are one of my favorite appetizers…The thing is, are they healthy? No. Are they even in the middle, like not healthy but not not healthy ? No. [recipe column; see Creme de la Crumb, 2022 in Other Internet Resources]

While these may appear contradictory, that diagnosis relies on the status of S is not not P as an instance of \(\neg(\neg\)(S is P)) within a logic employing a robust Law of Double Negation. Arguably, however, in each of these attestations, the inner negation— not brown, not classical, not healthy, and even not-raining— can be viewed as a coerced or virtual contrary, in which case the two negations do not fully cancel out. Thus, just as not impossible fails to reduce to possible, not not classical is distinct from classical, and no actual violation of LNC is ultimately condoned. But, as on Grice’s (1989) analysis of irony and tautology, it is the recognition of the apparent contradiction that the speaker exploits to generate the higher-order coherence of the message.

A less, or perhaps differently, mediated case of coherence in apparent contradictories involves prosody, such as “He isn’t rich, he’s RICH”, from Geurts (2010: 186). In this construction, the hearer/reader must directly reconcile LNC with the joint predication of \(A\) and not A rather than the more complex not A and not not A . But on closer examination, the task is less daunting than it appears, as it’s really a matter of affirming \(A\) while rejecting \(\boldsymbol{A},\) or of metalinguistically rejecting \(A\) in favor of \(\boldsymbol{A}\):

  • “Rita”, he whispered. “I’m tired.” And the way he said the word, she understood. He wasn’t tired, he was tired \(,\) a condition of the mind as well as the body. A state of the soul. [Lisa Gardner, 2008, Say Goodbye , p. 151]
  • “Walt Davies doesn’t just have property. He has property . ” [Lisa Gardner, 2020, When You See Me , p. 171]
  • It’s not hot, it’s HOT . Dangerously and uncomfortably hot... (PhuketBigdaddy’s comment on TripAdvisor re July temperatures in Oman) [see PhuketBigdaddy, 2019 in Other Internet Resources]
  • I’m short. Not SHORT, but short . I’m \(5'8''\) (on a good day) with a \(30''\) inseam. [see Motorcycle Forum, 2007 in Other Internet Resources]

The prosodic or orthographic focus in such cases invokes a scalar contrast in degrees or qualities of A-ness; the result is analogous to instances in which a descriptor is contrasted with a clone (Horn 2018) or contrastive focus reduplication (Ghomeshi et al. 2004) of the same descriptor, yielding variants of the true borderline contradictions discussed in §6.

  • They are rich, of course...but not RICH rich. Not New York City rich. [Michael Cunningham, The Hours, cited as ex. (5a) in Ghomeshi et al. (2004: 347)]
  • A: I’m sorry, your husband is brain dead. B: But not DEAD dead, right? [exchange on The Good Wife (CBS-TV) 23 May 2010, cited as ex. (24) in Horn (2018: 248)]

Note the rhetorical if not truth-conditional contrast between a tycoon protesting that he is not RICH rich and acknowledging that he is not NOT rich. (See Stanton 2023 for more on the relation between clones and prosodic intensification.)

Finally, it is worth noting the role contradiction plays as a lively source of ironic humor, especially for the highbrow reader. In one New Yorker cartoon (Benjamin Schwartz, March 30, 2015), a veterinarian comes into the waiting room, places a comforting arm on the worried man’s shoulder, and breaks the news: “About your cat, Mr. Schrödinger—I have good news and bad news.” (See §4 above for more on the poor cat’s indeterminate prognosis.) In another (J. B. Handelsman, March 9, 1987), a mutton-chopped publisher, seated at his Victorian office desk and riffling through an immense manuscript, explains to the dejected bearded author, “I wish you would make up your mind, Mr. Dickens. Was it the best of times or was it the worst of times? It could scarcely have both.” .

For my valedictory, I borrow the last words of Samuel Beckett’s The Unnamable (1954)—“I can’t go on, I’ll go on”—since in fact I can’t go on.

  • Akiba, Ken, 1999. “On super- and subvaluation: a classicist’s reply to Hyde,” Mind , 108: 727–32.
  • Alxatib, Sam and Francis Jeffry Pelletier, 2011. “The psychology of vagueness: Borderline cases and contradictions,” Mind & Language , 26(3): 287–326.
  • Anton, John Peter, 1957. Aristotle’s Theory of Contrariety, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul. See especially Chapter Six.
  • Aristotle, Categories and De Interpretatione , J. N. Ackrill (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon, 1963.
  • –––, Metaphysics , Hippocrates Apostle (ed.), Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1966.
  • –––, Metaphysics Books \(\Gamma , \Delta\), and E , Christopher Kirwan (ed.), 2nd edition, Oxford: Clarendon, 1993.
  • –––, Prior and Posterior Analytics , W. D. Ross (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon, 1957.
  • Avicenna, La Métaphysique du Shifā Livres I à V , Georges Anawati (ed.), Paris: Vrin, 1978.
  • Balcerowicz, Piotr, 2003. “Some remarks on the Naya method,” in Essays in Jaina Philosophy and Religion. Warsaw Indological Studies (Volume 2), Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, pp. 37–68.
  • Barnes, Jonathan, 1969. “The law of contradiction,” Philosophical Quarterly , 19: 302–309.
  • –––, 1982. The Presocratic Philosophers , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Béziau, Jean-Yves, 2023. “Ex incompatibilitate sequitur quodlibet (The explosiveness of incompatibility and the compatibility of negation)”, in T. Madigan and J.-Y. Béziau (eds.), Universal Logic, Ethics, and Truth - Essays in Honor of John Corcoran (1937-2021), Birkhäuser, Cham, to appear. Downloadable at http://www.jyb-logic.org/papers.html.
  • Benveniste, Émile, 1956. “Remarks on the function of language in Freudian theory,” reprinted in Problems in General Linguistics , M. E. Meek (trans.), Coral Gables: University of Miami Press, 1971, pp. 65–75.
  • Bochenski, Joseph M., 1961. A History of Formal Logic , Ivo Thomas (ed. and trans.), Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Bonini, Nicolao, Daniel Osherson, Riccardo Viale, and Timothy Williamson, 1999. “On the psychology of vague predicates,” Mind & Language , 14: 377–93.
  • Clay, Graham, 2019. “Aristotle’s argument from truth in Metaphysics \(\Gamma 4\)”, Analysis , 79: 17–24.
  • Code, Alan, 1986. “Aristotle’s investigation of a basic logical principle”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 16: 341–58.
  • Cohen, S. Marc, 1986. “Aristotle on the Principle of Non-Contradiction”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy , 16: 359–70.
  • Coren, Daniel, 2018. “Why does Aristotle defend the Principle of Non-Contradiction against its contrary?”, Philosophical Forum , 49: 39–59.
  • Cresswell, M.J., 2003. “Non-contradiction and substantial predication”, Theoria , 69: 166–83.
  • Dummett, Michael, 1973. Frege: philosophy of language , London: Duckworth.
  • Dutilh Novaes, C., 2019, “Aristotle’s Defense of the Principle of Non-contradiction: A Performative Analysis”, in D. Gabbay, L. Magnani, W. Park, and A.V. Pietarinen (eds.), Natural Arguments: A Tribute to John Woods , London: College Publications, 529–542.
  • Fine, Kit, 1975. “Vagueness, truth, and logic”, Synthese , 30: 265–300.
  • van Fraassen, Bas, 1969. “Presuppositions, super-valuations, and free logic”, in K. Lambert (ed.), The Logical Way of Doing Things , New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 67–91.
  • Frankfurt, Harry, 1964. “The logic of omnipotence”, Philosophical Review , 73: 262–63.
  • Frege, Gottlob, 1892. “On sense and reference”, in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege , P. Geach and M. Black (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, 1952, pp. 56–78.
  • –––, 1919. “Negation,” in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege , P. Geach and M. Black (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, 1952, pp. 117–35.
  • Freud, Sigmund, 1910. “The antithetical sense of primal words,” in J. Strachey (ed.), The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (Volume 11), London: Hogarth Press, 1957, pp. 155–61.
  • Garfield, Jay, 1995. The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā , Jay L. Garfield (trans., commentary), New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Garfield, Jay and Graham Priest, 2002. “Nāgārjuna and the limits of thought,” in Priest 2002, pp. 249–70.
  • Geach, P. T., 1972. Logic Matters , reprinted Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980.
  • Geurts, Bart, 2010. Quantity Implicatures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Grice, H. P., 1989. Studies in the Way of Words , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Heraclitus, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments , G. S. Kirk (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1954.
  • Horn, Laurence, 1989. A Natural History of Negation , Chicago: University of Chicago Press; reissue edition, Stanford: CSLI, Publications, 2001.
  • –––, 2017. “Lie-toe-tease: double negatives and excluded middles,” Philosophical Studies , 174: 79–103.
  • –––, 2018. “The lexical clone: Pragmatics, prototypes, and productivity,” in R. Finkbeiner and U. Freywald (eds.), Exact Repetition in and Discourse, 233–264, Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Hyde, Dominic, 1997. “From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts,” Mind , 106: 641–660.
  • Jespersen, Otto, 1962. Negation in English and Other Languages , Copenhagen: A. F. Høst.
  • Kneale, William and Martha Kneale, 1962. The Development of Logic , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Krishnan, Nikhil, 2022. “How queer was Ludwig Wittgenstein?”, New Yorker, May 16, 2022,
  • Kumārila Bhaṭṭa, The Mīmāmsā-śloka-vārtika , R. Talainga (ed.), Benares: Freeman & Co., 1899.
  • Kyburg, Alice, 2000. “When vague sentences inform”, Synthese , 124: 175–91.
  • Lear, Jonathan, 1980. Aristotle and Logical Theory , Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.
  • Leibniz, Wilhelm Gottfried von, 1696. New Essays Concerning Human Understanding by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz , A. G. Langley (ed. and trans.), 2nd edition, Chicago: Open Court, 1916.
  • Lee-Goldman, Russell, 2011. “\(No\) as a discourse marker,” Journal of Pragmatics , 43: 2627–49.
  • Lewis, David. 1982. “Logic for equivocators,” Noûs , 16: 431–41.
  • Łukasiewicz, Jan, 1910. “On the principle of contradiction in Aristotle”, V. Wedin (trans.), Review of Metaphysics , 24 (1971): 485–509.
  • Mates, Benson, 1953. Stoic Logic , Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
  • Mavrodes, George, 1963. “Some puzzles concerning omnipotence,” Philosophical Review , 72: 221–23.
  • Meyer, Matthew. 2014. “Aristotle’s defense of the Principle of Non-Contradiction in Metaphyics IV”, in Reading Nietzsche Through the Ancient: An Analysis of Become, Perspectivism, and the Principle of Non-Contradiction, 55–115, Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Parsons, Terence, 1990. “True contradictions,” Canadian Journal Philosophy , 20: 335–53.
  • Peter of Spain, Tractatus, called afterwards Summulae Logicales , L. M. de Rijk (ed.), Assen: van Gorcum, 1972.
  • Plekhanov, Gyorgii. 1909. Fundamental Problems of Marxism , D. Ryazanov (ed.), New York: International Publishers, 1929.
  • Priest, Graham, 1987. In Contradiction , Dordrecht: M. Nijhoff.
  • –––, 1998. “To be and not to be—that is the answer. On Aristotle on the law of non-contradiction,” Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse , 1: 91–130.
  • –––, 2002. Beyond the Limits of Thought , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2006. In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent , The Hague: M. Nijhoff.
  • Priest, Graham, J. C. Beall, and Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), 2004. The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Rahlwes, Chris. 2022. “Nāgārguna’s negation”, Journal of Indian Philosophy , 50: 307–44.
  • Rahlwes, Chris. 2023. “Silence and contradiction in the Jaina Saptabhangī , Journal of Indian Philosophy , online version, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-023-09545-5.
  • Raju, P. T., 1954. “The principle of four-cornered negation in Indian philosophy,” Review of Metaphysics , 7: 694–713.
  • Razinsky, Hili, 2017. Ambivalence: A Philosophical Exploration , London: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Recanati, François, 2002. “Unarticulated constituents”, Linguistics and Philosophy , 25: 299–345.
  • Ripley, David, 2011. “Contradiction at the borders,” in R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, U. Sauerland, and H.-C. Schmitz (eds.), Vagueness in Communication , Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 169–88.
  • Robinson, Richard, 1967. Early Mâdhyamika in India and China , Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
  • Russell, Bertrand, 1905. “On descriptions”, Mind , 14: 479–93.
  • Sainsbury, R. M., 2004. “Option negation and dialetheias,” in Priest et al. (eds.) 2004, 85–92.
  • Savage, C. Wade, 1967. “The paradox of the stone,” Philosophical Review , 76: 74–79.
  • Siegel, Muffy, 2005. “Finding conversational facts: a role for linguistics in court,” International Journal of Speech, Language and the Law , 12: 255–278.
  • Smiley, Timothy, 1993. “Can contradictions be true?,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 67: 17–33.
  • Sorensen, Roy, 2001. Vagueness and Contradiction , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stanton, Kate, 2023. Composing words and non-words. Synthese 202:179, online pre-publication.
  • Strawson, P. F., 1952. Introduction to Logical Theory , London: Methuen.
  • Tillemans, Tom, 1999. “Is Buddhist Logic non-classical or deviant?,” Scripture, Logic, Language (Chapter 9) Boston: Wisdom Publications.
  • Wedin, Michael V., 2004a. “Aristotle on the firmness of the principle of non-contradiction,” Phronesis , 49: 226-65.
  • –––, 2004b. “On the use and abuse of non-contradiction: Aristotle’s critique of Protagoras and Heraclitus in Metaphysics Gamma 5,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , 26: 213–39.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Carey, Stan (2014). “ Sorry not sorry: The many names for non-apologies ,” LexiconValley blogpost, Slate , Nov. 20, 2014.
  • Creme de la Crumb (2022). Creme de la Crumb recipe column , recipe for mozzarella bread sticks, Dec. 20, 2022.
  • Invoke Sound (2017), youtube.com , description of Invoke Sound string quartet at YouTube performance video from TEDxYouth@Austin, June 1, 2017.
  • Liberman, Mark (2008). “ Yeah-no mailbag ,” Language Log blog post, April 3, 2008.
  • Motorcycle Forum (2017), Total Motorcycle Forum posting , comment by beardking on problems encountered by short motorcycle riders, May 31, 2007.
  • PhuketBigdaddy (2019). Oman in July , TripAdvisor warning on July temperatures in Oman.
  • Saturday Night Live (2017). Levi’s Wokes , non-gender-conforming style-free jeans introduced in faux commercial, Nov. 30, 2017.
  • Schulz, Kathryn (2014). “ The walking cure: Talking to Cheryl Strayed about what made Wild work ,” Vulture , Dec. 3, 2014.

Aristotle, General Topics: logic | Aristotle, General Topics: metaphysics | Aristotle, Special Topics: on non-contradiction | dialetheism | fatalism | Heraclitus | liar paradox | logic: many-valued | negation | Russell’s paradox | Sorites paradox | square of opposition | truth values | vagueness

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to SEP’s anonymous readers for their critiques of earlier versions. Thanks also to Zoltan Szabó, Piotr Balcerowicz, and Matthew Meyer for helpful comments.

Copyright © 2024 by Laurence R. Horn < laurence . horn @ yale . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2024 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Hegel-by-HyperText Resources

Excerpt from Hegel for Beginners

Source : Hegel for Beginners , by Llyod Spencer and Andrzej Krauze, Published by Icon Books, 14 of 175 pages reproduced here, minus the abundant illustrations.

"Classical reasoning assumes the principle of logical identity: A = A or A is not non-A".

"But in writing that book I became aware of employing a new and unprecedented way of thinking".

Dialectical Thinking

Aufhebung or sublation, a grammar of thinking.

"I liken my study of logic to the study of grammar. You only really see the rewards when you later come to observe language in use and you grasp what it is that makes the language of poetry so evocative".

Three Kinds of Contradiction

  • The three divisions of the Science of Logic involve three different kinds of contradiction. In the first division Being the opposed pair of concepts at first seem flatly opposed, as if they would have nothing at all to do with one another: Being Nothing / Quantity Quality. Only be means of analysis or deduction can they be shown to be intimately interrelated.
  • In the second division Essence the opposed pairs immediately imply one another. The Inner and the Outer, for example: to define one is at the same time to define the other.
  • In the third division the Concept [ Notion ] we reach an altogether more sophisticated level of contradiction. Here we have concepts such as identity whose component parts, Universality and Particularity, are conceptually interrelated.

Triadic Structure

  • The analytic logic of understanding which focuses the data of sense-experience to yield knowledge of the natural phenomenal world.
  • The dialectical logic of understanding which operates independently of sense-experience and erroneously professes to give knowledge of the transcendent noumena ("things in themselves" or also the "infinite" or the "whole")
  • Analytic understanding is only adequate for natural science and practical everyday life, not for philosophy.
  • Dialectic reason s not concerned with Kant's "transcendent", nor with the abstract "mutilated" parts of reality, but with reality as a totality , and therefore gives true knowledge.

What is Knowing?

"the whole of philosophy resembles a circle of circles".

Further Reading: Introduction to Shorter Logic | Meaning of Hegel's Logic

—  Hegel-by-HyperText Home Page @ marxists.org  —

Home

On Aristotle's dialectical method

  • Brendan Montague

Creative Commons 4.0

Bird

Dialectic is a process of discovery and pedagogy that takes place between two individuals using logical argument, according to Aristotle. To an extent, this is the same as the familiar “thesis, antithesis, synthesis” to which Aristotle’s dialectic is often reduced, but that formulation actually originated with Johann Fichte (1762 - 1814). 

Dialectic is the same as rhetoric in that it is an intellectual activity aimed at changing minds, and is the same as logic in that it relies on reasoning to validate (or invalidate) arguments. It differs from rhetoric in that only logic should be deployed to persuade, and that it is aimed at a particular individual rather than a group, or a crowd. It differs from logic in that it is not concerned with the pursuit of absolute truth, or first principles, but in convincing a person of an argument. 

Read 'The nature of Aristotle's dialectic' here. 

Dr Evans explains that while dialectic is concerned with the individual and her perspective, logic is not: “Pure logic is not concerned with the vagaries of the individual's reaction, and indeed in its search for objectivity it is positively prohibited from considering the individual as such.” (75) He adds later: “Aristotle is aware that the conditions of the exercise of dialectical skill are such that, although the dialectician is indeed required to argue his case purely by logical means, he must at the same time not ignore the various ways in which circumstances which are external to his argument can affect its character.” (92) 

So what is the method of dialectic? Dialectic involves a dialogue between two people. These individuals do need an understanding of the logical method of reasoning - set out more fully here - and need to be seriously and genuinely engaged in the process. The concern is validating arguments on both sides. Dialectic is not a method for bad actors or the resolution of primarily emotional disputes. 

Aristotle asserts that dialectic does use logic to advance knowledge through the validation of arguments and through deductive reasoning through inference. “[W]e need to distinguish how many kinds of dialectical argument there are,” he writes in Topics. “One kind is induction, another is deduction. Here we discuss deduction, which is the essence of logic. 

The aim of both logic and dialectic is to validate the definition of things (indeed, everything from abstract concepts to physical objects). Logic seeks a true, absolute definition. Dialectic aims to validate or invalidate definitions presented in argument.

The beginning of any process of definition (of demonstration, and of argument) is actually very simple: we start with “this is the same is that,” and “this is different to that”: the human is the same as the bonobo in this way; the human is different to the bonono in this way. Dr Evans states: [T]here are certain things - same, other etc. - with which the dialectician is characteristically concerned...” (38). This is because ‘same’ and ‘different’ are the foundations of definition (of cognition and categorisation), which is how we come to recognise and define the things around us.

In both dialectic and logic, any one thing can only be defined by its relation to other things. The basic structure of a proposition includes a subject (the thing being defined) and an object (the thing it is defined in relation to) is. A proposition can be used as a premise in an argument, and through argument we can infer a new proposition, which is the conclusion. 

Definition 

Dialectic and logic both arrive at definitions by identifying the unique properties that belong to the subject - the properties that really make it what it is as opposed to superfluous detail, which Aristotle calls the accidents.

For example, in a definition humans we would want to include language, but not necessarily fingernails. It is the use of language that differentiates humans from other apes. Both humans and apes have fingernails. Language is a unique property in this instance, fingernails are accidents. 

Dialectic, like logic, is concerned with propositions that include a subject and a predicate, and the relationship between the two. The subject is the thing that is defined in any proposition. The predicate is the object and the relation to that object that defines the subject. An example of such a statement is, “all humans are animals”.

Here, the human is the subject and animal the predicate. We know that those properties that are universal to animals (for example, the property of needing to eat to survive) will also be true for us humans. The object of the sentence - the animal - is used to describe the subject - the human. Both unique properties and accidents are predicates, but only the former is useful in establishing a higher level definition. 

To define something skillfully, we need to understand the wider class of things to which our subject belongs. This, in Aristotle’s terminology, is its genus. A genus is a class or category of things that share the same property. The genus ‘vehicle’ will include modes of transport including busses, cars and bicycles.

We then need to establish what properties distinguish it from the other things in its genus. These properties Aristotle calls differentia. The subject that is differentiated within a genus is the species (from specific). The bus is a public mode of transport used by many, the car a private use of transport used by a few.

The mode of ownership and use differentiates the specific car, and specific bus, which are both in the genus, or category, vehicle. Dr Evans states: “Aristotle argues that only if the definition contains the genus and the differentia, can it indicate the essence of the subject” (114). We define our subject by placing it into the correct place in a wider system of categories. 

A true definition of any subject states its essence: the essence is those properties that allow us to categorise it in its genus, and then differentiate it from other members of that genus. We arrive at the essence of any thing through this double-sided process of classification. This is why for Aristotle the pursuit of the essence of things is primary and paramount. As Dr Evans writes: “[T]he requirement that the definition indicate the essence is an unargued premiss to the discussion in Topics...elsewhere in Aristotle’s work the axiomatic character of this requirement can be seen.” (107). 

We can see here the influence of Aristotle’s interest in biology, and the natural world provides a useful range of things that can give us concrete examples of what we mean. Let’s begin with what is most familiar: ourselves.

Humans are a species. The species human belongs to the genus of ape. One of the many differences between humans and other animals is that we have a complex language. Therefore, through this double process of establishing our genus (the general group that we belong to) and our differentia (that which is specific to our species) we are able to develop a definition of human: an ape with language. This definition describes the essence of what it means to be human. 

The process of defining a thing through its genus and species is derived from, but not limited to, the practice of biology. We can use the same process to define concepts, such as “true” and “false”. These terms appear to be entirely the opposite of each other. However, both are concerned with the validity of whatever they happen to describe.

They belong to the genus of statements about validity. Yet the differentia is one is positive and one is negative. The definition of “true” is therefore “a positive statement about validity”. This provides us with the essence of what we mean by true. 

In dialectics, and in logic, when we define any object we are not required to fix the genus and the species. The choice we make depends on what exactly we are trying to define and - in dialectic - for whom.

For example, we can also say that all humans are systems. Here, we may be concerned about universal claims about all systems. These claims would logically be true of humans. The terms we chose in our propositions depend very much on what we are hoping to establish. With dialectics (but not logic) it also depends on the premises that we can agree with our interlocutor.

This process of establishing definitions and validating arguments is enhanced through the use of the syllogism. (A longer definition of syllogism is provided in this Endoxa article). In short, a syllogism is a method of arriving at (or inferring) a valid conclusion from two valid premises.

There is - Aristotle establishes - a particularly useful from of syllogism where the first premise states the general (or universal); the second states the specific (the individual) and the third the relationship between the two (the particular). The classic syllogism would look like this:

All humans are animals

Eve is a human

Eve is an animal

If we agree that the premise that “all humans are animals” and also that “Eve is a human” then we can infer that the statement “Eve is an animal” is valid. This is the basis of formal logic. Dialectic uses the syllogism because it is compelling: it is highly likely to convince the person you are in conversation with, whereas logic utilises the same technique for slightly different purposes - the pursuit of absolute truth.

A sortie - a long chain of syllogisms - is the aim of rational thought. Aristotle argues in Topics: “[F]or it is impossible to demonstrate something if one does not start from the special foundations and link one's reasoning in a chain until one reaches what is at the end” (34/35).

This begs the question. What are these “special foundations”. For the syllogism, we need premises. Dialectic begins with “the securing of premises”. As we can see above, valid premises should provide us with valid conclusions, an invalid premise can conversely result in an invalid conclusion.

The house we build is only as sound as the foundations on which it sits. The securing of premises - according to Aristotle - includes 1. The detection of ambiguity; 2. The discovery of differences, and 3. The consideration of similarities. This follows tidily from our exploration of definition, above.

In this article I have attempted to give a brief definition and overview of Aristotle’s dialectic, setting out its aims, scope and method. Now that we have a working understanding of dialectic I want to follow Dr Evans in developing a dialectical definition of dialectic itself. This involves establishing the genus, or category, to which it belongs and setting out what properties define all the members of this category. Then I want to discuss how it is different to the other members of the category - it’s differentia. This will focus on the difference between dialectic and logic. 

The difference between dialectic and logic can be briefly and broadly explained by the fact logic (such as pure logic, formal logic) seeks absolute truth developed from true premises and sound argument, where dialectic seeks to persuade and calibrate arguments from the foundation of common sense.

Dialectic is therefore concerned with what people already understand, what is absolutely understandable, and how a person can guide her interlocutor from the first to the second position.

In the next article I will establish the essence of Aristotle’s dialectic.

This Author 

Brendan Montague is editor of  The Ecologist.  This article is part of the  Endoxa.review  project. 

Donate to The Ecologist and support high impact environmental journalism and analysis.

Birds in formation

The nature of Aristotle's dialectic

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

Freedom begins in the workplace

Birds

A dialectical definition of Aristotle's dialectic - Pt II

More from this author.

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

Movement power: action and tactics

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

Parents 'can seed ecological awareness'

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

Movement power: strategic and prefigurative

  • Editors’ Picks
  • Ecologist Writers' Fund
  • Biodiversity
  • Climate Breakdown
  • Economics and policy
  • Food and Farming
  • Yasmin Dahnoun
  • Catherine Early
  • Simon Pirani
  • Gareth Dale
  • Marianne Brown
  • Resurgence & Ecologist
  • Ecologist recycled
  • Movement Power
  • Megamorphosis

Library homepage

  • school Campus Bookshelves
  • menu_book Bookshelves
  • perm_media Learning Objects
  • login Login
  • how_to_reg Request Instructor Account
  • hub Instructor Commons

Margin Size

  • Download Page (PDF)
  • Download Full Book (PDF)
  • Periodic Table
  • Physics Constants
  • Scientific Calculator
  • Reference & Cite
  • Tools expand_more
  • Readability

selected template will load here

This action is not available.

Social Sci LibreTexts

Developing a Dialectical Perspective on Vygotsky’s Theory

  • First Online: 18 May 2018

Cite this chapter

aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

  • Manolis Dafermos 6  

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Cultural-Historical Research ((PCHR,volume 4))

1373 Accesses

1 Citations

The chapter proposes an alternative, dialectical reading of Vygotsky’s theory that may help us better understand its philosophical underpinnings. The chapter starts with a brief sketch of the history of dialectics. Αn attempt will be made to define dialectics and its main historical forms. Then, three key methodological issues of dialectics will be examined and its relations to Vygotsky’s theory: the relation between essence and phenomenon , the ascent from the abstract to the concrete and its relation to the movement of thinking from the sensory concrete to the abstract and the relation between the logical and historical method . The chapter includes also a reflection on the dialectical method and its application to psychology in the USSR.

We step and do not step into the same rivers, we are and are not . (Heraclitus) Dialectics consists in formulating a “ contradiction ,” bringing it to the fullest sharpness and clarity of expression, and then finding a real, concrete, object-related, and therefore obvious, resolution of it…dialectics is by no means a mysterious Art only for mature and select minds . It is the real logic of real thinking—a synonym for concrete thinking. People must be trained in it from childhood . (Ilyenkov 2007a , p. 24, 20)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

It is worth noting that the law of the negation of negation as well as any reference to the Hegelian concept “aufhebung” was omitted by Stalin in “Dialectical and historical materialism” (1938). Until Stalin’s death, a serious discussion on materialistic dialectic and its relation to Hegelian dialectic was impossible.

Lenin stated in his “Philosophical notebook”: “In Capital, Marx applied to a single science logic, dialectics and the theory of knowledge of materialism [three words are not needed: it is one and the same thing] which has taken everything valuable in Hegel and developed it further” (Lenin 1976 , p. 317).

Ilyenkov’s account of dialectical contradictions has been labeled by Bakhurst as “flawed” (Bakhurst 1991 , p. 170). The rejection of dialectical contradictions by Bakhurst ( 1991 ) has been justifiably criticized by Engeström for ignoring “the possibility that dialectical contradictions are foundationally different from the contradictions described in the formal-logical principle of noncontradiction” (Engeström 2015 , p. xxix).

For Ilyenkov, philosophy is the theory of thought, rather the objective world itself. During that period, Soviet philosophers were preoccupied with trying to find the relations between the external world of objects, on the one hand, and the internal world of thoughts, on the other. Rejecting ontologization of the subject matter of philosophy, Ilyenkov argued that the logic can be examined as its primary subject matter. Ilyenkov and his friend Korovikov presented their views on their famous “Theses” that caused controversy at the Faculty of philosophy of Moscow Moscow University (MGU). In the discussion that was sparked they were accused of “Hegelianism” and were sacked from MGU (Bakhurst 1991 , 2013 ; Ilyenkov and Korovikov 2016 ).

It is important to take into account the essential difference between the 1960s and 1970s in Soviet philosophy. The 1960s was “the golden age” in Soviet philosophy when new, creative insights emerged and high-level discussion on dialectics was achieved. In the 1970s the tendencies of the stagnation became dominant in the USSR and in Soviet philosophy. As Korovikov remarks “… Il’enkov left this world at a time when the momentum of history had gone from the Soviet project and Russian society was utterly stagnant, to use the metaphor that came to characterize the period. What killed Il’enkov, according to his friend, was the unspiritual (‘‘antidukhovnaja’’) atmosphere, from which all the oxygen had been sucked by careerists, cynics, and petty bureaucrats. In such a world, it was no longer possible to define one’s intellectual identity as a moment in the unfolding of a grand historical project” (Bakhurst 2013 , p. 284)

For illustrating the mismatch between the methodology in K. Marx’s “Das Kapital” and the application of the concept of activity in Soviet psychology, the following example can be used. Jones ( 2009 ) demonstrates that Marx used the concept of activity not in a general sense, but in the sense of the labor process involved in capitalist production, in a concrete, historically specific productive activity .

Allakhverdov, V. (2009). Razmyshlenie o nauke psikhologii s voskli tsa tel’nym znakom [Reflection on the Science of Psychology with an Exclamation Mark]. Sankt Petersburg: Format.

Google Scholar  

Arthur, C. J. (2004). The new dialectic and Marx’s Capital . Leiden: Brill.

Bakhurst, D. (1991). Consciousness and revolution in Soviet philosophy: From the Bolsheviks to Evald Ilyenkov . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bakhurst, D. (2013). Il’enkov’s Hegel. Studies in East European Thought, 65 (3), 271–285. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-014-9187-0 .

Article   Google Scholar  

Basseches, M. (1980). Dialectical schematas: A framework for the empirical study of the development of dialectical thinking. Human Development, 23, 400–442.

Basseches, M. (1984). Dialectical thinking and adult development . Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Basseches, M. (2005). The development of dialectical thinking as an approach to integration. Integral Review , 1 , 47.

Batishchev, G. S. (1990). The activity approach in the captivity of substantialism’. In V. A. Lektorsky (Ed.), Activity: Theories, methodology, and problems (pp. 169–176). Moscow: Politizdat.

Bidell, T. (1988). Vygotsky, Piaget and the dialectic of development. Human Development, 31, 329–348.

Blakeley, T. (1964). Soviet Philosophy. A general introduction to contemporary Soviet thought . Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

Blunden, A. (1997). Vygotsky and dialectical method . Retrieved September 15, 2017, from https://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/comment/vygotsk1.htm .

Blunden, A. (2010). An interdisciplinary theory of activity . Chicago: Haymarket Books.

Book   Google Scholar  

Blunden, A. (2013). Unit of Analysis . Retrieved September 12, 2017, from http://wiki.lchc.ucsd.edu/CHAT/Unit_of_Analysis .

Blunden, A. (2015). The germ cell of Vygotsky’s science . Retrieved September 12, 2017, from https://www.academia.edu/11387923/The_Germ_Cell_of_Vygotsky_s_Science .

Bochenski, J. M. (1961). Soviet Logic. In J. M. Bochenski & T. J. Blakeley (Eds.), Studies in Soviet thought (pp. 29–38). Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel Publishing Company.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Braun, C. M. J. (1991). The Marxist categories of the ‘abstract’ and ‘concrete” and the cultural-historical school of psychology. Multidisciplinary Newsletter for Activity Theory, 4, 36–41.

Brushlinskii, A. V. (2004). The activity approach and psychology. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 42 (2), 69–81.

Buss, A. R. (1979). A dialectical psychology . New York: Irvington.

Cole, M., & Scribner, S. (1978). Introduction. In M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner, & E. Souberman (Eds.), Mind in society : The development of higher psychological processes . L. S. Vygotsky (pp. 1–14). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Dafermos, M. (2014). Reductionism. In T. Teo (Ed.), Encyclopedia of critical psychology (pp. 1651–1653). Berlin: Springer.

Dafermos, M. (2015). Reflection on the relationship between cultural-historical theory and dialectics. Psychological Science and Education, 20 (3), 16–24.

Danziger, K. (1997). Naming the mind: How psychology found its language . London: Sage.

Danziger, K. (1999). Natural kinds, human kinds, and historicity. In W. Maiers et al. (Eds.), Challenges to theoretical psychology (pp. 78–83). Toronto: Captus Press.

Davydov, V. V. (1988). The Concept of theoretical generalization and problems of educational Psychology. Studies in Soviet Thought, 36, 169–202.

Davydov, V. V. (1990). The place of the category of activity in modern theoretical psychology. In V. P. Lektorsky (Ed.), Activity: The theory, methodology, and problems (pp. 75–82). Orlando, FL: Paul M. Deutsch Press, Inc.

Davydov, V. V. (1996). Teorija razvivajuscego obucenija [Theory of developmental education] . Moscow: Intor.

Davydov, V. V. (1998). Vygotsky, L. S. and the reform of today’s school. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 36 (4), 83–101.

Davydov, V., & Radzikhovskii, L. (1985). L. Vygotsky’s theory and the activity oriented approach in psychology. In J. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication and cognition: Vygotskian perspectives (pp. 35–65). Cambridge: University Press.

Descartes, R. (1985). Rules for the direction of the mind. In Descartes (Ed.), The philosophical writings of Descartes (J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch) (Vol. I, pp. 7–78). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Dreier, O., & Kvale, S. (1984). Dialectical and hermeneutical psychology. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 25, 5–19.

Duarte, N. (2011). Vygotsky and the dialectical appropriation of reality by scientific knowledge . Paper presented at ISCAR Congress, Rome, 8th September. Retrieved September 12, 2017, from https://www.academia.edu/958469/Vygotsky_and_the_Dialectical_Appropriation_of_Reality_by_Scientific_Knowledge .

Elhammoumi, M. (2015). Marxist psychology and dialectical method. In I. Parker (Ed.), Handbook of critical psychology (pp. 271–279). New York: Routledge.

Engels, F. (1859). Review “A contribution to the critique of political economy”. Retrieved September 12, 2017, from https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/download/Marx_Contribution_to_the_Critique_of_Political_Economy.pdf .

Engels, F. (1987). Dialectics of nature . In K. Marx, & F. Engels (Eds.), Collected works (Vol. 25, pp. 313–590). London: Lawrence & Wishart.

Engeström, Y. (2015). Learning by expanding: An activity-theoretical approach to developmental research . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Friedrich, R. W. (1972). Dialectical sociology: toward a resolution of the current ‘crisis’ in Western sociology. The British Journal of Sociology, 23 (3), 263–274.

Galperin, P. (1999). Vvedenie v psycholgiu [Introduction to psychology]. Moscow: Rostov na Donu-Kniznii Dom Feniks.

Galperin, P. Y., & Elkonin, D. B. (1967). K analizu teorii Z. Piaze o razvitii detskogo myslenia [Analysis of J. Piaget’s Theory on development of children’s thinking]. In J. H. Flavell (Ed.), Genetisheskaja psihologia Zana Piaze [The Developmental Psychology of Jean Piaget] (pp. 596–621). Moscow: Prosveshenie.

Georgoudi, M. (1983). Modem dialectics in social psychology: A reappraisal. European Journal of Social Psychology, 13, 77–93.

Gergen, K. (1982). Toward transformation in social knowledge . New York: Springer.

Greenwood, J. D. (2004). The disappearance of the social in American social psychology . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Groisman, B. (2007). What is dialectic? Some remarks on Popper’s criticism. Retrieved September 15, 2017, from http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/3980/ .

Hegel, G. V. F. (1970). Raboty pasnykh let [Works from various years] (Vol. 1, p. 265). Moscow: Misl.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1991). Encyclopaedia of philosophical sciences (T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, & H. S. Harris, part 1, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

Hegel, G. W. F. (2004). Phenomenology of spirit (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hegel, G. W. F. (2010). The science of logic (G. di Giovanni, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ilyenkov, E. (1953). Some issues of materialist dialectics in Marx’s “A contribution to the critique of political economy”. Moscow: Moscow State University. Retrieved September 12, 2017, from http://caute.ru/ilyenkov/texts/cand/index.html .

Ilyenkov, E. (1960). The dialectics of the abstract and the concrete in Marx’s ‘Capital’ . Moscow: Academy of Sciences of USSR.

Ilyenkov, E. (1970). Psikhika cheloveka pod ‘lupoj vremeni’ [The human psyche under ‘time’s looking glass’]. Priroda, 1, 89–91.

Ilyenkov, E. (1979). Problema protovorichija ve logike [The problem of contradiction in logic]. In B. M. Kedrov (Ed.), Dialekticheskoe protovorechie [Dialectical contradiction] (pp. 122–143). Moscow: Politizdat.

Ilyenkov, E. (1991). Ancient dialectics as form of thinking. In E. Ilyenkov (Ed.), Philosophy and culture (pp. 56–100). Moscow: Political Literature.

Ilyenkov, E. (2007a). Our schools must teach how to think! Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 45 (4), 9–49.

Ilyenkov, E. (2007b). A contribution on the question of the concept of “activity” and its significance for pedagogy. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 45 (4), 69–74.

Ilyenkov, E. (2009). The Ideal in human activity . Pacifica, CA: Marxists Internet Archive.

Ilyenkov, E., & Korovikov, V. (2016). Strasti po tezisam [Passions of the Theses]. Moscow: Canon.

Jones, P. (2009). Breaking away from Capital ? Theorising activity in the shadow of Marx. Outlines, 1, 45–58.

Jovanovic, G. (2015). Vicissitudes of history in Vygotsky’s cultural historical theory. History of the Human Sciences, 28 (2), 10–33.

Kakarinos, G. (2013). Methodological reflections on Leontiev’s activity theory: Activity theory and “The logic of history”. In A. Marvakis, J. Motzkau, D. Painter, R. Ruto-Korir, G. Sullivan, S. Triliva, & M. Wieser (Eds.), Doing psychology under new conditions (pp. 279–288). Ontario: Captus Press.

Kant, E. (1998). Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer, & A. Wood, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kedrov, B. M. (1979). Protivoreshivost poznanija i poznanie protivoreshijia [Contradictoriness of knowledge and knowledge of contradiction]. In B. M. Kedrov (Ed.), Dialekticheskoe protivorechie [Dialectical contradiction] (pp. 9–38). Moscow: Politizdat.

Khamidov, A. (2016). The evolution of Batishchev’s views on the nature of objective activity, and the limits of the activity approach. In A. Maidansky, & V. Oittinen (Eds.), The practical essence of Man. The ‘activity approach’ in late Soviet philosophy (pp. 120–136). Leiden: Koninklijke Brill.

Kosik, K. (1976). Dialectics of the concrete: A study on problems of man and world . Dordrecht, Holland, Boston: R. Reidel Publishing Company.

Kozulin, A., & Gindis, B. (2007). Sociocultural thinking and education of children with special needs. From defectology to remedial pedagogy. In H. Daniels, M. Cole, & J. V. Wertsch (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Vygotsky (pp. 332–362). New York: Cambridge University Press.

Lektorsky, V. (2016). The activity approach in Soviet philosophy and contemporary cognitive studies, In A. Maidansky, & V. Oittinen (Eds.), The practical essence of man. The ‘activity approach’ in late Soviet philosophy (pp. 137–153). Leiden: Koninklijke Brill.

Lenin, V. I. (1976). Collected works (Vol. 38). Moscow: Progress publishers.

Leontiev, A. N. (2005). Study of the environment in the pedological works of L. S. Vygotsky. A Critical Study. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 43 (4), 8–28.

Leontiev, A. N. (2009a). Activity and consciousness . Pacifica, CA: Marxists Internet Archive.

Leontiev, A. N. (2009b). The development of mind . Pacifica, CA: Marxists Internet Archive.

Levant, A., & Oittinen, V. (2014). Ilyenkov in the context of Soviet philosophical culture: An interview with Sergey Mareev. In A. Levant & V. Oittinen (Eds.), Dialectics of the ideal: Evald Ilyenkov and creative Soviet Marxism (pp. 81–98). Leiden, Boston: Brill.

Levin, R., & Lewontin, R. (1985). The dialectical biologist . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Luria, A. R. (1976). Cognitive development: Its cultural and social foundations . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Luria, A. R. (1982). Language and cognition . New York: Wiley.

Luria, A., & Vygotsky, L. (1992). Ape, primitive man, and child: Essays in the history of behavior . New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

Maidansky, A. (2016). Reality as activity: The concept of praxis in Soviet philosophy. In A. Maidansky, & V. Oittinen (Eds.), The practical essence of Man. The ‘activity approach’ in late Soviet philosophy (pp. 42–57). Leiden: Koninklijke Brill.

Mankovskij, L. A. (1962). Logischeskie kategorii v ‘Kapitale’ K. Marksa [The logical concepts of ‘Capital’]. Moscow: Moskovksii Pedagogisheskii Insitut imeni Lenina. Uschenie Zapiski 179.

Mareev, S. (2016). Abstract and concrete understanding of activity: ‘Activity’ and ‘labour’ in Soviet philosophy. In A. Maidansky, & V. Oittinen (Eds.), The practical essence of man. The ‘activity approach in late Soviet philosophy (pp. 96–102). Leiden: Koninklijke Brill.

Marx, K. (1865). Letter to F. Engels, 31 July. In K. Marx, & F. Engels (Eds.), Correspondence. Retrieved September 12, 2017, from http://marxists.anu.edu.au/archive/marx/works/1865/letters/65_07_31.htm .

Marx. K. (1975). Contribution to the critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of law. In K. Marx, & F. Engels (Eds.), Collected works (Vol. 3, pp. 3–129). London: Lawrence & Wishart.

Marx, K. (1976). Capital. A critique of political economy . London: Penguin Books.

Marx, K. (1986). Economic manuscript 1857–1858. Introduction. In K. Marx, & F. Engels (Eds.), Collected works (Vol. 28, pp. 17–48). London: Lawrence & Wishart.

Mikhailov, F. (1980). The riddle of the self . Moscow: Progress. Retrieved September 12, 2017, from https://www.marxists.org/archive/mikhailov/works/riddle/riddle1c.htm .

Naumenko, L. K. (1968). Monism kak printsip dialekticheskoy logiki [Monism as a postulate of dialectical logic] . Alma-Ata: Nauka.

Nikoulin, D. (2010). Dialectic and dialogue . Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.

Nissen, M. (2012). The subjectivity of participation. Articulating social work practice with youth in Copenhagen . New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Ollman, B. (2003). Dance of the dialectic. Steps in Marx’s method . Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

Orudzev, Z. M. (1964). K. Marks i dialektisheskaja logika [K. Marx and dialectical logic]. Baku: Azerbaizdankaja gosudarsvenaja izdatelsctvo.

Patelis, D. (2011). Socio-philosophical heritage and the logic of History. Fragmentos de Cultura, Goiânia, 21 (7/9), 389–414.

Plato (1997a). Cratylus. In Plato, J. M. Cooper (Eds.), Complete works (pp. 101–156). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

Plato (1997b). Republic. In Plato, J. M. Cooper (Eds.), Complete works (pp. 971–1223). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

Popper, K. (1940). What is dialectic? Mind, 49 (196), 403–426.

Rescher, N. (2007). Dialectics. A classical approach to inquiry . Frankfurt, Paris: Ontos verlag.

Riegel, K. F. (1973). Dialectic operations: The final period of cognitive development. Human Development, 16, 346–370.

Riegel, K. F. (1979). Foundations of dialectical psychology . New York: Academic Press.

Robbins, D. (1999). Prologue. In R. Richer, & A. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of Vygotsky (Vol. 6, pp. v–xxii). New York: Plenum Press.

Robbins, D. (2003). Vygotsky’s non-classical dialectical metapsychology. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 33 (3), 303–312.

Rothenberg, A. (1996). The Janusian process in scientific creativity. Creativity Research Journal, 9, 207–231. https://doi.org/10.1080/10400419.1996.9651173 .

Rozental, M. M. (1952). Marksistsky dialektichesky metod [Marxist dialectical method] . Moscow: Gospolitizdat.

Rozental, M. M. (1955). Voprosy dialektiki v ‘Kapitale’ Marksa [Questions of dialectic in Marx’ ‘Capital’]. Moscow: Gospolitizdat.

Rozental, M. M. (1967). Dialektika ‘Kapitala’ K. Marksa [The dialectic of K. Marx’s ‘Capital’]. Moscow: Mysl.

Rubinštejn, S. L. (1958). O mischnenii i putiah evo islledovania [On thinking and ways of its investigation]. Moscow: Institute of Philosophy of Academy of Sciences of USSR.

Rubinštejn, S. L. (1987). Problems of psychology in the works of Karl Marx. Studies in Soviet Thought, 33 (2), 111–130.

Sheehan, H. (1993). Marxism and the philosophy of science: A critical history . Atlantic Highlands, N. J.: Humanities Press International.

Sokolova, E. E. (2011). Dialectical logic of cultural and activity psychology as a tool to identify the nature of mental reality. Psychology in Russia: State of the art, 4, 24–38.

Stetsenko, A. (2010). Standing on the shoulders of giants: A balancing act of dialectically theorizing conceptual understanding on the grounds of Vygotsky’s project. In W.-M. Roth (Ed.), Re/structuring science education: ReUniting psychological and sociological perspectives (pp. 53–72). New York: Springer.

Suvorov, A. V. (2003). Experimental philosophy (E. V. Ilyenkov and A. I. Meshcheriakov). Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 41 (6), 67–91.

Tipuhin, V. N. (1961). Metod voshozdenija ot abstraktnovo k konkretnomu v ‘Kapitale’ K. Marksa [The method of the ascent from the abstract to the concrete in K. Marx’s Capital]. Omsk: Omskii Selskohozjaisvenii Institut imeni S. M. Kirova.

Toulmin, S., & Leary, D. E. (1985). The cult of empiricism in psychology, and beyond. In S. Koch & D. E. Leary (Eds.), A century of psychology as science (pp. 594–617). New York: McGraw-Hill.

Tse, L. (1904). The book of the simple way . London: Philip Wellby.

Van der Veer, R., & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky. A quest for synthesis . Oxford: Blackwell.

Van der Zweerde, E. (1997). Soviet historiography of philosophy . Springer Science+Business Media.

Vazjulin, V. A. (1968a). Logika ‘Kapitala’ Karla Marksa [The logic of Karl Marx’s ‘Capital’]. Moscow: MGU.

Vazjulin, V. A. (1968b). Problema issledovanija protivoreschija v ‘Capitale’ K. Marksa [The problem of investigation of contradiction in K. Marx’s ‘Capital’]. Vestnik Mosk. Universiteta , Ser. 8, Philosophy , 2 , 32–40.

Vazjulin, V. A. (1970). Methodologischeskaja rol problemi istorischeskovo i logischeskovo v konkretnih naukah [The methodological role of the problem of historical and logical in the concrete sciences]. In V. Molotsova & A. Ilina (Eds.), Methodologischeskie problemi sovremennoi nauki [Methodological problems of contemporary science] (pp. 100–126). Moscow: MGU.

Vazjulin, V. A. (1985). Rassudocnoe i razumnoe myslenije v razvitii poznanija [Understanding and reason in the development of cognition]. In M. N. Alekseev & A. M. Korshunov (Eds.), Dialektika protsessa poznanija [Dialectics of the cognitive process] (pp. 173–197). Moscow: MGU.

Veraksa, N. E. (2010). Structural approach to dialectic cognition. Psychology in Russia: State of the Art, 3, 227–239.

Veresov, N. (1999). Undiscovered Vygotsky . Frankfurt am Main and New York: Peter Lang.

Veresov, N. (2000). Vygotsky, Ilyenkov and Mamardashvili. Towards a monistic theory of mind (methodological notes). In V. Oittinen (Ed.), Evald Ilyenkov’s philosophy revisited (pp. 131–145). Helsinki: Kikimora Publishers.

Veresov, N. (2014). Refocusing the lens on development: Towards genetic research methodology. In M. Fleer, & A. Ridgway (Eds.), Visual methodologies and digital tools for researching with young children (pp. 129–149). Springer.

Veresov, N., & Fleer, M. (2016). Perezhivanie as a theoretical concept for researching young children’s development. Mind, Culture, and Activity . https://doi.org/10.1080/10749039.2016.1186198 .

Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes . Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). Thinking and speech . In R. W. Rieber, & A. S. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (Vol. 1, pp. 39–285). New York: Plenum Press.

Vygotsky, L. (1993). The difficult child. In R. W. Rieber, & A. S. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (Vol. 2, pp. 139–149). New York: Plenum Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1994). The problem of the environment. In R. Van der Veer & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The Vygotsky reader (pp. 338–354). Oxford: Blackwell.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1996). Leksii po pedologii [Lectures on pedology]. Ijevsk: Edition University of Udmourty.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1997a). The historical meaning of the crisis of psychology. In R. Rieber, & J. Wolloc (Eds.), The collected works of L .S. Vygotsky (Vol. 3, pp. 233–344). New York, London: Plenum Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1997b). Preface to Koffka. The problem of development in structural psychology. In R. W. Rieber (Ed.), The collected works of L .S. Vygotsky (Vol. 3, pp. 195–232). New York, London: Plenum Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1997c). The history and development of higher mental functions. In R. W. Reiber (Ed.), The collected Works of L. S. Vygotsky (Vol. 4, 1–252). New York: Plenum Press.

Vygotsky, L. (1998a). The problem of age. In R. Rieber (Ed.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (Vol. 5, pp. 187–205). New York, London: Plenum Press.

Vygotsky, L. (1998b). The pedology of the adolescent. In R. Rieber (Ed.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (Vol. 5, pp. 3–186). New York, London: Plenum Press.

Walsh, R. T. G., Teo, T., & Baydala, A. (2014). A critical history and philosophy of psychology: Diversity of context, thought, and practice . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wong, W. C. (2006). Understanding dialectical thinking from a cultural–historical perspective. Philosophical Psychology, 19 (2), 239–260.

Yan, B., & Arlin, P. (1999). Dialectical thinking: implications for creativity thinking. In M. A. Runco, & S. R. Pritzker (Eds.), Encyclopedia of creativity (Vol. 1, pp. 547–552). San Diego, Calif., London: Academic Press.

Yaroshevsky, M. G., & Gurgenidze, G. S. (1997). Epilogue. In R. W. Rieber, & J. Wollock (Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (Vol. 3, pp. 345–370). New York: Plenum Press.

Yudin, E. G. (1976). Activity as an explanatory principle and as a subject of scientific study. Voprosy Filosofii, 5, 65–78.

Zinov’ev, A. A. (1973). Foundation of scientific knowledge . Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Psychology, University of Crete, Rethymnon, Greece

Manolis Dafermos

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Manolis Dafermos .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Dafermos, M. (2018). Developing a Dialectical Perspective on Vygotsky’s Theory. In: Rethinking Cultural-Historical Theory. Perspectives in Cultural-Historical Research, vol 4. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-0191-9_9

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-0191-9_9

Published : 18 May 2018

Publisher Name : Springer, Singapore

Print ISBN : 978-981-13-0190-2

Online ISBN : 978-981-13-0191-9

eBook Packages : Education Education (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

IMAGES

  1. Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis

    aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

  2. Thesis Antithesis Synthesis Ppt

    aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

  3. What Is Antithesis, and How Do You Use It in Writing?

    aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

  4. Thesis Antithesis Synthesis Ppt

    aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

  5. thesis and antithesis method

    aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

  6. thesis and antithesis method

    aristotle thesis antithesis synthesis

VIDEO

  1. Thesis, Anti-thesis & Synthesis

  2. Dialectic and Praxis 12 of 18

  3. Thesis, antithesis, synthesis

  4. Lecture Designing Organic Syntheses 15 Prof G Dyker 261114

  5. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's Philosophy (Tagalog-English)

  6. History class 10📚Thesis Antithesis Synthesis 📚 #msdhoni #cricket #history #ipl #exam #study #test t

COMMENTS

  1. Hegel's Dialectics

    For G.R.G. Mure, for instance, the section on Cognition fits neatly into a triadic, thesis-antithesis-synthesis account of dialectics because the whole section is itself the antithesis of the previous section of Hegel's logic, the section on Life (Mure 1950: 270).

  2. Dialectic

    In classical philosophy, dialectic ( διαλεκτική) is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter-arguments, advocating propositions (theses) and counter-propositions ( antitheses ). The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition, or of a synthesis, or a combination of the opposing ...

  3. Hegel's Dialectic: A Comprehensive Overview

    An overview of Hegel's dialectic, a philosophical theory that explains how ideas progress through thesis, antithesis and synthesis.

  4. Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis

    In philosophy, the triad of thesis, antithesis, synthesis (German: These, Antithese, Synthese; originally: Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis) is a progression of three ideas or propositions. The first idea, the thesis, is a formal statement illustrating a point; it is followed by the second idea, the antithesis, that contradicts or negates the first; and lastly, the third idea, the synthesis ...

  5. Contradiction

    The contradiction between thesis and antithesis results in the dialectical resolution or superseding of the contradiction between opposites as a higher-level synthesis through the process of Aufhebung (from aufheben, a verb simultaneously interpretable as 'preserve, cancel, lift up').

  6. Excerpt from Hegel for Beginners

    In classical logic, this double negation ("A is not non-A") would simply reinstate the original thesis. The synthesis does not do this. It has "overcome and preserved" (or sublated) the stages of the thesis and antithesis to emerge as a higher rational unity.

  7. PDF The Dialectical Circumplex Model: A Theory of Dialectic and Its

    Undiscovered Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis Dialectics, however, reaffirms the connection between Hegel and the triadic dialectic while offering a reinterpretation of the Hegelian dialectical format. ... Two-dimensional circumplex model based on Aristotle's conception of the four

  8. dialectic

    The general formulation of Hegel's dialectic is a three-step process comprising the movement from thesis to antithesis to synthesis. One begins with a static, clearly delineated concept (or thesis), then moves to its opposite (or antithesis), which represents any contradictions derived from a consideration of the rigidly defined thesis.

  9. Analysis, Synthesis and Dialectic: Hegel's Answer to Aristotle, Newton

    No reader of the Science of Logic interested in the history and philosophy of science, will fail to observe that in Hegel's doctrine of method the two ancient ways of analysis and synthesis constitute the immediate precursor of the dialectic, which forms the crown of his whole system.

  10. The Antinomy of Pure Reason

    Chapter5 analyzes the general structure of the antinomy of pure reason and the specific structures of its four versions, including a detailed logical reconstruction of all thesis and antithesis proofs. To understand the logical structure and epistemological...

  11. On Aristotle's dialectical method

    On Aristotle's dialectical method. The aims, scope and method of Aristotle's dialectic. Dialectic is a process of discovery and pedagogy that takes place between two individuals using logical argument, according to Aristotle. To an extent, this is the same as the familiar "thesis, antithesis, synthesis" to which Aristotle's dialectic is ...

  12. Antithesis

    In dialectics (any formal system of reasoning that arrives at the truth by the exchange of logical arguments) antithesis is the juxtaposition of contrasting ideas, usually in a balanced way. The logical arguments are said to be stated in the order thesis, antithesis, synthesis .

  13. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

    The final proposition, that despite the potential immorality of aborting a fetus, there are certain values to be considered in the practice, is the synthesis. The human mind is full of contradictory thoughts and notions (thesis v. antithesis) but continuously strives to find resolution in the synthesis.

  14. Hegel's Eurocentric Triads of Dialectics and Its Transformation to

    To be more important, the essence of the idealistic system rested on a triad of thesis—antithesis—synthesis which corrected Descartes' rational Foundationalism by means of absorbing the principles of Bacon's inductive reasoning which was, however, in contrast with Aristotle's deductive reasoning [25].

  15. 8.2: Plato and Aristotle

    The Dialectic Approach involved developing an opening thesis or position and an antithesis or opposite position. These positions were fully developed and discussed. The goal of this dialogue was to arrive at synthesis, which Plato said could be considered the absolute Truth. Synthesis could be thesis, antithesis, or a new position developed during the dialogue process. To Plato, synthesis ...

  16. Dialectic

    Although Kant, in his Transcendental Dialectic, had set out the antinomies of pure reason as four sets of thesis and antithesis, he did not call his resolution of the antinomies a synthesis.

  17. Hegel's Undiscovered Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis Dialectics

    For over fifty years, Hegel interpreters have rejected the former belief that Hegel used thesis-antithesis-synthesis dialectics. In this incisive analysis of Hegel's philosophy, Leonard F. Wheat shows that the modern interpretation is false.

  18. PDF Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis

    His central thesis is that liberalism's commit-ment to individual liberty will be vindicated only if it incorporates critical Marxian insights. The resulting synthesis—Marxian Liberalism—secures the fullest possible principles of justice and the widest scope for liberty that historical circumstances permit.

  19. PDF On the development of Dialectical Materialism

    In this first methodical thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, whereof the latter consists in a process or course of gradually closer self-determination, we have at once an example or type of all succeeding theses, and shall understand these the more readily, by referring to the above simple movement of thought." (Chalybäus 1837 [1854]).

  20. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

    Fichte introduced into German philosophy the three-step of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, using these three terms. Schelling took up this terminology. Hegel did not. He never once used these three terms together to designate three stages in an argument or account in any of his books.

  21. Thesis, antithesis, synthesis

    The synthesis solves the conflict between the thesis and antithesis by reconciling their common truths and forming a new thesis, starting the process over.

  22. Developing a Dialectical Perspective on Vygotsky's Theory

    Ollman ( 2003) calls into question the equation of dialectics with the simplistic triadic formula of "thesis-antithesis-synthesis " and offers a general definition of dialectics: "…dialectics is a way of thinking that brings into focus the full range of changes and interactions that occur in the world" (Ollman 2003, p. 12).

  23. Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis

    Katz, C. "Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis." Review of Politics 75(3), 2013. This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications and Other Works by Department at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science: Faculty Publications and Other Works by an authorized administrator of Loyola ...