Bodleian Libraries

  • Bodleian Libraries
  • Oxford LibGuides
  • Dissertations

Music: Dissertations

  • Online Resources
  • Collections overview

Dissertations on music

Oxford dissertations  have traditionally been deposited in hard-copy in the Bodleian and are treated as manuscripts. All doctoral dissertations now have entries on SOLO  and many more recent theses are available in full-text through Oxford's research repository ORA . Composition degrees also involve the deposit of portfolio submissions or degree 'exercises', many of which (some dating back to the 18th century) are held in the Weston Library.

For general information on accessing theses and dissertations, click here .

The principal published lists of dissertations on music are:

  • Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology – Online . DDM  is a free international database of bibliographic records for completed dissertations and new dissertation topics in the fields of musicology, music theory, and ethnomusicology, as well as in related musical, scientific, and humanistic disciplines. Hosted by the American Musicological Society, the database currently containing over 14,000 records, including the corrected and updated contents of all earlier printed editions of Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology and its supplements contributed from musicological centres throughout the world.
  • ProQuest Dissertations & Theses Global (PQDT) is the world's most comprehensive collection of full-text dissertations and theses in all subjects. As the official digital dissertations archive for the Library of Congress and as the database of record for graduate research, PQDTGlobal includes millions of searchable citations to dissertations and theses from 1861 to the present day together with over a million full-text dissertations that are available for download in PDF format. Over 2.1 million titles are available for purchase as printed copies. The database offers full text for most of the dissertations added since 1997 and strong retrospective full-text coverage for older graduate works. It also includes content from PQDT UK & Ireland (aka Index to Theses). 
  • EThOS (Electronic Theses Online Service) is a British Library service covering dissertations from most British universities. Search over 500,000 doctoral theses and register for free to download instantly for your research, or order a scanned copy quickly and easily. Hard-copy theses can sometimes be made available in the Bodleian on Inter-Library Loan .
  • Archive of Dissertation Abstracts in Music  provides abstracts both to completed dissertations and to those in progress.

Other sources for European dissertations:

  • DART-Europe E-theses Portal  provides access to 1,079,176 open access research theses from 570 Universities in 29 European countries.
  • Full retrospective lists of German-language dissertations to 1970 will be found in Richard Schaal: Verzeichnis deutschsprachiger musikwissenschaftlicher Dissertationen (Bärenreiter, 1963; with supplement 1974). Retrospective coverage of French dissertations will be found in Jean Gribenski's printed guide: Thèses de doctorat en langue française relatives à la musique (Pendragon Press, 1979).
  • Many printed dissertations from European universities, and a small number of American dissertations, are held by the Bodleian. Most can be found on SOLO .
  • << Previous: Online Resources
  • Next: Collections overview >>
  • Last Updated: Apr 24, 2024 11:21 AM
  • URL: https://libguides.bodleian.ox.ac.uk/music

Website feedback

Accessibility Statement - https://visit.bodleian.ox.ac.uk/accessibility

Google Analytics - Bodleian Libraries use Google Analytics cookies on this web site. Google Analytics anonymously tracks individual visitor behaviour on this web site so that we can see how LibGuides is being used. We only use this information for monitoring and improving our websites and content for the benefit of our users (you). You can opt out of Google Analytics cookies completely (from all websites) by visiting https://tools.google.com/dlpage/gaoptout

© Bodleian Libraries 2021. Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International Licence

Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology

Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology (DDM) is an international database of bibliographic records for completed dissertations and new dissertation topics in the fields of musicology, music theory, and ethnomusicology, as well as in related musical, scientific, and humanistic disciplines.

  • Report a new dissertation
  • Update an existing dissertation record

What is included

The fully searchable database containing over 16,400 records, including the corrected and updated contents of all earlier printed editions of Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology and supplements contributed from musicological centers throughout the world. Records include normal bibliographic information as well as publication details and internet availability (if available).

References to the following tools are also included when available:

  • Dissertation Express

What is not included

DDM does not include the dissertations themselves.

Additional information and background

A number of dissertations awarded by UK institutions and included here are also listed in the British Library’s EThOS E-Theses database . Over 100,000 are available for immediate, free download. For many others, you can order a scanned copy (charges may apply)

This implementation of DDM was prepared by Durrell Bowman in 2010. Click here for further information about DDM and a short history of the project.

The AMS is grateful to people and institutions who have worked hard to make DDM a useful research tool: Durrell Bowman, Peter Slemon, Thomas Mathiesen, Alis Dickinson, Cecil Adkins, Helen Hewitt, Indiana University, and the University of North Texas.

RSS Feed

  • Administration
  • Best Practices
  • Study Groups
  • NYU/AMS Lectures
  • AMS/LC Lectures
  • AMS/RRHOFM Lectures
  • Administrative Handbook
  • Join or Renew
  • Alvin H. Johnson AMS 50
  • Howard Mayer Brown
  • Travel and Research Grants
  • Awards / Prizes
  • Publication subventions
  • AMS 75 PAYS subventions
  • List of recurring grants
  • Journal of the AMS
  • AMS Studies
  • Music of the USA
  • Works of William Billings
  • Doctoral Dissertations (DDM)
  • Books supported by the AMS
  • Other Publications
  • AMS and RILM-U.S.
  • Musicology links
  • AMS-Announce BB and list
  • RSS Feeds at the AMS
  • Jrnl Music History Pedagogy
  • How to make a contribution
  • Grad programs
  • Historical Resources
  • Forensic musicology
  • Information for Advertisers
  • Music Books for Children
  • Other questions? Ask us!

Copyright © 2003-2024 the American Musicological Society, Inc. All rights reserved. American Musicological Society, Inc. • 20 Cooper Square, Floor 2 • New York, NY 10003 tel. 212-992-6340 • toll-free tel./fax 877-679-7648 Contact us      •      Privacy Policy      •      Refund Policy      •      Report a web site error

  • Harvard Library
  • Research Guides
  • Faculty of Arts & Sciences Libraries

Music Research Guide

Dissertations and theses.

  • HOLLIS (Library catalog and more)
  • Dictionaries, Encyclopedias, Bibliographies
  • Recordings and Videos
  • Scores and Sheet Music
  • Concert Reviews
  • Collected Works Editions
  • Music in Special Collections
  • Ethnomusicology Research @ Harvard
  • Jazz Research @ Harvard This link opens in a new window
  • American Indigenous Music
  • Senior Thesis Style Guide: Footnotes
  • Senior Thesis Style Guide: Bibliography
  • Multimedia Production Resources
  • ProQuest Dissertations and Theses Global (AKA Dissertation Abstracts) Full text of graduate works added since 1997, along with selected full text for works written prior to 1997 and citations for dissertations and theses dating from 1743-present.
  • DASH (Digital Access to Scholarship at Harvard) A central, open-access repository of research (including dissertations and scholarly articles) by members of the Harvard community.
  • Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology - Online (DDM) A bibliography of completed dissertations and proposed topics in musicology, music theory, ethnomusicology, and related disciplines. Maintained by the American Musicological Society.
  • MTO Dissertation Index An index of dissertations in music theory, with abstracts and tables of contents, maintained by the Society for Music Theory.
  • << Previous: Collected Works Editions
  • Next: Music in Special Collections >>

Except where otherwise noted, this work is subject to a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License , which allows anyone to share and adapt our material as long as proper attribution is given. For details and exceptions, see the Harvard Library Copyright Policy ©2021 Presidents and Fellows of Harvard College.

Finding Music Materials

Why use dissertations for your research.

Dissertations are excellent sources of trustworthy, thorough, and narrowly-focused research. They represent the cutting-edge of research on music, and provide in-depth analysis of everything for composers' styles, their works, and their lives. For performers, dissertations can be great sources for annotated bibliographies of repertoire, and they can also include detailed examination of specific works that can help with everything from tonal analysis to performance practice. Lastly, they include really helpful bibliographies and lists of references that can help you to find other relevant sources for your own research.

The dissertation databases below represent a range of resources:

  • Some provide   full-text access  to PDFs of dissertations (look for the PDF icon or a button that says download PDF)  
  • Others list author names and other publication information that you can use to place a request for the item through interlibrary loan . 

Top pick for finding dissertations: ProQuest Dissertation and Theses Global

  • Dissertations and Theses Global This link opens in a new window Collection of dissertations and theses from around the world, offering millions of works from thousands of universities. Each year hundreds of thousands of works are added. Full-text coverage spans from 1743 to the present, with citation coverage dating back to 1637.

ProQuest Dissertations & Theses should be your first stop for searching for dissertations because:

An image of the "Download PDF" button from the ProQuest Dissertations and Theses database.

TIP: Want to see what dissertations are available from other institutions around the world and that you can't access through ProQuest Dissertations & Theses Global? Check out the links at the bottom of this page, and contact Jessica Abbazio, Music Librarian, at [email protected] for help!

What to do when you can't access a pdf/the full text of a dissertation.

  • Some provide full-text access to PDFs of dissertations (look for the PDF icon or a button that says download PDF)  
  • Others list author names and other publication information that you can use to place a request for the item through interlibrary loan . If you locate a dissertation you need but can't access a full-text document, try clicking the maroon and gold M-Find It button (if you see one):

An image of the M-Find It button that appears in Libraries digital resources when the Libraries does not have direct access to a resource and it's necessary to request it through interlibrary loan.

Clicking the M-Find It button will take you to the Libraries catalog, where you should click on the Interlibrary Loan (ILL) link to place a request through the ILL system:

An image of the interlibrary loan link that appears in the catalog record after a user clicks the M-Find It button to access an item to which the University Libraries does not have direct access.

If you don't see an M-Find It button, you can place a request for the item by filling out a form on the the Libraries Interlibrary Loan page:

  • Visit the ILL homepage at  lib.umn.edu/interlibraryloan  

An image of the University Libraries Interlibrary Loan homepage with an arrow pointing to the link for the form needed to create a delivery request for a thesis or dissertation.

  • Once you're logged in with your University ID and password, fill out the form with as much information as you have about the dissertation (NOTE: If you found the resource in one of the dissertation databases below, it's helpful to keep that page open in a tab on your browser; all of the information you'll need to complete this form should be available for you to copy and paste from the database.)

Questions? Need help? Contact Jessica Abbazio, Music Librarian, at [email protected]

Find dissertations and conference papers.

  • Center for Research Libraries Global Resources Network Looking for a dissertation that was not published in the US or Canada? Search for it in the Center for Research Libraries (CRL) Global Resources Network. Not finding the dissertation you're looking for? Contact Jessica Abbazio, Music Librarian, at [email protected] to learn about options.
  • DART Europe e-Theses Portal Access to over 800,00 open access research theses from 617 Universities in 28 European countries.
  • Dissertationsmeldestelle der Gesellschaft für Musikforschung Open repository of German-language dissertations from Austria, Switzerland, and Germany. Some publications from other European countries are included. Documents date from 1998 and later.
  • Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology The American Musicological Society's Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology (DDM) is an international database of bibliographic records for completed dissertations and new dissertation topics in the fields of musicology, music theory, and ethnomusicology, as well as in related musical, scientific, and humanistic disciplines. The fully searchable database containing over 16,400 records, including the corrected and updated contents of all earlier printed editions of Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology and supplements contributed from musicological centers throughout the world. Records include normal bibliographic information as well as publication details and internet availability (if available). DDM does not include the dissertations themselves.
  • ERIC Education (Ebscohost) ERIC (Education Resources Information Center) is a database of full-text education literature and resources. With coverage dating back to 1966, it is essential for education researchers of all kinds.
  • Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations A free catalog of over 5 million electronic theses and dissertations published by an international group of around 175 institutions.
  • RILM Abstracts of Music Literature with Full Text RILM Abstracts of Music Literature with Full Text is a comprehensive bibliography of writings about music featuring citations, abstracts, and indexes. It covers over one million publications from the early 19th century to the present on traditional music, popular music, classical music, and related subjects, enhanced with the full text of more than 200 periodicals.
  • Theses Canada Portal Free database of over 500,000 Canadian theses dating from 1965 and later. Theses Canada is a collaborative program between Library and Archives Canada (LAC) and nearly 70 universities accredited by Universities Canada. Documents completed in 1998 and later are available in full text; earlier publications are available in microform through interlibrary loan.
  • University of Minnesota Digital Conservancy The University of Minnesota Digital Conservancy (UDC) is a venue for faculty to deposit open access copies of their scholarly work, a showcase for select student works, such as dissertations and honors theses, a home to the Data Repository for the University of Minnesota (DRUM), and centralized, searchable access to institutional digital records including those of the University of Minnesota Archives.
  • << Previous: Find journal articles
  • Next: Find newspaper articles >>

Ask Yale Library

My Library Accounts

Find, Request, and Use

Help and Research Support

Visit and Study

Explore Collections

Music: Dissertations

  • Search Library Catalogs
  • Reference Books and Online Resources
  • Dissertations
  • Overview and Printed Scores
  • Online Scores (Yale only)
  • Online Scores (Freely Available)
  • Scholarly and Critical Editions
  • Manuscripts and Rare Editions
  • Reproductions of Manuscripts and Rare Editions
  • CDs, LPs, etc.
  • Online Recordings (Yale only)
  • Free Online Recordings
  • VHS and DVD videos
  • Online Video (Yale)
  • Free Online Video
  • Reserve Titles
  • Special Collections
  • Related Guides

Dissertations and Theses

  • ProQuest Dissertations & Theses Global Includes millions of searchable citations to dissertations and theses from 1861 to the present day together with over a million full-text dissertations that are available for download in PDF format. The database offers full-text for most of the dissertations added since 1997 and strong retrospective full-text coverage for older graduate works. It includes the more than 28,000 Yale PhD and MD theses (1861-present). Of these, more than 18,500 are in full-text: almost all since 1960, and selected dissertations back to 1868. It also includes PQDT UK & Ireland content.
  • Articles+ Dissertations It can be easier to locate a known dissertation by author and title using Articles+ (which searches against ProQuest Dissertations & Theses) and limiting to dissertations. The link above has already been limited to dissertations.

Search for dissertations in Quicksearch:

The Music Library has purchased many copies of dissertations from other universities.  Most Yale dissertations that are not full-text in ProQuest (above) are available in paper or microfilm for reading, scanning, or printing.

Dissertations can be located in Quicksearch by: (1) Entering the author or title in the Basic Search box. Remember to enclose exact word-by-word phrases in quotation marks.

dissertation music definition

(2) Using the Quicksearch Books+ Advanced Search:

  • To browse all dissertations & theses, leave the search rows empty, enter All fields: music, or enter your search terms in the search boxes
  • Limit by Format: Dissertation & Theses
  • Limit by Location: Music Library (optional) 

dissertation music definition

(a) The example below shows a blank search limited to Dissertations & Theses format and Music Library location: 2,713 results.

 (b) Refine your search using the facets on the left of the results screen.

dissertation music definition

3) If you do not locate a Yale dissertation in Quicksearch, check the card catalog at Manuscripts and Archives. Except for some early dissertations that are not available, the originals of all Yale dissertations are held at Manuscripts and Archives.

Finding Dissertations Online - Additional Resources

  • Dart-Europe E-Theses Portal
  • Dissertation Express
  • Dissertationsmeldestelle der Gesellschaft fur Musikforschung
  • Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology
  • EDT Digital Library
  • Music Theory Online Dissertation Index
  • OhioLink ETD Center
  • Theses Canada Portal
  • WorldCat (OCLC)
  • Archive of Dissertation Abstracts in Music (Europe).
  • Finding Dissertations on Music (Indiana U guide)

How to get a copy

If you find a dissertation that you need, but there is not a full text link, there are several options: search for it at Yale, borrow a copy through Borrow Direct or Interlibrary Loan (ILL) , or request that the library purchase a copy.  You may also purchase a copy in various formats.

Citing Electronic Resources

There are three major citation styles used in the humanities, social sciences, and some scientific disciplines. Consult one of the following official style manuals :

  • APA Style The Publication Manual of the American Psychological Association is the style manual of choice for writers, editors, students, and educators in the social and behavioral sciences.
  • MLA Style Center Website with updates and tips for the Modern Language Association's 8th edition of the MLA Handbook (see entry below). Includes a Quick Guide to works cited, an FAQ, and posts on topics such as URLs and citing ebooks.
  • The Chicago Manual of Style online With state-of-the-art recommendations on editorial style and publishing practices in the digital age, The Chicago Manual of Style is the must-have reference for everyone who works with words.
  • The Columbia guide to online style Janice R. Walker and Todd Taylor. A guide to locating, translating, and using the elements of citation for both a humanities style (i.e., MLA and Chicago) and a scientific style (APA and CBE) for electronically-accessed sources. Access is available to the Yale Community. Often preferred in history and many other disciplines.
  • << Previous: Reference Books and Online Resources
  • Next: Images >>
  • Last Updated: Feb 22, 2024 1:01 PM
  • URL: https://guides.library.yale.edu/music-research

Yale Library logo

Site Navigation

P.O. BOX 208240 New Haven, CT 06250-8240 (203) 432-1775

Yale's Libraries

Bass Library

Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library

Classics Library

Cushing/Whitney Medical Library

Divinity Library

East Asia Library

Gilmore Music Library

Haas Family Arts Library

Lewis Walpole Library

Lillian Goldman Law Library

Marx Science and Social Science Library

Sterling Memorial Library

Yale Center for British Art

SUBSCRIBE TO OUR NEWSLETTER

@YALELIBRARY

image of the ceiling of sterling memorial library

Yale Library Instagram

Accessibility       Diversity, Equity, and Inclusion      Giving       Privacy and Data Use      Contact Our Web Team    

© 2022 Yale University Library • All Rights Reserved

University Libraries

Music research: dissertation and thesis guidance for topic selection and copyright permissions.

  • Introduction
  • Article Databases
  • Reference Sources
  • Streaming Audio and Video Databases
  • Dissertation and Thesis Guidance for Topic Selection and Copyright Permissions

Selecting a topic is the first consideration for a writer of a dissertation or thesis. This will of course be done in consultation with their major professor. The PhD, DMA, or master's student is required do original research. This might involve making new discoveries about an already well-researched topic or making discoveries about an unfamiliar topic.  Someone might think there is nothing new to be discovered about a composer such as Bach or Beethoven, for example, but that may not be the case. An unfamiliar topic might seem safer, but that may not be the case. In considering a topic, the student should begin by doing the most thorough search they can to see what has already been done. If they find little or nothing, the topic might be promising. However, for an unfamiliar topic, sometimes so little has been done that researching it is not even feasible. However, If research has been done, even if resources are only available in distant archives in other countries, the student could pursue the topic. It is unacceptable to ignore resources in distant or difficult to access places.  Once a topic is approved and the student starts writing, there are important matters to deal with early on. One of them is the quoting of copyrighted material. U.S. copyright law includes provisions for fair use of copyrighted material for such purposes as scholarship and research. Quotation of very brief excerpts might qualify as fair use. However, for extended examples, the student must obtain written permission from the copyright holder. Their are many websites dealing with fair use. This one from the U.S. Copyright Office is helpful:  https://www.copyright.gov/fair-use/ Determining the identity of a copyright holder is not always easy. For printed music which has been published, the copyright holder is the publisher. Many large publishing houses have links on their websites for requesting permissions. For a music manuscript, the copyright holder would be the composer, but only if that composer is still alive. If not, their estate or an institution such as a research library which has custody of the manuscript might be the copyright holder. Something similar might be the case for musical examples found on websites. The copyright holder for an image found on a website would be the provider of the website. It may be helpful for a student to know that sites such as Wikimedia Commons,  https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/Main_Pag e  offer many high-quality images which are in the public domain.  Whatever the case, the student should investigate and request appropriate permissions well in advance of the completion of their dissertation or thesis. Many students have waited till the last minute, only to discover that the permissions are very difficult or impossible to obtain. Without the permissions, the examples cannot be used.  Music library personnel are available to assist PhD, DMA, and master's students who need help with any of these aspects of working on their dissertations or theses. Please send your questions to  [email protected] or come by the library to meet with us in person.

  • << Previous: Websites
  • Last Updated: Apr 22, 2024 10:14 AM
  • URL: https://guides.library.unt.edu/music-research

Additional Links

UNT: Apply now UNT: Schedule a tour UNT: Get more info about the University of North Texas

UNT: Disclaimer | UNT: AA/EOE/ADA | UNT: Privacy | UNT: Electronic Accessibility | UNT: Required Links | UNT: UNT Home

  • Skip to main content
  • Accessibility information

dissertation music definition

  • Enlighten Enlighten

Enlighten Theses

  • Latest Additions
  • Browse by Year
  • Browse by Subject
  • Browse by College/School
  • Browse by Author
  • Browse by Funder
  • Login (Library staff only)

In this section

Creativity and Wellbeing in Music Education — philosophy, policy and practice in the context of contemporary Scottish primary education

Kim, Hanah (2020) Creativity and Wellbeing in Music Education — philosophy, policy and practice in the context of contemporary Scottish primary education. PhD thesis, University of Glasgow.

This is an interdisciplinary study encompassing elements of music, education, and aspects of philosophy and psychology. The principal aim of this research is to investigate ways of fostering musical creativity and wellbeing in primary schools, as well as providing curriculum guidelines and drawing out practical implications for Music Education in the present era.

Contemporary society represents a new wave of development in human affairs. Resting upon rapid technological innovation, it has created greater opportunities for revealing and experiencing creativity in forms that can then underpin enhanced states of human welfare. At the same time, these far-reaching changes have in many places become threats to human wellbeing, resulting from the dislocating social and emotional impact of new styles of living. As a consequence, ‘creativity’ and ‘wellbeing’ have arisen as important themes in the current era, chiefly as assets and attitudes required for human beings: to live, to respond, to cope, to prosper, and to succeed. In this turbulent context, education is tasked with nurturing both ‘creativity’ and ‘wellbeing’. These concepts are especially meaningful to be investigated through Music Education at the present time, since human beings have had an enduring relationship with sound and music in almost all cultures on record, even and especially those moving through great change.

From its basis in musical theory and Music Education, this research also develops a distinctive theoretical foundation in the concepts of ‘Romantic Aesthetics’ and ‘Romantic Irony’––which is a literary, aesthetic, and stylistic term that involves an advanced psychological concept of ‘self’ (e.g. Garber, 2014; Allen, 2007) very apposite to the current age. Specifically, for the present research, I wanted to apply these concepts and theories to the practices of contemporary Music Education, to help devise a useful curriculum for music classes in primary schools consistent with my wider interests in children’s creativity, and children’s wellbeing and resilience, when their lives are often under great pressure. The teaching methods and activities are researched, devised, implemented and evaluated encompassing what is recognised today as the four major components of Music Education: listening to music, singing, playing instruments, and composing.

The hypothesis within this research is that applying insights and approaches derived from ‘Romantic Irony’ to Music Education in modern primary schools can also be empowering in fostering pupils’ creativity and wellbeing. Across a broad cross-section of literature in different research areas––not only education but also philosophy and aesthetics, psychology, sociology––it is possible to set the premise that creativity and Romantic Irony are related in various vital aspects. Moreover, it is also possible, this thesis shows, to fashion and actualise a practice of Music Education in regular primary classrooms responsive not only to the rising emphasis on the concept of creativity but also to the pursuit of emotional resilience as a vital and life-supporting dimension of that creativity. Thus, this thesis will attempt to show that applying Romantic Aesthetics and Romantic Irony to Music Education for the development of pupil creativity and wellbeing may a constructive innovation within the compass of all teachers committed to the place of music in the primary curriculum.

With due reference to the educational environment and surroundings of Scotland, where this project was deliberately targeted and unfolded, the research herein consists of two types of interventions: a conceptual and an empirical strand. The first part of the research is allocated to investigating and critically assessing theories of creativity, emotion, Romantic Aesthetics, Romantic Irony, Health and Wellbeing, and music therapy––alongside the educational practices in that these concepts may be meaningfully applied or manifest. For the empirical part of the research, I adopted a ‘Vignette’ and ‘thematic approach’ partially indebted to both practioner enquiry and Action Research, to craft ways of enhancing creativity and wellbeing through Music Education in a number of classrooms where I had been previously welcome and active as a serving teacher. The classroom interventions were divided into 3 Vignettes to stimulate pupils’ innate musical creativity and to form relationships, to deliever basic theoretical knowledge, and then to provide opportunities to apply skills in relation to certain topics that appear in daily lives. Thereafter, important academic conversations with experts were conducted in order to examine deeper views of the researcher’s philosophy and approaches and to search for the directions that Music Education ought to follow in contemporary society.

The thesis concludes with the conviction that Music Education preserves a rich potential for realising and expressing the core values of progressive education today: promoting for the children in our schools the experiences of creativity, health, resilience and wellbeing which matter so much for surviving and attaining the good life in our protean 21st century society.

Actions (login required)

Downloads per month over past year

View more statistics

-

The University of Glasgow is a registered Scottish charity: Registration Number SC004401

University Libraries

  • UI School of Music
  • Location and Hours
  • My Personal Library

Music Dissertations, Theses, and Recording Projects: a guide: Dissertation and Theses Databases

  • Get Started
  • Formatting Your Thesis
  • Musical Examples
  • Bibliography This link opens in a new window
  • Open Access
  • Dissertation and Theses Databases

Iowa Research Online

dissertation music definition

Dissertations and Theses written here at Iowa, available open access and scoped to Music.

ProQuest Dissertations and Theses

Proquest dissertations.

proquest logo

Dissertations and theses from around the world, available via Library Subscription.

  • << Previous: Cover Art
  • Last Updated: Dec 14, 2023 10:42 AM
  • URL: https://guides.lib.uiowa.edu/musictd

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

The Philosophy of Music

Philosophy of music is the study of fundamental questions about the nature and value of music and our experience of it. Like any “philosophy of X,” it presupposes knowledge of its target. However, unlike philosophy of science, say, the target of philosophy of music is a practice most people have a significant background in, merely as a result of being members of a musical culture. Many people take music to play a significant and valuable role in their lives. Thus, as with the central questions of metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics, not only can most people quickly grasp the philosophical questions music raises, they tend to have thought about some of those questions before encountering the academic discipline itself.

Music arguably presents more philosophical puzzles than any other art. Unlike painting, its works often have multiple instances, none of which can be identified with the work itself. Thus, the question of what exactly the work is is initially more puzzling than the same question about works of painting, which appear (at least initially) to be ordinary physical objects. Unlike much literature, the instances of a work are performances, which offer interpretations of the work, yet the work can also be interpreted (perhaps in a different sense) independent of any performance, and performances themselves can be interpreted. This talk of “interpretation” points to the fact that we find music an art steeped with meaning, and yet, unlike drama, music—at least “pure” instrumental music—has no obvious semantic content. This quickly raises the question of why we should find music so valuable. Central to many philosophers’ thinking on these subjects has been music’s apparent ability to express emotions while remaining an abstract art in some sense.

This entry focuses almost exclusively on contemporary philosophy of music (i.e., work since the mid-twentieth century) in an analytic vein. For a historical overview, see the entries on the history of Western philosophy of music: antiquity to 1800 and history of Western philosophy of music: since 1800 . For much broader introductions to philosophy of music, covering its history, major figures, connections with other disciplines, and a wider range of topics, see Gracyk & Kania 2011 and McAuley, Nielsen, & Levinson 2021. Useful single-author overviews include Scruton 1997, Kivy 2002, Hamilton 2007, and Kania 2020.

Most analytic work has primarily discussed Western classical music. (For criticism of this tendency, see Alperson 2009.) In the last 25 years, there has been increasing recognition that different musical practices may not only suggest different answers to the same philosophical questions, but also raise different philosophical questions. Apart from Western classical music, popular Western traditions, such as rock and jazz, have received the most attention. Non-Western musical traditions have received little attention. (Exceptions include S. Davies 2001: 254–94 and 2007; Alperson, Nguyen, & To 2007; S. P. Walton 2007; and Higgins 2007.)

1.1 Music Alone and Together

1.2 the definition of “music”, 2.1 the fundamentalist debate, 2.2 higher-level ontological issues, 3.1 emotions in the music, 3.2 emotions in the listener, 4.1 basic musical understanding, 4.2 higher-level musical understanding, 5.1 music’s artistic value, 5.2 music’s moral value, other internet resources, related entries, 1. what is music.

It is plausible that song is the most common kind of music listened to across history and the globe. Moving images (film, television, videogames, etc.) are ubiquitous in the contemporary world, and most have musical soundtracks. Nonetheless, most philosophy of music considers what Peter Kivy calls music alone (1990)—instrumental music with no non-musical aspects, elements, or accompaniments. At least three reasons can be given to defend this narrow focus. First, pure music often presents the most difficult philosophical problems. The maudlin text of a song plausibly contributes to the song’s expressiveness; it is more puzzling how a piece of music alone could be emotionally expressive. Second, though the problems are more difficult, the solutions are likely to be more easily evaluated with respect to music alone. Just as apportioning blame is easier when one person is responsible for a crime than when the blame must be divided between a number of conspirators, the success of a solution to the problem of musical expressiveness may be clearer if it can explain the expressiveness of music alone. Third, the expressiveness of music alone will play a role in the expressiveness of musical hybrids such as song or film. Though its text may contribute to the expressiveness of a song, for instance, the musical aspects of the song must play some role. A maudlin text set to a jauntily upbeat melody will clearly not have the same overall expressiveness as the same text set to a plodding dirge. Though expressiveness is used as an example here, these same points apply to discussions of musical understanding and value.

Even if these three reasons are compelling (see Ridley 2004 for a sustained critique), music’s combination with other media raises further philosophical questions. There is no space to consider those questions here, but on the aesthetics of song, see Levinson 1987; Gracyk 2001; Bicknell & Fisher 2013; and Bicknell 2015. On music drama, see Kivy 1988b, 1994; Goehr 1998; and Penner 2020. On film music, see Carroll 1988: 213–225; Smith 1996; Levinson 1996b; and Kivy 1997a. See also the chapters in part V of Gracyk & Kania 2011. On hybrid art forms more generally, see Levinson 1984 and Ridley 2004.

Explications of the concept of music usually begin with the idea that music is organized sound. They go on to note that this characterization is too broad, since there are many examples of organized sound that are not music, such as human speech, or the sounds non-human animals and machines make. There are two further kinds of necessary conditions philosophers have added in attempts to fine tune the initial idea. One is an appeal to “tonality” or essentially musical features such as pitch and rhythm (Scruton 1997: 1–79; Hamilton 2007: 40–65; Kania 2011a). Another is an appeal to aesthetic properties or experience (Levinson 1990a; Scruton 1997: 1–96; Hamilton 2007: 40–65). As these references suggest, one can endorse either of these conditions in isolation, or both together.

The main problem with the first kind of condition is that every sound seems capable of being included in a musical performance, and thus characterizing the essentially musical features of sounds seems hopeless. (We need only consider the variety of “untuned” percussion available to a conservative symphonist, though we could also consider examples of wind machines, typewriters, and toilets, in Ralph Vaughan Williams’s Sinfonia Antartica , Leroy Anderson’s The Typewriter , and Yoko Ono’s “Toilet Piece/Unknown.”) Defenders of such a condition have turned to sophisticated intentional or response-dependent theories of tonality in order to overcome this problem. If the essentially musical features of a sound are not intrinsic to it, but somehow related to how it is produced or perceived, we can classify just one of two “indiscernible” sounds as music.

If one endorses only an aesthetic condition, and not a tonality condition, one still faces the problem of poetry—non-musical aesthetically organized sounds. Levinson, who takes this approach, excludes organized linguistic sounds explicitly (1990a: 272). This raises the question of whether there are further distinctions to be made between arts of sound. Andy Hamilton defends a tripartite division, arguing that sound art , as opposed to both music and literature, was established as a significant art form in the twentieth century (2007: 40–65). This is one reason that Hamilton endorses both tonal and aesthetic conditions on music; without the former, Levinson is unable to make such a distinction. On the other hand, by endorsing an aesthetic condition, Hamilton is forced to exclude scales and Muzak, for instance, from the realm of music. Kania (2020: 296–301) suggests that it is a mistake to think that music is necessarily an art. He argues that we should distinguish the medium of music from its artistic uses, just as we do in the cases of language and literature, depiction and painting, and so on.

Jonathan McKeown-Green (2014) makes trenchant criticisms of definitions of music that assume that the nature of music is settled by our conception of music (395, italics removed). He argues that no such definition could be future-proof, since it would be hostage to our changing conception of music. At best, we would end up with a kind of sociological history of music that would fail to fulfill any of the functions of a definition. McKeown-Green singles out the definitions of Kania (2011a) and Levinson (1990a), stated in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, as of this hopeless kind. But Kania (2020: 302–5) argues that McKeown-Green’s criticisms apply equally to the looser definitions of Hamilton and S. Davies (2012).

Having discussed complications, it’s worth returning to the basic idea of “organized sound.” Most theorists note that music does not consist entirely of sounds. Most obviously, much music includes rests. You might think that silence can function only to organize the sounds of music. One counterargument is that an understanding listener listens to the rests, just as she listens to the sounds (Kania 2010). Another is to provide putative cases of music in which the silences do not structure sounds as ordinary rests do. John Cage’s 4′33″ is frequently discussed, though there is broad agreement that this piece is not silent—its content is the ambient sounds that occur during its performance. (See Dodd 2018 for dissent.) Anyway, S. Davies (1997a), Dodd (2018), and Kania (2010) all argue that Cage’s piece is not music—Davies and Dodd because its sounds (if any) fail to qualify as organized, Kania because they fail to meet a tonality condition. Wadle (forthcoming) argues that the piece is music, because of its contextual connections to previous musical works. Kania considers several other contenders for the label of “silent music,” arguing that there are indeed extant examples, most notably Erwin Schulhoff’s “In Futurum” from his Fünf Pittoresken , which predates Cage’s 4′33″ by some 33 years.

2. Musical Ontology

Musical ontology is the study of the kinds of musical things there are and the relations that hold between them. The most discussed issues within this field have been the metaphysical nature of works of Western classical music (the “fundamentalist debate”), and what it is to give an “authentic performance” of such works. Recently there has been growing interest in the ontologies of other Western musical traditions, such as rock and jazz, and discussion of the methodology and value of musical ontology. (For more detailed overviews of these debates, see Matheson & Caplan 2011, and Nussbaum 2021.)

Musical works in the Western classical tradition admit of multiple instances (performances). Much of the debate over the nature of such works thus reads like a recapitulation of the debate over the “problem of universals”; the range of proposed candidates covers the spectrum of fundamental ontological theories. We might divide musical ontologists into the realists, who posit the existence of musical works, and the anti-realists, who deny their existence. Realism has been more popular than anti-realism, but there have been many conflicting realist views. We begin with two unorthodox realist views before moving on to more orthodox Platonist and nominalist theories, concluding with a consideration of anti-realism.

Idealists hold that musical works are mental entities. Collingwood (1938) and Sartre (1940) respectively take musical (and other) works to be imaginary objects and experiences. The most serious objections to this kind of view are that (i) it fails to make works intersubjectively accessible, since the number of works going under the name The Rite of Spring will be as multifarious as the imaginative experiences people have at performances with that name, and (ii) it makes the medium of the work irrelevant to an understanding of it. One might have the same imaginative experience in response to both a live performance and a recording of The Rite of Spring , yet it seems an open question whether the two media are aesthetically equivalent. But see Cox 1986 and Cray & Matheson 2017 for attempts to revive idealism.

David Davies argues that musical works, like all works of art, are actions , in particular the compositional actions of their composers (2004). Thus he revives what we might call an “action theory” of the ontology of art. (An earlier defender of such a view is Gregory Currie (1989), who argues that artworks are types of action, rather than the particular actions with which Davies identifies them.) Although deciding between theories of musical ontology is always to some extent a matter of finding a balance between the benefits of a theory and its cost in terms of our pre-theoretic intuitions, action theories have a particularly hard row to hoe since they imply that an instance of a work is some action performed by a composer, rather than a performance. In order to make up for such damage to our intuitions the theoretical benefits of an action theory would have to be quite extensive.

Most theorists think that some kind of Platonist or nominalist theory of musical works is more plausible than those so far considered. Platonism, the view that musical works are abstract objects, is arguably still the dominant view, though it seems to be losing ground to sophisticated nominalisms. Its great advantage is its ability to respect more of our pre-theoretic intuitions about musical works than other theories can. On the other hand, it is the most ontologically puzzling, since abstract objects are not well understood. Nonetheless, Platonism has been tenacious, with much of the debate centering around what variety of abstract object musical works are. What we might call “simple Platonism” (known simply as “Platonism” in the literature), is the view that works are eternal existents, existing in neither space nor time (Kivy 1983a, 1983b, Dodd 2007). Puy (2019) presents a variation according to which musical works are higher-order types, of which the types other Platonist thinks are works are specific versions of works. (See D. Davies 2021 for discussion.)

According to “complex Platonism,” musical works come to exist in time as the result of human action. The complexity is motivated by a number of features of musical practice, including the intuition that musical works are creatable, the attribution of various aesthetic and artistic properties to works, and the fine-grained individuation of works and performances (e.g., in terms of who composed them, or what instruments they are properly performed upon) (Ingarden 1961; Thomasson 2004; Wolterstorff 1980; Wollheim 1968: 1–10, 74–84; Levinson 1980, 1990b, 2012; S. Davies 2001: 37–43; Howell 2002; Stecker 2003a: 84–92).

Nominalists identify a musical work with something concrete. The most obvious candidate is a collection of performances, whether the collection be understood as a set (Goodman 1968; Predelli 1995, 1999a, 1999b, 2001), a fusion (Caplan & Matheson 2004, 2006), or something more esoteric (Tillman 2011; see also Moruzzi 2018). Charles Nussbaum (2007: 143–87) and P. D. Magnus (2012) argue for a close analogy between musical works and species. Nussbaum (2021: 334) points out that a sophisticated nominalist theory of species has been developed in great detail over the years by Ruth Millikan (1984, 2000). While such views are attractive because they appeal only to the least problematic kinds of entities, they face serious challenges. Though many of our claims about musical works may be paraphraseable into claims about sets of (possible) performances, some seem to make intractable reference to works. For instance, most performances of The Rite of Spring—even including the possible ones—include several wrong notes. Thus it is difficult to imagine how the paraphrase schema will avoid the nonsensical conclusion that The Rite of Spring contains several wrong notes, if the work consists entirely of performances. In response to this problem, most nominalists add to the collection of performances some provenential item, such as an original score or act of composition. Whether this addition can solve the problem without necessitating the reintroduction of an abstract entity is one question any nominalist must address.

Intermediate between Platonism and nominalism are the views of Philip Letts (2018) and Guy Rohrbaugh (2003). Letts argues that any view of musical works as types would be improved by identifying those types with their associated properties, a proposal that may be developed in a Platonist or nominalist direction. Rohrbaugh’s view of musical works as historical individuals “embodied in,” but not constituted by, physical things such as scores and performances closely resembles to the views of Nussbaum and Magnus, discussed above, but Rohrbaugh takes the work to be an abstract object over and above its embodiments. (For discussion, see Dodd 2007: 143–66.)

In contrast to all these realist views stand those of the anti-realists, who deny that there are any such things as musical works. An early proponent of such a view is Richard Rudner (1950), though it is difficult to say whether he is best interpreted as an eliminativist or a fictionalist, the two anti-realist views currently on the table. According to eliminativists, there are no such things as musical works, and thus we ought to stop trying to refer to them. Ross Cameron (2008) defends such a view, but only with respect to “Ontologese”—the language we speak when we do ontology. He argues that ordinary English locutions such as “there are many musical works” can be true without there being any musical works. (For critical discussion, see Predelli 2009 and Stecker 2009.) According to fictionalists, the value of discourse about musical works is not truth, and thus we ought not to abandon the discourse despite the non-existence of its subject matter, but rather to adopt a different, make-believe attitude towards it (or perhaps we already do so). (See Kania 2008; for criticism, see D. Davies 2011: 45–50, Letts 2015, and Nussbaum 2021: 337.)

Much of this debate over the fundamental ontological category to which musical works belong has turned on “technical” issues, that is, controversial general metaphysical claims about the nature of properties, causation, embodiment, and so on (e.g., Howell 2002; Trivedi 2002; Caplan & Matheson 2004, 2006; Dodd 2007; Hazlett 2012; Kleinschmidt & Ross 2012; Dodd & Letts 2017; Cameron 2008). In the face of this, some theorists have pointed out that musical works are cultural entities, and thus the methodology appropriate to uncovering their ontological status might be quite different from that of general metaphysics (Goehr 1992; S. Davies 2003a; D. Davies 2004; Thomasson 2006). For further discussion of the methodology of musical ontology, see D. Davies 2009, 2017; Predelli 2009; Stecker 2009; Dodd 2010, 2013; Mag Uidhir 2012b; and Nussbaum 2021.

It might seem that, since musical works are ontologically multiple, once we have figured out their true nature, we will know what relation holds between the work and its performances, namely, whatever relationship holds between entities of that kind and their instances. However, since the fundamentalist debate is about the basic ontological category to which works belong, resolving that debate may leave open many questions about the relation between a work and its performances. For instance, is the use of a harpsichord required to instance Bach’s Brandenburg Concerto No. 5 in performance? Would producing harpsichord-like sounds on a synthesizer do just as well? What about using another keyboard instrument from Bach’s time, or a modern piano? Learning that musical works are, say, eternal types will not necessarily help settle this issue of “authentic performance,” which is perhaps the most discussed music-ontological issue, of interest to philosophers, musicologists, musicians, and audiences alike. (For an excellent overview of the authentic performance debate, see S. Davies 2001: 201–53. For an investigation of authenticity with respect to things other than instantiation of the work, see Kivy 1995; Gracyk 2001, 2009, 2017; Bicknell 2015; and Cray 2019.)

There have been two sources of widespread confusion in the debate over authenticity in performance. One is a failure to recognize that authenticity is not simply a property, but a relation that comes in degrees and holds with respect to different aspects of its target. Something may be more authentic in one regard and less authentic in another (S. Davies 2001: 203–5). Another is the assumption that authenticity is an evaluative concept, in the sense that “authentic” implies “good.” That this is not the case is clear from the fact that an authentic murderer is not a good thing (S. Davies 2001: 204). Thus, our value judgments will be complex functions of the extent to which we judge performances authentic in various regards, and the values we assign to those various kinds of authenticity.

The central kind of authenticity that has been discussed is authenticity with respect to the instantiation of the work. Most agree that the fullest such authenticity requires the production of the right pitches and rhythms in the right order. (For skepticism based on the history of the practice, see Dyck 2014; Ravasio 2019a; and the discussion in Dodd 2020b and Ravasio 2020.) Pure sonicists argue that this is sufficient (e.g., Kivy 1988a). Timbral sonicists argue that these pitches must also have timbres reflecting the composer’s instrumentation (e.g., Dodd 2007: 201–39). Instrumentalists argue that such sounds must be produced on the kinds of instruments specified in the score (e.g., Levinson 1990c). Much of the debate is over what kinds of aesthetic or artistic properties are essential to musical works. If the limpid textures of Bach’s Brandenburg Concerto No. 5 are essential to it, then one cannot authentically instance the work using a grand piano instead of a harpsichord. As such, the debate reflects a wider one in aesthetics, musical and otherwise, between formalists (or empiricists, or structuralists), who believe that the most important properties of a work are intrinsic ones, accessible to listeners unaware of the historical and artistic context in which it was created, and contextualists , who believe that a work is essentially tied to its context of creation. Stephen Davies has argued for a strong contextualism, claiming that one cannot give a single answer to the question of whether particular instrumentation is required for the fully authentic instantiation of a work. Works can be ontologically “thicker” or “thinner” as a result of the specifications of a composer working within certain conventions (1991, 2001). The more properties of a fully authentic performance a particular work specifies, the thicker it is. Thus for some works (typically earlier in the history of Western music) instrumentation is flexible, while for others (e.g., Romantic symphonies) quite specific instrumentation is required for fully authentic performances.

In addition to the question of what constitutes authenticity, there has been debate over its attainability and value. Those who question its attainability point to our historical distance from the creation of some works (Young 1988). We may no longer be able to read the notation in which the work is recorded, or construct or play the instruments for which it was written. If so, full authenticity is not attainable. But we rarely have no idea about these matters, and thus we might achieve partial authenticity (S. Davies 2001: 228–34). Those who question the value of authenticity often target kinds other than work-instantiation. For instance, one might question the value of producing a performance that authentically captures the sound of performances as they took place in the context of a work’s composition, on the basis that musicians were not as highly skilled then as now, for instance (Young 1988: 229–31). Such arguments, though, have no consequences for the value of work-instantiation. Some argue that although we might attain an authentic instance of a work, the idea that we might thereby hear the work as its contemporaries heard it is wishful thinking, since the musical culture in which we are immersed enforces ways of listening upon us that we cannot escape (Young 1988: 232–7). Thus the point of such authenticity is questioned. In response, we may consider not only the possibility that we are in a better position to appreciate historical works than contemporary ones, but also the remarkable flexibility people seem to show in enjoying many different kinds of music from throughout history and the world (S. Davies 2001: 234–7).

Julian Dodd (2020a) argues that there is more than one way to be true to a musical work, and thus to produce an authentic performance: One can comply with the score, or one can be true to the music’s overall integrity or point (136). When the two conflict, interpretive authenticity trumps score-compliance authenticity (147) because the fundamental norm of work-performance practice is to perform it in a way that evinces a subtle or profound understanding of it (163), while score compliance is valued only because it tends to lead to such performances. Andrew Kania responds that it is unclear whether, even by the lights of Dodd’s own theory, Dodd’s central examples are cases of interpretive authenticity trumping score compliance (Kania 2022: 131–2). More importantly, he argues that Dodd’s conception of the music’s overall integrity or point misses the importance of the surface-level details to a work’s meaning or content. Kania suggests, instead, that the fundamental norm of the practice is to evince an understanding of the work through complying with its score (2022: 127, italics altered).

Moving on from authenticity, a second area that may be independent of the fundamentalist debate is that of comparative ontology. (For dispute over this framing issue, see Brown 2011, 2012.) Just as classical works from different historical periods may be ontologically diverse, so may works from different contemporary traditions. Theodore Gracyk has argued that instances of works of rock music are not performances. Rather, the work is instanced by playing a copy of a recording on an appropriate device (1996; cf. Fisher 1998). Stephen Davies has argued that rock is more like classical music than Gracyk acknowledges, with works for performance at the heart of the tradition, albeit works for a different kind of performance (2001: 30–6). Gracyk’s view has been amplified and defended in attempts to find a place for composition, live performance, and performance skill within his basic framework (Kania 2006, Bruno 2013, Bartel 2017, Magnus 2022).

Work on the ontology of jazz has centered on the nature of improvisation, particularly the relation between improvisation and composition (Alperson 1984, 1998; Valone 1985; Brown 1996, 2000; Hagberg 1998; Gould & Keaton 2000; Sterritt 2000; and Young & Matheson 2000; Bresnahan 2015; Love 2016; Magnus 2016). This has been a useful reminder that not all music is the performance of pre-composed works (Wolterstorff 1987: 115–29). However, improvisation can occur within the context of such a work, as in the performance of an improvised cadenza in a classical concerto. Some have argued that there is not as significant a distinction between improvisation and composition as is usually thought (Alperson 1984). Others have argued that all performance requires improvisation (Gould & Keaton 2000). Yet others restrict the possibility of improvisation to certain kinds of musical properties, such as “structural” rather than “expressive” ones (Young & Matheson 2000). However, none of these arguments are compelling. Usually they turn on equivocal use of terms such as “composition” and “performance,” or beg the question by defining improvisation in terms of deviation from a score or variation of a limited set of “expressive” properties.

Though jazz is not necessarily improvisational, and very few jazz performances lack any sort of prior compositional process, the centrality of improvisation to jazz presents a challenge to the musical ontologist. One might argue that jazz works are ontologically like classical works—composed for multiple, different performances—but that they tend to be thinner, leaving more room for improvisation (Gould & Keaton 2000; Young & Matheson 2000). The difficulty is to specify the work without conflating one work with another, since tokening the melody may not be required, and many works share the same harmonic structure. As a result, some argue that the performance is itself the work (Alperson 1984; Hagberg 2002; S. Davies 2001: 16–19). One problem here is parity with classical music. If jazz performances are musical works in their own right, it is difficult to deny that status to classical performances of works, yet this seems to multiply works beyond what we usually think is necessary. A third possibility is that in jazz there are no works, only performances (Brown 1996, 2000: 115; Kania 2011b). This is counterintuitive if “work” is an evaluative term, but it is not obvious that this is the case.

Julian Dodd (2014a) argues that the kinds of considerations adduced in favor of these views confuse questions of ontology with questions of value. Jazz is ontologically like early classical music, according to Dodd: the focus of critical attention is the improvisatory performance rather than the composition it instantiates, but that composition is no less a musical work for that difference in critical emphasis. (See Fisher 2018 for an attempted reconciliation.) Similar considerations might be adduced against the increasingly complicated ontologies of rock referred to above. Such arguments return us to debates about the methodology of musical ontology.

3. Music and the Emotions

The most widely discussed philosophical question concerning music and the emotions is that of how music can express emotions. (For a more extensive introduction, see part II of Gracyk & Kania 2011; for a thorough treatment, see S. Davies 1994.) There is a second group of questions centered around listeners’ emotional responses to music. These include questions about why and how we respond emotionally to music, the value of such responses, and why we choose to listen to music that elicits “negative” responses from us, such as sadness. Theorists typically restrict themselves to “pure” or “absolute” music on the grounds that it is easier to understand how music with an accompanying text, say, could express the emotions evident in the text. However, an important criterion for the evaluation of such music is how appropriately the composer has set her chosen text to music. So an accompanying text is clearly not sufficient for the musical expression of an emotion. Thus, a better reason for initially putting such music to one side is perhaps that the interrelation of music and text, or other elements, is likely to be highly complex, and best approached with as well-developed a theory of the more basic phenomena in hand as possible. (For an extended criticism of this approach, see Ridley 2004: 1–104.)

Pieces of music, and performances of them, are standardly said to be happy, sad, and so on. Music’s emotional expressiveness is a philosophical problem since the paradigm expressers of emotions are psychological agents, who have emotions to express. Neither pieces of music, nor performances of them, are psychological agents, thus it is puzzling that such things could be said to express emotions.

One radical way to solve the puzzle is to deny that music is emotionally expressive. A major burden of such eliminativism is to explain away the widespread tendency to describe music in emotional terms. This has been attempted by arguing that such descriptions are shorthand or metaphor for purely sonic features (Urmson 1973), basic dynamic features (Hanslick 1854), purely musical features (Sharpe 1982), or aesthetic properties (Zangwill 2007). There are many problems with such views. For one thing, they seem committed to some sort of scheme for reduction of expressive predicates to other terms, such as sonic or musical ones, and such a scheme is difficult to imagine (Budd 1985a: 31–6). For another, anyone not drawn to this theory is likely to reject the claim that the paraphrase captures all that is of interest and value about the passage described, precisely because it omits the expressive predicates (Davies 1994: 153–4).

Conventionalism is the view that music’s expressiveness is a matter of the conventional association of certain musical elements, such as slow tempi, with certain emotional states, such as sadness. Such conventions must play a role in some cases of expression—for instance, cases of particular musical instruments (e.g., the snare drum) being associated with particular situations (e.g., war) and thus emotions (e.g., foreboding). But such conventions seem unlikely to account for all musical expressiveness, since much of that expressiveness seems less arbitrary than conventionalism would suggest. It seems implausible, for instance, that the convention for funeral dirges might just as easily have that they should be quick-paced and in major keys. Even in cases like the snare drum, it seems possible that the instrument was chosen for the battlefield in part because of the expressive character of its sonic profile.

The cliché that music is “the language of the emotions” is often considered as a possible starting point for a theory of musical expressiveness. The idea combines the attractive simplicity of conventionalism with the formalist notion that music’s order is to be understood in terms of syntax. (See Lerdahl & Jackendoff 1983 for a theory along the latter lines.) However, although Deryck Cooke (1959) and Leonard Meyer (1956) are often cited as proponents, it is not clear that anyone holds a full-blown version of the theory. The central problem is the great disparities between language and music, in terms of the ways in which each is both syntactic and semantic (Jackendoff 2011). A serious subsidiary problem is that even if music were about the emotions in the way that language can be, that would not account for music’s expressiveness . The sentence “I am sad” is about the emotions, but it is not expressive of sadness in the way a sad face is, though you could use either to express your sadness. Most people agree that music’s relation to emotion is more like that of a sad face than that of a sentence. (This last criticism is also applicable to Susanne Langer’s theory (1953) that music is about the emotions in a symbolic yet non-linguistic way.)

We now turn to theories that attempt to connect the notion of music’s expressiveness to actual felt emotions. One obvious way to do so is to argue that pieces of music or performances of them are expressions of such emotions—those of the composer or performer. There are two major problems with this “expression theory.” The first is that neither composers nor performers often experience the emotions their music is expressive of as it is produced. Nor does it seem unlikely that a composer could create, or a performer perform, a piece expressive of an emotion that she had never experienced. This is not to deny that a composer could write a piece expressive of her emotional state, but for the expression theory to be an account of musical expressiveness, at least all central cases of expressiveness must follow this model, which is not the case. Moreover, if a composer is to express her sadness, say, by writing a sad piece, she must pen the right kind of piece. In other words, if she is a bad composer she might fail to express her emotion. This brings us to the second major problem for the expression theory. If a composer can fail to express her emotions in a piece, then the music she writes is expressive independent of the emotion she is experiencing. Thus music’s expressiveness cannot be explained in terms of direct expression.

Those usually cited as classic expression theorists include Tolstoy (1898), Dewey (1934), and Collingwood (1938). (A classic critique is Tormey 1971: 97–127.) These theorists have been defended in recent discussions, however, from accusations that they hold the simple view outlined above (Ridley 2003, Robinson 2005: 229–57). Jenefer Robinson has attempted to revive the expression theory, though she defends it as an interesting and valuable use of music’s expressiveness, rather than an account of expressiveness itself (2005: 229–347; 2011).

A second way to link music’s expressiveness with actual felt emotions is through the audience. According to arousalism, the expressiveness of a passage of music amounts to its tendency to arouse that emotion in a competent listener. Arousalism faces several objections. First, some competent listeners seem emotionally unmoved by music (or are at least not moved to the specific emotions expressed by it). But perhaps the arousalist can simply restrict the class of listener to which his theory appeals to those who are so moved. Second, some emotions, such as fear, require a particular kind of intentional object (something threatening), yet there is no such object at hand when we hear fearful music. Thus it seems implausible to claim the music’s fearfulness resides in its arousal of fear in us. But perhaps the arousalist can broaden the class of aroused emotions to include appropriate responses to the expressed emotion, such as pity. Third, in many cases it seems that listeners respond emotionally to the expressiveness of the music. It is not clear that the arousalist can handle such cases non-circularly. (A sophisticated defense of the arousal theory is to be found in Matravers 1998: 145–224, though see the second thoughts in Matravers 2011. For an extended critique, see S. Davies 1994: 104–200.)

Despite the problems of the arousal theory as the whole story of musical expressiveness, there is a growing consensus, thanks largely to the work of Jenefer Robinson (1994, 2005), that our lower-level, less cognitive responses to music must play some role in the emotional expressiveness we attribute to it. However, this role is likely to be a causal one, rather than part of an analysis of what it is for music to be emotionally expressive.

Several theorists have defended accounts of musical expressiveness known variously as resemblance, contour, or appearance theories (e.g., Kivy 1989, though see Kivy 2002: 31–48 for recent qualms; Budd 1995: 133–54; S. Davies 1994: 221–67). The central idea is that music’s expressiveness consists in the resemblance between its dynamic character and that of various typical aspects of people experiencing emotions. The aspects appealed to include the phenomenology of the experience of the emotion, the emotion’s facial expression, the contour of vocal expression or bodily behavior of a person experiencing the emotion. Stephen Davies argues that such theories hold music to be expressive in a literal albeit secondary sense of the term. We say that a piece of music is sad in the same sense in which we say that a weeping willow is sad (S. Davies 2006: 183). Such uses are no more metaphorical than a claim that a chair has arms.

Jerrold Levinson agrees that there is an important resemblance between the contour of music expressive of an emotion and the contour of typical behavioral expressions of that emotion. He objects, however, that such an account cannot be the whole, or even the most fundamental part of the story (Levinson 1996a, 2006b). He drives in a wedge precisely at the point where an appeal is made to the resemblance between the music and typical behavioral expressions. He asks what the manner and extent of the resemblance between the two must be, precisely, in order for the music to count as expressive of some emotion. After all, everything resembles everything else in all sorts of ways, and so one could point out many resemblances between a funeral march and an expression of joy, or for that matter a cup of coffee and sadness. The resemblance theorist must give some account of why the funeral march, and not the cup of coffee, is expressive of sadness and not joy. Levinson claims that the obvious answer here is that the funeral march is “readily hearable as” an expression of sadness. If this is correct, then the resemblance the music bears to emotional behavior is logically secondary—a cause or ground of its expressiveness. The expressiveness itself resides in the music’s disposition to elicit the imaginative response in us of hearing the music as a literal expression of emotion. As a logical consequence, the imaginative experience prompted must include some agent whose expression the music literally is.

In reply to this kind of objection, Stephen Davies has emphasized the role of the listener’s response in resemblance theories. Such responses have always been appealed to by such theories, as evidenced by Malcolm Budd’s talk of “hearing as” (1995: 135–7), and Peter Kivy’s discussion of our tendency to “animate” that which we perceive (1980: 57–9). But Davies now makes the appeal quite explicit and central, devoting as much space to explication of the response-dependent nature of expressiveness as to the role of resemblance (2006). For Davies, the response of the competent listener upon which the expressiveness of the music depends is one of an experience of resemblance rather than imagined expression (2006: 181–2). Matteo Ravasio (2019b) argues that this leads to further problems.

Since Davies’s theory posits at base a contour-recognition experience while Levinson’s posits an imaginative experience of expression, the link between literal expression and musical expressiveness looks closer in Levinson’s theory than in Davies’s. An empirical consequence seems to be that Davies’s theory will predict weaker emotional responses to music than Levinson’s. Whether or not this is an advantage or disadvantage of the theory depends on the empirical facts about how we respond emotionally to music.

There are three main questions asked about our emotional responses to pure music, apart from what role they play in expressiveness. The first is analogous to the “paradox of fiction.” It is not clear why we should respond emotionally to music’s expressiveness when we know that no one is undergoing the emotions expressed. The second is a variant of the “paradox of tragedy.” If some music arouses “negative” emotional responses in us, such as sadness, why do we seek out the experience of such music? This leads to the more general question of the value of our emotional responses to music. The first two questions are addressed in this section, and the third in section 5.1.

Peter Kivy (1999) argues that those who report emotional reactions to music are confusing the pleasure they take in the beauty of the music, in all its expressive individuality, with the feeling of the emotion expressed. Though most philosophers appeal to ordinary experience and empirical data to reject the plausibility of Kivy’s position, they admit the problem that motivates it, namely, the conceptual tension between the nature of music and the nature of the emotions we feel in response to it. There is some consensus that emotions are cognitive, in the sense that they take intentional objects—they are about things—of certain kinds. For instance, in order to feel fear , one must believe that something is threatening (the “intentional object” of the emotion). When one listens to a sad piece of music, however, one knows there is nothing literally feeling sad, and thus it is puzzling that one should be made sad by the experience.

Part of the solution is that not all emotional responses (broadly construed) are cognitive (Robinson 1994; 2005: 387–400). For instance, it is no more puzzling that one could be startled by a fortissimo blow to a bass drum than that one could so respond to a thunderclap. Another part of the solution is that the music can be the object of our emotions, as when we are delighted by an effective ending to a long and complex piece.

As for emotional responses to music’s expressiveness, there are at least two possible explanations. One appeals to the phenomenon of “emotional contagion” or “mirroring responses” (S. Davies 1994: 279–307; 2006: 186–8). When surrounded by moping people, one tends to become sad. Moreover, such a “mood” is not about some intentional object. One is not necessarily sad for the mopers, nor whatever they are sad about, if anything. Similarly, when “surrounded” by music that presents an appearance of sadness, one might become sad, but not sad about the music, or anything else (Radford 1991). For critical discussion, see Robinson 2005: 379–412 and S. Davies 2011b.

If our experience of music’s expressiveness necessarily involves imagining that the music is a literal expression of emotion, then our emotional responses to that expressiveness are no more puzzling than emotional responses to other imagined expressive agents, such as fictional characters in novels. The advantage is only slight because the question of how and why we respond emotionally to fictions is itself a philosophical problem of some magnitude. Nonetheless, there are several theories available (see the supplement to the entry on imagination, §2 ). One difficulty with appealing to a solution to the paradox of fiction is that it is not clear that our emotional responses to the expressiveness of music are the same as those to emotionally expressive characters. For instance, the standard example of an emotional response to music is being made sad by a dirge, while the standard example of emotional response to fiction is (something like) to feel pity for a sad character. If the former is to be explained in the same way as the latter, we would expect listeners to feel pity in response to the funeral march (pity for the persona imagined to be expressing her sadness through it). However, we surely do feel sad (in some sense) in response to tragedy, and it is not obvious that we do not feel pity (or imagined pity, or whatever one’s preferred theory of emotional response to fiction posits) in response to sad music.

Leaving behind the topic of how and why we respond emotionally to music, we turn to the question of why we seek out music that arouses “negative” emotions in us, such as sadness, assuming henceforth that we are in fact aroused to such emotions. (Since this problem is a close analog of the “paradox of tragedy,” some of the references below are to literature not explicitly about music, but the transposition of the arguments to music is not difficult to imagine. (See also the supplement to the entry on imagination, §3 .) Most solutions assume that our negative emotional response is a price we are willing to pay for the benefits of engaging with the piece in question. The benefits appealed to include understanding and appreciating the music, including the expressiveness responsible for the negative response (Goodman 1968: 247–51; S. Davies 1994: 311–20; Goldman 1995: 68; Robinson 2005: 348–78).

A different benefit is Aristotelian catharsis , in which our negative emotional response to expressive art results in a psychological purgation of the negative emotions (Aristotle 1987: 6, 1449b21–1450b20). A less therapeutic approach is the suggestion that, since these emotions are without “life implications” (that is, as discussed above, we are not sad about any actual tragic events), we are able to take advantage of our responses to savor these emotions, gain an understanding of them, and be reassured that we have the capacity to feel them (Levinson 1982). Two things that must be explained by any defender of this kind of response are, first, our persistence in seeking out music that elicits negative emotional experiences after we have received the resulting benefit and, second, the enjoyment we seem to take in these negative responses, as opposed to putting up with them for their related benefits.

A different kind of solution to the problem argues that responses such as sadness that are evoked by expressive music are not really negative. Hume (1757) argues, with respect to tragedy, that the pleasure we take in the mode of presentation of the content of an artwork does not simply counterbalance the negative emotion evoked, but rather subsumes and transforms it into a pleasurable feeling. Kendall Walton argues (also with respect to tragedy) that sadness is not in itself negative. Rather, it is the situation to which sadness is the response that is negative. Thus, though we would not seek out the death of a loved one, given the death we “welcome” the sorrow (K. Walton 1990: 255–9). Similarly, we cannot affect the sadness of a musical work by not listening to it, and so we welcome our sorrowful response to it as appropriate. Berys Gaut (2007: 203–26) argues that though sadness is typically aroused by situations we would prefer to avoid, sadness in response to artistic expressiveness is an exception and thus not negative in any paradoxical way. A difficulty for all three solutions is the extent to which they accord with our emotional experience in rejecting the characterization of our sadness as negative.

4. Understanding Music

A central topic in the understanding of narrative art forms, such as literature and film, is what constitutes an acceptable interpretation of a work. One debate concerns whether there is a single correct interpretation of any work or multiple acceptable interpretations. Another concerns the constraints on acceptable interpretations, e.g., the extent to which the artist’s intentions may or should be taken into account.

Though these questions seem equally applicable to musical works (S. Davies 2002a; Dubiel 2011), most of the literature on understanding music has focused on two more specifically musical topics: first, our understanding of basic musical features, such as pitch and rhythm and, second, interpretations of works of the sort given by music theorists. (For more detailed introductions to these and other topics in musical understanding, see S. Davies 2011c and Huovinen 2011.)

Before we turn to those topics, it is worth noting that two distinct activities go by the name of “interpretation” in music (and other performance arts): what might be called performative and critical interpretation (Levinson 1993). While a critical interpretation of a musical work (often called an analysis) is roughly equivalent to an interpretation of a novel—typically expressed linguistically—a performative interpretation is a way of playing or singing the work, typically expressed in a performance of it. It is not easy to clarify the relationship between these two kinds of musical interpretation, but see Levinson 1993, Maus 1999, Thom 2007, Neufeld 2012, and Dodd 2020a.

Animals can hear music in a sense—your dog might be frightened by the loud noise emitted by your stereo. People, by contrast, can understand the music they hear. What constitutes this experience of understanding music? To use an analogy, while the mere sound of a piece of music might be represented by a sonogram, our experience of it as music is better represented by something like a marked-up score. We hear individual notes that make up distinct melodies, harmonies, rhythms, sections, and so on, and the interaction between these elements. Such musical understanding comes in degrees along a number of dimensions. Your understanding of a given piece or style may be deeper than mine, while the reverse is true for another piece or style. My general musical understanding may be narrow, in the sense that I only understand one kind of music, while you understand many different kinds (Budd 1985b: 233–5; S. Davies 2011c: 88–95). Moreover, different pieces or kinds of pieces may call on different abilities, since some music has no harmony to speak of, some no melody, and so on. Many argue that, in addition to purely musical features, understanding the emotions expressed in a piece is essential to adequately understanding it (e.g., Ridley 1993; S. Davies 1994; Levinson 1990d: 30; Scruton 1997; Robinson 2005: 348–78).

At the base of the musical experience seem to be (i) the experience of tones , as opposed to mere sounds of various frequencies, where a tone is heard as being in “musical space,” that is, as bearing relations to other tones such as being higher or lower, or of the same kind (at the octave), and (ii) the experience of movement , as when we hear a melody as leaping up or wandering far afield and then coming to rest where it began. Roger Scruton (1983; 1997: 1–96) argues that these experiences are irreducibly metaphorical, since they involve the application of spatial concepts to that which is not literally spatial. (There is no identifiable individual that moves from place to place in a melody (S. Davies 1994: 229–34).) Malcolm Budd (1985b) argues that to appeal to metaphor in this context is unilluminating since, first, it is unclear what it means for an experience to be metaphorical and, second, a metaphor is only given meaning through its interpretation, which Scruton not only fails to give, but argues is unavailable. Budd suggests that the metaphor is reducible, and thus eliminable, apparently in terms of purely musical (i.e., non-spatial) concepts or vocabulary. Stephen Davies (1994: 234–40) doubts that the spatial vocabulary can be eliminated, but he is sympathetic to Budd’s rejection of the centrality of metaphor. Instead, he argues that our use of spatial and motion terms to describe music is a secondary, but literal, use of those terms that is widely used to describe temporal processes, such as the ups and downs of the stock market, the theoretical position one occupies, one’s spirits plunging, and so on. The debate continues in Budd 2003, Scruton 2004, and S. Davies 2011d.

Davies is surely right about the ubiquity of the application of the language of space and motion to processes that lack individuals located in space. The appeal to secondary literal meanings, however, can seem as unsatisfying as the appeal to irreducible metaphor. We do not hear music simply as a temporal process, it might be objected, but as moving in the primary sense of the word, though we know that it does not literally so move. Andrew Kania (2015) develops a position out of this intuition by emphasizing Scruton’s appeal to imagination while dropping the appeal to metaphor, arguing that hearing the music as moving is a matter of imagining that its constituent sounds move. (See also de Clercq 2007 and Trivedi 2011: 116–18.) Kania explicitly models his theory on the popular Waltonian theory of fiction (K. Walton 1990), though Walton seems to resist the application of his theory to basic musical understanding because of the differences between music and more paradigmatically representational arts (K. Walton 1988: 358–9, 1994: 53–4).

Apart from pitch space and melodic movement, there has been little philosophical discussion of either the nature and understanding of basic musical features such as melody, rhythm, meter, and harmony or how these elements work together in complex musical wholes. But see Roger Scruton 1997: 19–79, 2007; Stephen Davies 2001: 47–71; Hamilton 2007: 119–52; and Cheyne, Hamilton, and Paddison 2020.

It is widely acknowledged that explicit music-theoretical knowledge can aid deeper musical understanding and is essential for the adequate description and understanding of musical experiences—including one’s own (Kivy 1990). However, several philosophers have argued that one need not possess these concepts explicitly (nor the correlative vocabulary) in order to listen with understanding (Budd 1985b; 245–8; S. Davies 1994: 346–9; Levinson 1990d: 35–41). Mark DeBellis (1995: 117–31) argues that understanding fairly basic features of music, such as different kinds of cadences, requires a fused experience in which one applies a concept such as dominant seventh in one’s perception of the musical sounds. Stephen Davies (2011c: 88–94) responds that the serious but untutored listener should be able to develop such concepts, and thus have such experiences. Erkki Huovinen (2008) provides an example intended to cast doubt on this. Suppose that a melody is transposed from C major to D-flat major, but in a lower octave. One listener might hear the melody as reappearing higher, since D-flat is a half-step above C, while another might hear it as lower, since the constituent pitches of the second appearance are all lower than those of the first. Only a listener who understands the sense in which both these claims are true—that the melody has been transposed down a major seventh—truly understands what is going on musically. Yet such concepts of pitch organization … are not usually learned without some tuition (Huovinen 2008: 325).

For various art-historical reasons, formalism was the dominant approach to music-theoretic analysis, that is, the critical interpretation of musical works, throughout the twentieth century. (Hamilton 2007: 66–94 & 153–91 provides a useful discussion of the history from a philosophical perspective.) In short, the value of works of music was held to reside primarily in their large-scale harmonic structure.

Jerrold Levinson (1997) makes a case against such “architectonicism” in favor of “concatenationism,” the view that basic musical understanding consists in following the musical and emotional qualities of passages of music, and transitions between them, that are short enough to be apprehended as a single experience (“quasi-hearing”). He qualifies this basic idea considerably, allowing for the experience of previous parts of the piece, and anticipation of future parts, to modify one’s experience of the music in the moment. He also allows that architectonic awareness may play a role in enhancing one’s moment-to-moment experience, and may even play an ineliminable part in the understanding of some pieces. Nonetheless, Levinson maintains that the part played by architectonic knowledge in basic musical understanding is minimal, and that the cases where architectonic knowledge is necessary are very much the exception.

Peter Kivy has taken up the gauntlet on behalf of architectonicism (2001; see also S. Davies 2011c: 95–9). While Kivy acknowledges that the kinds of experiences Levinson champions are necessary to basic musical understanding, he defends the idea that grasping the large-scale form of most pieces of Western classical music, at least, is necessary for an adequate understanding of them. He does not deny that the experience of the form of a piece in listening to it is more intellectual than quasi-hearing, but he rejects Levinson’s argument that it is non-perceptual, and thus marginal to an adequate experience of it as music. Rather, Kivy argues, such experience is a matter of bringing one’s perceptions under sophisticated concepts. (A tactic Kivy does not consider is an attempt to hoist Levinson with his own contextualist petard, arguing that even if architectonic listening is non-perceptual it is a well-established mode of understanding pieces of music in the Western classical music world, and thus that to argue music must be understood primarily perceptually is to beg the question.)

The extent of the disagreement between the architectonicist and the concatenationist is unclear. They agree that the aspect of musical understanding the other emphasizes is a non-negligible component in the full understanding of a musical work. Levinson has been explicit since the first publication of his view that he intends it more as a polemic against and corrective to architectonicism, rather than as a replacement for it (1997: ix–xi; 1999: 485; 2006a). Perhaps that purpose has now been fulfilled, but see Huovinen 2013 for a revival of the debate and an attempted synthesis.

5. Music and Value

Most philosophical discussions of the value of music are implicitly restricted to the artistic value of purely instrumental musical works. To the extent that such discussions are motivated by the abstract nature of such music (see below), it is not clear to what extent they can be extended to musical hybrids such as song. Moreover, as we saw in section 1.2, it is not obvious that all music is art. Perhaps non-art music can be artistically valuable, but it presumably has other values; a complete theory of the value of music would apparently have to account for those values. (Presumably, art music can also have non-artistic value.)

Following the literature, however, the remainder of this subsection considers the artistic value of purely musical works. This is not the place to go into the many disputes about the nature of aesthetic and artistic value. (For an excellent introduction, see Stecker 2003b.) For our purposes, we can note there are two central points about artistic value on which there is some consensus. First, most philosophers take the value of artworks to be intrinsic (or inherent ) to them, in the sense that the value of a work is tied essentially to the experience that the work affords. Thus, artworks are not (properly) valued merely instrumentally, as means to some end, but “for” or “in” themselves (Budd 1995: 1–16; S. Davies 1987: 198–200; Scruton 1997: 374–6; Levinson 1992: 15–17).

The question that naturally arises next is what it is about the experience an artwork affords that makes it valuable. That pleasure is a non-negligible part of the answer to this question is the second point upon which there is some consensus (S. Davies 1987: 198–205; Levinson 1992; Kivy 1997b: 212–17). However, concomitant with this consensus is an acknowledgment that simple pleasure taken, say, in the sensuousness of the musical sounds is too trivial to ground the great value widely attributed to music. In looking for other sources, the puzzle that arises is that music is supposed to be an abstract art, par excellence . If this means that music is divorced from everything else that concerns us in the “real world” (that is, extra-musical life), it is puzzling why we should find so valuable the experiences musical works afford.

There are a couple of dimensions to most solutions of the puzzle of pure music’s value. One is the extent to which it is agreed that music really is abstract. To the extent that one thinks that music is not divorced from the real world, one will be able to argue that music’s value is at least no more puzzling than the value of arts more obviously related to the real world, such as literature and representational painting and sculpture. The other dimension to most solutions of the puzzle of pure music’s value is the extent to which one thinks the abstractness of music is the source of its value. Thus, two theorists might agree on the extent to which music is related to the real world (by being expressive, say), yet one locate its primary value in that expressiveness while the other locates it in its abstract, purely formal features.

Unsurprisingly, those who take the experience of music’s expressiveness to be a more intimately emotional one (through being predicated on imaginative engagement with the music, say), tend to emphasize that experience as more central to musical understanding, and thus attribute a larger part of music’s value to its expressiveness. Those, on the other hand, whose theory of the experience of musical expressiveness is more distanced (a matter of noticed resemblance, say), tend to place less weight on this element in their theories of musical value. At one extreme of this spectrum is the position that denies music to be expressive at all, and thus cannot attribute any of music’s value to its expressiveness (most notably Hanslick 1854; see also Zangwill 2004). Most theorists agree, however, that music’s value is to be located in different kinds of experience, including the experience of formal and expressive features; their disagreements are mostly about the relative weight of these different kinds of experiences in a complete account of musical value.

The extent of the disagreement between various parties to this dispute is not clear. Those defending the value of music’s expressiveness tend to claim that its contribution to overall musical value is significant, but many stop short even of according it primary value, and do not argue against the value of formal elements of musical works (Ridley 1995: 192–6; Levinson 1982, 1992: 20–2, 1996a: 124–5; Robinson 2005: 413; Young 2014: 150–4). They content themselves rather with pointing out the ways in which expressiveness can be valuable, focusing largely on the value of the emotional responses such expressiveness elicits in us. These include many of the features discussed above with respect to our interest in listening to music that arouses negative affective states in the listener. To recap, our emotional responses to music’s expressiveness can enable us to savor, understand, and even (to some extent) experience emotions in a “safe” way. They can provide us with a cathartic release, and enable us to participate in a kind of communication with the composer or communion with other members of our musical culture (Levinson 1982, 1996a; Higgins 1991, 2012; S. Davies 1994: 271). Emphasizing this last point, Roger Scruton argues that music’s value is quasi-moral, in that the kinds of music one responds to, or those valued in a particular culture, reflect the state of that individual’s or culture’s “soul” (1997: 380–91; see also S. Davies 1994: 275–6.) Stephen Davies (1987: 207–12) has argued that there are beneficial consequences of an interest in music in general , such as heightened emotional and aural sensitivity, which are not properly valued as consequences of listening to individual pieces, but which lead us to value musical culture as a whole (just as we value kindness for its consequences in general, while rejecting instrumental motivations for kind acts as inappropriate).

By contrast, those who defend the value of formal features tend to argue that the value of those features is primary, and that the value of music’s expressiveness is overrated. Peter Kivy, for instance, argues that expressive properties serve merely to highlight musical structure, as color might be used by the painter to emphasize contour or mass. Other expressive properties serve as structural properties in their own right (1990: 196). (See also Sharpe 2000: 1–83, and Zangwill 2004.)

Alan Goldman (1992) argues against the idea that music is particularly suited to the expression of emotion, claiming that representational arts such as painting and literature are better at this. Moreover, he disputes the grounds of the value of expressiveness given above. For example, he denies that music can teach us much about the emotions, and that we can savor our negative emotional responses to expressive music. Similarly, after an extensive discussion of the nature of musical expressiveness, Malcolm Budd argues that such expressiveness cannot come close to explaining music’s value (1995: 155–7). He points to the facts that much valuable music is not expressive and that the equal expressiveness of different pieces would be outweighed in a comparative evaluation by the differences between them in terms of formal value.

Both Goldman and Budd locate the value of pure music precisely in the abstractness that to some seems the greatest obstacle to explaining that value. Budd (1995: 164–71) points out that we have an extensive interest in abstract forms outside the realm of music, such as those of natural formations and in the decorative arts, and that such forms are capable of possessing valued aesthetic properties, such as beauty, elegance, and so on. Thus, it is no surprise that we value highly the works of an art of abstract forms. Goldman (1992), by contrast, emphasizes the detachment from the world of practical affairs implied by music’s abstractness. The complexity of great musical works demands the active engagement of our cognitive faculties, which we find rewarding, yet not in the pursuit of some practical goal that could be frustrated.

These issues are thrown into sharp relief in the debate over how instrumental musical works could be “profound.” See Kivy 1990: 202–18, 1997b: 140–78, 2003; Levinson 1992; White 1992; Ridley 1995, 2004: 132–65; S. Davies 2002b; Dodd 2014b.

There is no space here to discuss the evaluation of musical works and performances. See S. Davies 1987, Levinson 1990e, and Gracyk 2011.

There are musical aspects or elements of many uncontroversially representational art forms, such as song. Jeanette Bicknell (2015: 81–91) and Aaron Smuts (2013) discusses the ethics of song performance. But there has been little discussion, in the analytic tradition, of the relationship between musical and ethical values (as opposed to musical examples of more general ethical concerns, such as cultural appropriation). Kathleen Higgins (1991, 2012) and Roger Scruton (1997: 457–508) argue in very different ways that music is – or should be – central to our thinking about ethics. Garry Hagberg has explored many connections between improvisatory jazz practice, ethics, and politics (2002, 2006, 2008, 2021; see also Higgins 1991: 177). Peter Kivy (2008) argues against music’s capacity to affect our moral knowledge, behavior, or character. Jerrold Levinson (2013: 51–5), Philip Alperson (2014), and James Harold (2016) defend music’s moral efficacy.

The debate over whether an artwork’s moral flaws are artistic flaws has focused almost exclusively on representational (especially narrative) art forms. (Gaut (2007) offers an excellent overview.) Music has largely been ignored because it has been assumed to lack sufficient representational capacity to embody an attitude toward some object. Maria José Alcaraz León (2012), however, argues that music’s emotional expressiveness is enough to apply arguments about whether moral flaws are artistic flaws to pure instrumental music. (For critical discussion, see Kania 2020: 254–5.) Musicologist Susan McClary argues that canonical works of instrumental classical music oppress women by expressing a positive attitude toward narratives of the subjection of feminine elements (e.g., certain musical themes) by masculine ones. (See, for example, McClary 1991: 19–23, 53–79; for critical discussion, see Maus (2011).)

  • Alcaraz León, María José, 2012, “Music’s Moral Character”, Teorema , 31(3): 179–91.
  • Alperson, Philip, 1984, “On Musical Improvisation”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 43(1): 17–29. doi:10.2307/430189
  • –––, 1998, “Improvisation: An Overview”, in Encyclopedia of Aesthetics (Volume 1), Michael Kelly (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 478–9.
  • –––, 2009, “Facing the Music: Voices from the Margins”, Topoi , 28(2): 91–96. doi:10.1007/s11245-009-9052-9
  • –––, 2014, “Music and Morality”, in Ethics and the Arts , Paul Macneill (ed.), New York: Springer, pp. 21–31.
  • Alperson, Philip, Nguyen Chi Ben, & To Ngoc Thanh, 2007, “The Sounding of the World: Aesthetic Reflections on Traditional Gong Music of Vietnam”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 65(1): 11–20. doi:10.1111/j.1540-594X.2007.00233.x
  • Aristotle, Poetics , Stephen Halliwell (trans.), London: Duckworth, 1987.
  • Bartel, Christopher, 2017, “Rock as a Three-Value Tradition”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 75(2): 143–54.
  • Bicknell, Jeanette, 2015, Philosophy of Song and Singing: An Introduction , New York: Routledge.
  • Bicknell, Jeanette & John Andrew Fisher (eds.), 2013, Special Issue on Song, Songs, and Singing, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 71(1).
  • Bordwell, David and Noël Carroll (eds.), 1996, Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies , Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
  • Bresnahan, Aili, 2015, “Improvisation in the Arts”, Philosophy Compass , 10(9): 573–82. doi:10.1111/phc3.12251
  • Brown, Lee B., 1996, “Musical Works, Improvisation, and the Principle of Continuity”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 54(4): 353–69. doi:10.2307/431917
  • –––, 2000, “‘Feeling My Way’: Jazz Improvisation and its Vicissitudes—A Plea for Imperfection”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 58(2): 113–23. doi:10.2307/432090
  • –––, 2011, “Do Higher-Order Music Ontologies Rest on a Mistake?” British Journal of Aesthetics , 51(2): 169–84. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayr002
  • –––, 2012, “Further Doubts about Higher-Order Ontology: Reply to Andrew Kania”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 52(1): 103–6. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayr045
  • Bruno, Franklin, 2013, “A Case for Song: Against an (Exclusively) Recording-Centered Ontology of Rock”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 71(1): 65–74.
  • Budd, Malcolm, 1985a, Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • –––, 1985b, “Understanding Music”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplement), 59(1): 233–48. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/59.1.215
  • –––, 1995, Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry and Music , London: Penguin.
  • –––, 2003, “Musical Movement and Aesthetic Metaphors”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 43(3): 209–23. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/43.3.209
  • Cameron, Ross P., 2008, “There Are No Things That Are Musical Works”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 48(3): 295–314. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayn022
  • Caplan, Ben & Carl Matheson, 2004, “Can a Musical Work be Created?” British Journal of Aesthetics , 44(2): 113–34. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/44.2.113
  • –––, 2006, “Defending Musical Perdurantism”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 46(1): 59–69. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayj004
  • Carroll, Noël, 1988, Mystifying Movies: Fads and Fallacies in Contemporary Film Theory , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Cheyne, Peter, Andy Hamilton, & Max Paddison (eds.), 2019, The Philosophy of Rhythm: Aesthetics, Music, Poetics , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Collingwood, R.G., 1938, The Principles of Art , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Cooke, Deryck, 1959, The Language of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Cox, Renée, 1986, “A Defence of Musical Idealism”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 26(2): 133–142. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/26.2.133
  • Cray, Wesley D., 2019, “Transparent and Opaque Performance Personas”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 77(2): 181–91. doi:10.1111/jaac.12635
  • Cray, Wesley D. & Carl Matheson, 2017, “A Return to Musical Idealism”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 95(4): 702–15. doi:10.1080/00048402.2017.1281323
  • Currie, Gregory, 1989, An Ontology of Art , New York: St. Martin’s Press.
  • Davies, David, 2004, Art as Performance , Malden: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2009, “The Primacy of Practice in the Ontology of Art”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 67(2): 159–71. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6245.2009.01345.x
  • –––, 2011, Philosophy of the Performing Arts . Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9781444343458
  • –––, 2017, “Descriptivism and its Discontents”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 75(2): 117–29.
  • –––, 2021, “Puy on ‘Nested Types’”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 79(2): 251–5.
  • Davies, Stephen, 1987, “The Evaluation of Music”, in S. Davies 2003: 195–212.
  • –––, 1991, “The Ontology of Musical Works and the Authenticity of their Performances”, Noûs , 25(1): 21–41. doi:10.2307/2216091
  • –––, 1994, Musical Meaning and Expression , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1997a, “John Cage’s 4′33″ : Is it Music?”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 75(4): 448–62. Reprinted in Davies 2003b: 11–29. doi:10.1080/00048409712348031
  • –––, 2001, Musical Works and Performances: A Philosophical Exploration , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2002a, “The Multiple Interpretability of Musical Works”, in Is There a Single Right Interpretation? , Michael Krausz (ed.), University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 231–50.
  • –––, 2002b, “Profundity in Instrumental Music”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 42(4): 343–56. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/42.4.343
  • –––, 2003a, “Ontologies of Musical Works”, in S. Davies 2003b: 30–46.
  • –––, 2003b, Themes in the Philosophy of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2006, “Artistic Expression and the Hard Case of Pure Music”, in Kieran 2006: 179–91.
  • –––, 2007, “Balinese Aesthetics”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 65(1): 21–29. doi:10.1111/j.1540-594X.2007.00234.x
  • –––, 2011b, “Emotional Contagion from Music to Listener”, in S. Davies 2011e: 47–65.
  • –––, 2011c, “Musical Understandings”, in S. Davies 2011e: 88–129.
  • –––, 2011d, “Music and Metaphor”, in S. Davies 2011e: 21–34.
  • –––, 2011e, Musical Understandings and Other Essays on the Philosophy of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2012, “On Defining Music”, The Monist , 95: 535–55.
  • DeBellis, Mark, 1995, Music and Conceptualization , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • De Clercq, Rafael, 2007, “Melody and Metaphorical Movement”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 47(2): 156–68. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayl053
  • Dewey, John, 1934, Art as Experience , New York: Minton, Balch.
  • Dodd, Julian, 2007, Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2010, “Confessions of an Unrepentant Timbral Sonicist”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 50(1): 33–52. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayp044
  • –––, 2013, “Adventures in the Metaontology of Art: Local Descriptivism, Artefacts and Dreamcatchers”, Philosophical Studies , 165(3): 1047–68. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-9999-z
  • –––, 2014a, “Upholding Standards: A Realist Ontology of Standard Form Jazz”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 72(3): 277–90.
  • –––, 2014b, “The Possibility of Profound Music”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 54(3): 299–322. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayu031
  • –––, 2018, “What 4′33″ Is”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 96(4): 629–41.
  • –––, 2020a, Being True to Works of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2020b, “Blurred Lines: Ravasio on ‘Historically Informed Performance’”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 78(1): 85–90.
  • Dodd, Julian, & Philip Letts, 2017, “Types, Tokens, and Talk about Musical Works”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 75(3): 249–63.
  • Dubiel, Joseph, 2011 “Analysis”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 535–45.
  • Dyck, John, 2014, “Perfect Compliance in Musical History and Musical Ontology”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 54(1): 31–47.
  • Fisher, John Andrew, 1998, “Rock ’n’ Recording: The Ontological Complexity of Rock Music”, Musical Worlds: New Directions in the Philosophy of Music , Philip Alperson (ed.), University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press. 109–23.
  • –––, 2018, “Jazz and Musical Works”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 76(2): 151–62. doi:10.1111/jaac.12450
  • Gaut, Berys, 2007, Art, Emotion and Ethics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Goehr, Lydia, 1992, The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1998, The Quest for Voice: On Music, Politics, and the Limits of Philosophy: The 1997 Ernest Bloch Lectures , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Goldman, Alan, 1992, “The Value of Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 50(1): 35–44. doi:10.2307/431065
  • –––, 1995, “Emotions in Music (A Postscript)”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 53(1): 59–69. doi:10.2307/431737
  • Goodman, Nelson, 1968, Languages of Art , Indianapolis: Hackett; second edition, 1976.
  • Gould, Carol & Kenneth Keaton, 2000, “The Essential Role of Improvisation in Musical Performance”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 58(2): 143–8. doi:10.2307/432093
  • Gracyk, Theodore, 1996, Rhythm and Noise: An Aesthetics of Rock , Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
  • –––, 2001, I Wanna Be Me: Rock Music and the Politics of Identity , Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
  • –––, 2009, “The Song Remains the Same, But Not Always,” in Led Zeppelin and Philosophy: All will be Revealed , Scott Calef (ed.), Chicago: Open Court, 31–45.
  • –––, 2011, “Evaluating Music”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 165–75.
  • –––, 2017, “Performer, Persona, and the Evaluation of Musical Performance”, Contemporary Aesthetics , 15(13). [ Gracyk 2017 available online ]
  • Gracyk, Theodore & Andrew Kania (eds.), 2011, The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music , New York: Routledge.
  • Hagberg, Garry L., 1998, “Improvisation: Jazz Improvisation”, in Encyclopedia of Aesthetics (Volume 1), Michael Kelly (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, 479–82.
  • –––, 2002, “On Representing Jazz: An Art Form in Need of Understanding”, Philosophy and Literature , 26(1): 188–98. doi:10.1353/phl.2002.0013
  • –––, 2006 “Jazz Improvisation: A Mimetic Art?”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie , 238: 469–85.
  • –––, 2008, “Jazz Improvisation and Ethical Interaction: A Sketch of the Connections”, in Art and Ethical Criticism , Garry L. Hagberg (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 259–85.
  • –––, 2021, “Jazz”, in The Oxford Handbook of Western Music and Philosophy , Tomás McAuley, Nanette Nielsen, Jerrold Levinson, & Ariana Phillips-Hutton (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 579–99. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199367313.013.28
  • Hamilton, Andy, 2007, Aesthetics and Music , New York: Continuum.
  • Hanslick, Eduard, [1854] 1986, On the Musically Beautiful: A Contribution towards the Revision of the Aesthetics of Music ( Vom Musikalisch-Schönen ), Geoffrey Payzant (trans.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (First published 1854.)
  • Harold, James, 2016, “On the Ancient Idea that Music Shapes Character”, Dao , 15: 341–54. doi:10.1007/s11712-016-9515-9
  • Hazlett, Allan, 2012, “Indication, Abstraction, and Individuation”, in Mag Uidhir 2012a: 161–78.
  • Higgins, Kathleen Marie, 1991, The Music of Our Lives , Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
  • –––, 2007, “An Alchemy of Emotion: Rasa and Aesthetic Breakthroughs”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 65(1): 43–54. doi:10.1111/j.1540-594X.2007.00236.x
  • –––, 2012, The Music Between Us: Is Music a Universal Language? , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Howell, Robert, 2002, “Types, Indicated and Initiated”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 42(2): 105–27. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/42.2.105
  • Hume, David, [1757] 1985, “Of Tragedy”, in Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary , E. Miller (ed.), Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, pp. 216–25.
  • Huovinen, Erkki, 2008, “Levels and Kinds of Listeners’ Musical Understanding”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 48(3): 315–37. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayn023
  • –––, 2011, “Understanding Music”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 123–33.
  • –––, 2013, “Concatenationism and Anti-architectonicism in Musical Understanding”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 71(3): 247–60. doi:10.1111/jaac.12018
  • Ingarden, Roman, [1961] 1986, The Work of Music and the Problem of its Identity ( Utwór muzyczny i sprawa jego tożsamości ), Adam Czerniawski (trans.), Berkeley, CA: University of California Press; first published in German in 1961.
  • Jackendoff, Ray, 2011, “Music and Language”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 101–12.
  • Kania, Andrew, 2006, “Making Tracks: The Ontology of Rock Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 64(4): 401–14. doi:10.1111/j.1540-594X.2006.00219.x
  • –––, 2008, “The Methodology of Musical Ontology: Descriptivism and Its Implications”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 48(4): 426–44. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayn034
  • –––, 2010, “Silent Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 68(4): 343–53. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6245.2010.01429.x
  • –––, 2011a, “Definition”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 1–13.
  • –––, 2011b, “All Play and No Work: An Ontology of Jazz”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 69(4): 391–403. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6245.2011.01483.x
  • –––, 2015, “An Imaginative Theory of Musical Space and Movement”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 55(2): 157–72. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayu100
  • –––, 2020, Philosophy of Western Music: A Contemporary Introduction , New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315210629
  • –––, 2022, “The Heart of Classical Work-Performance”, The British Journal of Aesthetics , 62(1): 125–141, doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayab031
  • Kieran, Matthew (ed.), 2006, Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art , Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • Kivy, Peter, 1980, The Corded Shell: Reflections on Musical Expression , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1983a, “Platonism in Music: A Kind of Defense”, Grazer Philosophische Studien , 19(1): 109–129. Reprinted in Kivy 1993: 35–58. doi:10.1163/18756735-90000194
  • –––, 1983b, “Platonism in Music: Another Kind of Defense”, American Philosophical Quarterly , 24(3): 245–252. Reprinted in Kivy 1993: 59–74.
  • –––, 1988a, “Orchestrating Platonism”, in Aesthetic Distinction , Thomas Anderberg, Tore Nilstun, & Ingmar Persson (eds.), pp. 42–55. Reprinted in Kivy 1993: 75–94.
  • –––, 1988b, Osmin’s Rage: Philosophical Reflections on Opera, Drama, and Text , Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Second edition with a new preface and final chapter, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999.)
  • –––, 1989, Sound Sentiment: An Essay on the Musical Emotions, including the complete text of “The Corded Shell” , Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
  • –––, 1990, Music Alone: Philosophical Reflections on the Purely Musical Experience , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1993, The Fine Art of Repetition: Essays in the Philosophy of Music , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1994, “Speech, Song, and the Transparency of Medium: A Note on Operatic Metaphysics”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 52(1): 63–68. doi:10.2307/431585
  • –––, 1995, Authenticities: Philosophical Reflections on Musical Performance , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1997a, “Music in the Movies: A Philosophical Enquiry”, in Film Theory and Philosophy , R. Allen & M. Smith (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. 308–28.
  • –––, 1997b, Philosophies of Arts: An Essay in Differences , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1999, “Feeling the Musical Emotions”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 39(1): 1–13. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/39.1.1
  • –––, 2001, “Music in Memory and Music in the Moment ”, in New Essays on Musical Understanding , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 183–217.
  • –––, 2002, Introduction to a Philosophy of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2003, “Another Go at Musical Profundity: Stephen Davies and the Game of Chess”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 43(4): 401–11. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/43.4.401
  • –––, 2008, “Musical Morality”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie , 238: 397–412.
  • Kleinschmidt, Shieva & Jacob Ross, 2012, “Repeatable Artwork Sentences and Generics”, in Mag Uidhir 2012a: 125–57.
  • Langer, Susanne K., 1953, Feeling and Form , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Lerdahl, Fred & Ray S. Jackendoff, 1983, A Generative Theory of Tonal Music , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Letts, Philip, 2015, “Against Kania’s Fictionalism about Musical Works”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 55(2): 209–24. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayu102
  • –––, 2018, “The Property Theory of Musical Works”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 76(1): 57–69.
  • Levinson, Jerrold, 1980, “What a Musical Work Is”, Journal of Philosophy , 77(1): 5–28. doi:10.2307/2025596
  • –––, 1982, “Music and Negative Emotion.” Reprinted in Levinson 1990f: 306–35.
  • –––, 1984, “Hybrid Art Forms”, The Journal of Aesthetic Education , 18(4): 5–13. doi:10.2307/3332623
  • –––, 1987, “Song and Music Drama”, in Levinson 1990f: 42–59.
  • –––, 1990a, “The Concept of Music”, in Levinson 1990f: 267–78.
  • –––, 1990b, “What a Musical Work Is, Again”, in Levinson 1990f: 215–63.
  • –––, 1990c, “Authentic Performance and Performance Means”, in Levinson 1990f: 393–408.
  • –––, 1990d, “Musical Literacy”, The Journal of Aesthetic Education , 24(1): 17–30. doi:10.2307/3332852; reprinted in Levinson 1996c: 27–41 [page reference is to the reprint].
  • –––, 1990e, “Evaluating Musical Performance”, in Levinson 1990f: 376–92.
  • –––, 1990f, Music, Art, and Metaphysics , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1992, “Pleasure and the Value of Works of Art”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 32(4): 295–306. Reprinted in Levinson 1996c: 11–24. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/32.4.295
  • –––, 1993, “Performative vs Critical Interpretation in Music”, The Interpretation of Music , Michael Krausz (ed.), Oxford : Clarendon Press. 33–60. Reprinted in Levinson 1996c: 60–89.
  • –––, 1996a, “Musical Expressiveness”, in Levinson 1996c: 90–125.
  • –––, 1996b, “Film Music and Narrative Agency”, in Bordwell & Carroll 1996: 254–88. Reprinted in Contemplating Art: Essays in Aesthetics , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, pp. 143–83.
  • –––, 1996c, The Pleasures of Aesthetics , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1997, Music in the Moment , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 1999, “Reply to commentaries on Music in the Moment ”, Music Perception , 16(4): 485–94. doi:10.2307/40285805
  • ––– (ed.), 2003, The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.001.0001
  • –––, 2006a, “Concatenationism, Architectonicism, and the Appreciation of Music”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie , 238: 505–14.
  • –––, 2006b, “Musical Expressiveness as Hearability-as-expression”, in Kieran 2006: 192–206.
  • –––, 2012, “Indication, Abstraction, and Individuation”, in Mag Uidhir 2012: 49–61. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199691494.003.0003
  • –––, 2013, “Popular Song as Moral Microcosm: Life Lessons from Jazz Standards”, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement , 71: 51–66. doi:10.1017/S1358246112000264
  • Love, Stefan Caris, 2016, “The Jazz Solo as Virtuous Act”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 74(1): 61–74. doi:10.1111/jaac.12238
  • Magnus, P.D., 2012, “Historical Individuals Like Anas platyrhynchos and ‘Classical Gas’”, in Mag Uidhir 2012a: 108–24.
  • –––, 2016, “Kind of Borrowed, Kind of Blue”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 74(2): 179–85.
  • –––, 2022, A Philosophy of Cover Songs , Cambridge: Open Book. doi:10.11647/OBP.0293
  • Mag Uidhir, Christy (ed.), 2012a, Art and Abstract Objects , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199691494.001.0001
  • –––, 2012b, “Introduction: Art, Metaphysics, and the Paradox of Standards”, in Mag Uidhir 2012a: 1–26.
  • Matheson, Carl & Ben Caplan, 2011, “Ontology”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 38–47.
  • Matravers, Derek, 1998, Art and Emotion , Oxford: Clarendon. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199243167.001.0001
  • –––, 2011, “Arousal Theories”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 212–22.
  • Maus, Fred Everett, 1999, “Musical Performance as Analytical Communication”, in Performance and Authenticity in the Arts , Salim Kemal & Ivan Gaskell (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 129–53. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511520051.007
  • –––, 2011, “Music and Gender”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 569–80.
  • McAuley, Tomás, Nanette Nielsen, Jerrold Levinson, & Ariana Phillips-Hutton (eds.), 2021, The Oxford Handbook of Western Music and Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199367313.001.0001
  • McClary, Susan, 1991, Feminine Endings: Music, Gender, and Sexuality , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • McKeown-Green, Jonathan, 2014, “What is Music? Is There a Definitive Answer?” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 72(4): 393–403.
  • Meyer, Leonard B., 1956, Emotion and Meaning in Music , Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Millikan, Ruth Garrett, 1984, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2000, On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay about Substance Concepts , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Moruzzi, Caterina, 2018, “Every Performance Is a Stage”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 76(3): 341–51.
  • Neufeld, Jonathan A., 2012, “Critical Performances”, Teorema , 31(3): 89–104.
  • Nussbaum, Charles O., 2007, The Musical Representation: Meaning, Ontology, and Emotion , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2021, “Ontology”, in The Oxford Handbook of Western Music and Philosophy , Tomás McAuley, Nanette Nielsen, Jerrold Levinson, & Ariana Phillips-Hutton (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 325–344. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199367313.013.17
  • Penner, Nina, 2020, Storytelling in Opera and Musical Theater , Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
  • Predelli, Stefano, 1995, “Against Musical Platonism”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 35(4): 338–50. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/35.4.338
  • –––, 1999a, “Goodman and the Score”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 39(2): 138–47. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/39.2.138
  • –––, 1999b, “Goodman and the Wrong Note Paradox”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 39(4): 364–75. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/39.4.364
  • –––, 2001, “Musical Ontology and the Argument from Creation”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 41(3): 279–92. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/41.3.279
  • –––, 2009, “Ontologese and Musical Nihilism”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 49(2): 179–83. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayp004
  • Puy, Nemesio García-Carril, 2019, “The Ontology of Musical Versions: Introducing the Hypothesis of Nested Types”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 77(3): 241–54.
  • Radford, Colin, “Muddy Waters”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 49(3): 247–52. doi:10.2307/431480
  • Ravasio, Matteo, 2019a, “Historically Uninformed Views of Historically Informed Performance”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 77(2): 193–205.
  • –––, 2019b, “Appearance Emotionalism in Music: Analysis and Criticism”, Journal of Aesthetic Education , 53(3): 93–105.
  • –––, 2020, “Historically Informed Performance: A Reply to Dodd”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 78(1): 90–4.
  • Ridley, Aaron, 1993, “Bleeding Chunks: Some Remarks about Musical Understanding”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 51(4): 589–96. doi:10.2307/431891
  • –––, 1995, Music, Value and the Passions , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2003, “Expression in Art”, in Levinson 2003: 211–27.
  • –––, 2004, The Philosophy of Music: Theme and Variations , Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
  • Robinson, Jenefer, 1994, “The Expression and Arousal of Emotion in Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 52(1): 13–22. doi:10.2307/431581
  • –––, 2005, Deeper than Reason: Emotion and its Role in Literature, Music, and Art , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2011, “Expression Theories”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 201–11.
  • Rohrbaugh, Guy, 2003, “Artworks as Historical Individuals”, European Journal of Philosophy , 11(2): 177–205. doi:10.1111/1468-0378.00182
  • Rudner, Richard, 1950, “The Ontological Status of the Esthetic Object”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 10(3): 380–8.
  • Sartre, Jean-Paul, [1940] 1948, The Psychology of Imagination ( L’imaginaire ), Translator unrecorded. New York, NY: Philosophical Library.
  • Scruton, Roger, 1983, “Understanding Music”, in The Aesthetic Understanding: Essays in the Philosophy of Art and Culture , Manchester: Carcanet Press, pp. 77–100.
  • –––, 1997, The Aesthetics of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2004, “Musical Movement: A Reply to Budd”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 44(2): 184–7. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/44.2.184
  • –––, 2007, “Thoughts on Rhythm”, in Stock 2007: 226–55.
  • Sharpe, R.A., 1982, Review of Peter Kivy, The Corded Shell , British Journal of Aesthetics , 22(1): 81–2. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/22.1.81
  • –––, 2000, Music and Humanism: An Essay in the Aesthetics of Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Smith, Jeff, 1996, “Unheard Melodies? A Critique of Psychoanalytic Theories of Film Music”, in Bordwell & Carroll 1996: 230–47.
  • Smuts, Aaron, 2013, “The Ethics of Singing Along: The Case of ‘Mind of a Lunatic’”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 71(1): 121–9. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6245.2012.01548.x
  • Stecker, Robert, 2003a, Interpretation and Construction: Art, Speech, and the Law , Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2003b, “Value in Art”, in Levinson 2003: 307–24.
  • –––, 2009, “Methodological Questions about the Ontology of Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 67(4): 375–86. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6245.2009.01367.x
  • Sterritt, David, 2000, “Revision, Prevision, and the Aura of Improvisatory Art”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 58(2): 163–72. doi:10.2307/432095
  • Stock, Kathleen (ed.), 2007, Philosophers on Music: Experience, Meaning, and Work , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Thom, Paul, 2007, The Musician as Interpreter , University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  • Thomasson, Amie L., 2004, “Roman Ingarden”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , (Spring 2004 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/ingarden/ >.
  • –––, 2006, “Debates about the Ontology of Art: What Are We Doing Here?” Philosophy Compass , 1(3): 245–55. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00021.x
  • Tillman, Chris, 2011, “Musical Materialism”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 51(1): 13–29. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ayq028
  • Tolstoy, Leo, [1898] 1995, What is Art? ( Chto takoe iskusstvo ), Richard Pevear & Larissa Volokhonsky (trans.), London: Penguin.
  • Tormey, Alan, 1971, The Concept of Expression: A Study in Philosophical Psychology and Aesthetics , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Trivedi, Saam, 2002, “Against Musical Works as Eternal Types”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 42(1): 73–82. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/42.1.73
  • –––, 2011 “Music and Imagination”, in Gracyk & Kania 2011: 113–22.
  • Urmson, J. O., 1973, “Representation in Music”, in Philosophy and the Arts (Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, Volume 6), London: Palgrave, 132–46. doi:10.1017/S0080443600000844
  • Valone, James J., 1985, “Musical Improvisation as Interpretive Activity”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 44(2): 193–4. doi:10.2307/430522
  • Wadle, Douglas, forthcoming, “Organized Sound, Sounds Heard, and Silence”, Ergo .
  • Walton, Kendall L., 1988, “What is Abstract about the Art of Music?”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 46(3): 351–64. doi:10.2307/431106
  • –––, 1990, Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Walton, Susan Pratt, 2007, “Aesthetic and Spiritual Correlations in Javanese Gamelan Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 65(1): 31–41. doi:10.1111/j.1540-594X.2007.00235.x
  • White, David A., 1992, “Toward a Theory of Profundity in Music”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 50(1): 23–34.
  • Wollheim, Richard, 1968, Art and its Objects , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; second edition (with six supplementary essays), 1980. doi:10.1017/CBO9781316286777
  • Wolterstorff, Nicholas, 1980, Works and Worlds of Art , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1987, “The Work of Making a Work of Music”, in What is Music? An Introduction to the Philosophy of Music , Philip Alperson (ed.), New York: Haven. 101–29.
  • Young, James O., 1988, “The Concept of Authentic Performance”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 28(3): 228–38. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/28.3.228
  • –––, 2014, Critique of Pure Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Young, James O. & Carl Matheson, 2000, “The Metaphysics of Jazz”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 58(2): 125–34. doi:10.2307/432091
  • Zangwill, Nick, 2004, “Against Emotion: Hanslick Was Right About Music”, British Journal of Aesthetics , 44(1): 29–43. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/44.1.29
  • –––, 2007, “Music, Metaphor, and Emotion”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 65(4): 391–400. doi:10.1111/j.1540-594X.2007.00272.x
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

aesthetic experience | aesthetics: aesthetic judgment | aesthetics: and cognitive science | al-Farabi | Aristotle, General Topics: aesthetics | art, definition of | Confucius | dance, philosophy of | Du Bos, Jean-Baptiste | emotion | fiction: fictional entities | Goodman, Nelson: aesthetics | Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: aesthetics | history of Western philosophy of music:antiquity to1800 | imagination | Ingarden, Roman | music: history of western philosophy of, since 1800 | ontology of art, history of | perception: auditory | Schopenhauer, Arthur: aesthetics | types and tokens value: intrinsic vs. extrinsic Xunzi

Copyright © 2023 by Andrew Kania < akania @ trinity . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2024 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Digital Commons @ University of South Florida

  • USF Research
  • USF Libraries

Digital Commons @ USF > College of The Arts > School of Music > Theses and Dissertations

Music Theses and Dissertations

Theses/dissertations from 2023 2023.

A Novel Jazz Music Curriculum for Young Children: Results of A Pilot Study , Jazmin D. Ghent

Theses/Dissertations from 2022 2022

Where We Live and Learn to Know: An Oral History of the Rochelle High School Music Program , John Sargeant

Theses/Dissertations from 2021 2021

School Music Administration During the COVID-19 Pandemic: Trauma, Loss, Meaning, Change, and Innovation , Christopher Burns

Development and Validation of a Scale to Measure Songwriting Self-Efficacy (SSES) with Secondary Music Students , Patrick K. Cooper

Measuring Parental Involvement as Parental Actions in Children’s Private Music Lessons in China , Cancan Cui

Instrumental Music Instruction and Executive Functions: A Cross-Sectional Study of Romanian Children (10-12 Years) , Adrian Sorin Iordache

Racial and Ethnic Difference in Music Performance Self-Efficacy Among Undergraduate Students , George W. Shannon Ii

Theses/Dissertations from 2020 2020

Vocal Health of Choral Singers from Kenya and the United States: Dysphonia and Vocal Fatigue in Relation to Musical Genres , Morgan Jolley Burburan

Theses/Dissertations from 2019 2019

Two Phenomena in Contemporary Music Education: Mental Toughness and the Law , Jason R. Sivill

Theses/Dissertations from 2018 2018

The Making of a Nationally Recognized Band in a Small, Private Liberal Arts University: The Historical Significance of the Bobby L. Adams Years, 1987-2012 , Joshua David Blair

The Effects of a Self-Regulated Learning Music Practice Strategy Curriculum on Music Performance, Self-Regulation, Self-Efficacy, and Cognition , Kimberly N. Mieder

Music Software in the Compositional Learning Process , Daniel L. Nevels

Behavioral, Affective, and Cognitive Engagement of High School Music Students: Relation to Academic Achievement and Ensemble Performance Ratings , Joel E. Pagán

Theses/Dissertations from 2017 2017

Re-envisioning Music Teacher Education: A Comparison of Two Undergraduate Music Education Programs in the U.S. , Jonathan Ross Kladder

Music Ensemble Participation: Personality Traits and Music Experience , Tracy A. Torrance

Theses/Dissertations from 2016 2016

Influence of Musical Engagement on Symptoms of Tourette’s Disorder , William Christopher Brown

Motivation of Adult, Auditioned Community Choirs: Implications toward Lifelong Learning , David James Redman

The Effects of Technical and Imagery-based Instruction on Aspiring Performing Artists’ Acquisition of Learning Newly Composed Pieces and Improvisation and on Listeners’ Perceived Expressivity , José Valentino Ruiz-Resto

Theses/Dissertations from 2015 2015

Preference of Chinese Undergraduate Music Majors for Chinese Xi-Qu and Western Opera , Hong Chen

Secondary Band Participation and Executive Function , Dakeyan Cha' Dre' Graham

Theses/Dissertations from 2014 2014

An Examination of Cooperating Teachers' Observations of Their Student Teachers in the Areas of Personal, Teaching, and Musical Skills in the Elementary Classroom , Mark Remsen Cole

I Did That Wrong and It Sounded Good: An Ethnographic Study of Vernacular Music Making in Higher Education , Victor Ezquerra

Creativity-Based Music Learning: Modeling the Process and Learning Outcomes in a Massive Open Online Course , Nicholas Michael Stefanic

Theses/Dissertations from 2012 2012

The Relationship between Death Depression and Death Anxiety among Cancer Patients in Saudi Arabia , Doaa A. Almostadi

World Percussion Approaches in Collegiate Percussion Programs: A Mixed-methods Study , Patrick Michael Hernly

The Impact of Arranging Music for the Large Ensemble on the Teacher: A Phenomenological Exploration , James Teodor Lindroth

Listening in Action: Students' Mobile Music Experiences in the Digital Age , Rebecca Marie Rinsema

Theses/Dissertations from 2011 2011

The Performance Production Process of an Outstanding High School Choir , Kathy K. Rolsten

Transitioning from Student to Teacher in the Master-Apprentice Model of Piano Pedagogy: An Exploratory Study of Challenges, Solutions, Resources, Reflections, and Suggestions for the Future , Melissa Maccarelli Slawsky

Self-Efficacy in Music Performance: Measuring the Sources Among Secondary School Music Students , Michael S. Zelenak

Theses/Dissertations from 2008 2008

Analytical Perspectives of Thematic Unity: Applications of Reductive Analysis to Selected Fugues by J.S. Bach and G.F. Handel , Adam C. Perciballi

Theses/Dissertations from 2007 2007

Expanded Tonality: The Treatment of Upper and Lower Leading Tones As Evidenced in Sonata "Undine,” IV by Carl Reinecke , Joshua Blizzard

Theses/Dissertations from 2005 2005

The Compositional Style of Francesco Geminiani: a Reflection of Theory and Practice in His Music and Guida Armonica Treatise , Valerie R. Weber

Theses/Dissertations from 2004 2004

An Application of the Grundgestalt Concept to the First and Second Sonatas for Clarinet and Piano, Op. 120, No. 1 & No. 2, by Johannes Brahms , Devon Burts

The French Art Song Style in Selected Songs by Charles Ives , Christy Jo Talbott

Theses/Dissertations from 2003 2003

Music Programs that Engage Our Communities: Making a Stronger Connection , La Gretta Snowden

Advanced Search

  • Email Notifications and RSS
  • All Collections
  • USF Faculty Publications
  • Open Access Journals
  • Conferences and Events
  • Theses and Dissertations
  • Textbooks Collection

Useful Links

  • School of Music Homepage
  • Rights Information
  • SelectedWorks
  • Submit Research

Home | About | Help | My Account | Accessibility Statement | Language and Diversity Statements

Privacy Copyright

ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository

Home > ETD > 2399

Electronic Theses and Dissertations

Factors that lead students to study music education : a descriptive study..

Alexander T. Hamilton II , University of Louisville Follow

Date on Master's Thesis/Doctoral Dissertation

Document type.

Master's Thesis

Degree Name

Music Education

Degree Program

Music Education, MME

Committee Chair

Amchin, Robert

Committee Co-Chair (if applicable)

Acklin, Amy

Committee Member

Byrne, Greg

Author's Keywords

music education; career; motivation; influence

The purpose of this study was to survey music education students in their first year of undergraduate studies to learn what influences and/or musical experiences affected their choice in selecting music education as their major. Participants ( N = 28) were enrolled in an Introduction to Music Education course at a mid-sized metropolitan university. Subjects were asked to complete a survey and rate perceived degree of influences on the selection of the music education major. Participants were also asked to provide written responses on personal influences that led them to select music education as a major. Survey results indicated that 89.3% of the students were most influenced by their high school music instructor in their decision to pursue music education. Other results show from all participants that previous experiences in music ensembles also had an influence on their decisions.

Recommended Citation

Hamilton, Alexander T. II, "Factors that lead students to study music education : a descriptive study." (2016). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 2399. https://doi.org/10.18297/etd/2399

Since June 13, 2016

Included in

Fine Arts Commons , Music Education Commons

Advanced Search

  • Notify me via email or RSS
  • Collections
  • Disciplines

Author Corner

  • Collection Policy
  • License Agreements
  • ThinkIR Electronic Resource Guide
  • Submit Research

Related Links

  • Guidelines for the Preparation and Processing of Theses and Dissertations (School of Interdisciplinary & Graduate Studies) ( PDF )
  • University of Louisville Libraries Research Assistance and Instruction
  • Nonexclusive License to Electronically Disseminate UofL ETD ( PDF )
  • Data Management Guides for Theses and Dissertations

Home | About | FAQ | My Account | Accessibility Statement

Privacy Copyright

  • How it works

researchprospect post subheader

Useful Links

How much will your dissertation cost?

Have an expert academic write your dissertation paper!

Dissertation Services

Dissertation Services

Get unlimited topic ideas and a dissertation plan for just £45.00

Order topics and plan

Order topics and plan

Get 1 free topic in your area of study with aim and justification

Yes I want the free topic

Yes I want the free topic

Music Dissertation Topics

Published by Carmen Troy at January 4th, 2023 , Revised On May 16, 2024

Music is one of the most beautiful forms of art that involves an organized and hierarchical sound and silence. It is generally performed in terms of pitch, rhythm, and sound quality. Music is a passion that many enthusiasts aspire to pursue. While the art of music can be an innate ability, it can be pruned with proper learning. Therefore, musicology is an academic field that offers the teaching of music.

Suppose you are an avid music learner, you have chosen musicology for higher studies. Then, you need to complete your degree with a final dissertation. If you are unsure what dissertation to write about, you can check out some of the topics suggested by experienced, professional experts in music.

You may also want to start your dissertation by requesting a  brief research proposal  from our writers on any of these topics, which includes an  introduction  to the problem,  research question , aim and objectives,  literature review , along with the proposed  methodology  of research to be conducted. Let us know if you need any help in getting started.

Check our  example dissertation  to get an idea of  how to structure your dissertation .

You can review step by step guide on how to write your dissertation  here .

Want to know what essay structure and style will work best for your assignment?

Problem fixed! We can write any type of essay in any referencing style. We ensure every essay written is beyond your expectations.

essay structure

Latest Music Dissertation Topics

Topic 1: examining the benefits of using music therapy for curing mental health patients – a study on the hospitals under nhs foundation trust..

Research Aim: The aim of this study is to identify the benefits of using music therapy for curing mental health patients. The study will mainly focus on the use of music therapy in hospitals under the NHS Foundation Trust.

Objectives:

  • To figure out the key advantages of using music therapy to cure mental health patients.
  • To elaborate on how music therapy is being used by the hospitals under NHS Foundation Trust aims to cure mental health patients.
  • To share a stringent set of recommendations for the hospitals under the NHS Foundation Trust to strategically use music therapy for curing mental health patients.

Topic 2: A detailed study on the transformation of British electronic dance music (EDM) over the last 10 years.

Research Aim: The study aims to conduct research on the transformation of British electronic dance music (EDM) over the last 10 years.

  • To share knowledge about the key aspects and specifications of British electronic dance music (EDM).
  • To provide a comprehensive analysis of the transformation of British electronic dance music (EDM) in the last decade.
  • To develop an understanding of how overall EDM practices can be improved and led towards advancement thereby aligning with the British culture.

Topic 3: Examining the growing influence of electronic and digital technology on music education in the UK.

Research Aim: The present research study aims to examine the growing influence of electronic and digital technology on music education in the UK.

  • To shed light on the changes in modern-age music education alongside the increasing dominance of advanced technologies.
  • To demonstrate how the growing use of electronic and digital technologies is redefining music education in the UK.
  • To recommend how electronic and digital technologies can be used in the best possible way to influence music education in the UK.

Topic 4: Describing the benefits of using music for children’s learning specifically during the stage of early development – a study on the UK government's changing perspective and investment in children's music and art.

Research Aim: The aim of this research study is to describe the benefits of using music for children’s learning specifically during the stage of early development. The UK government’s changing perspective and investment in children’s music and art will be emphasised in this study.

  • To identify the key benefits of using music in children’s learning, especially during their early development.
  • To exemplify the changing perspective of the UK government and how the government is investing in children’s music and art.
  • To recommend strategies that can help in the use of music in the best way to support children’s learning at their early development stage.

Topic 5: Investigating the impacts of removing gender disparity on music composition and performance in the British music industry.

Research Aim: The aim of this study is to investigate the impacts of removing gender disparity on music composition and performance in the British music industry.

  • To contextualise the importance of maintaining gender equality for maintaining healthy practices in music composition and performance.
  • To describe how the removal of gender disparity may help in music composition and performance in the British music industry.
  • To suggest strategies to eliminate gender discrimination and inequality in the British music industry.

More Music Dissertation Topics

Topic. 1: major music platforms in the world:.

Research Aim: There are many channels through which we can stream music. Each of the platforms has its perks and flaws that either excite or infuriate the users. The aim of the research will be to critically analyze the major music platforms in the world. 

Topic. 2: Impact of music talent shows on music:

Research Aim: Almost all countries around the world produce music talent shows usually aimed to find out new, young, emerging talent. The music talent shows have significant effects on the music, musicians, and music industry. Now, whether the impact is good or bad, the research will aim to find it out. The focal purpose of the study will be to identify the positive and negative repercussions of music talent shows. 

Topic. 3: Health benefit of music:

Research Aim: We all have heard that music is the food for the soul, but it is yet to find out if it is any good to our body. However, it is true that music cheers us up and helps us unwind things. It is significant to study if it aids an ailment. The research will aim to find out if music has health benefits and explore the details about the ailments and the remedy.

Topic. 4: Pop music in the contemporary world

Research Aim: Pop music was the undisputed king in the back times. Today, although we get to see the spark of pop in music, it is not truly pop. The research will analyze and evaluate the nature of pop music today and how it is amalgamated with contemporary music all around the world. 

Topic. 5: Role of technology in music

Research Aim: Technology is a crucial determiner that cannot be overlooked. It has affected all of the significant aspects of our lives, and music is no exception. The music that existed without technologically driven machines used to be different from what it is today. The aim of the research is to make a comparison and contrast between the nature of the two products of music and understand their similarities and differences under the light of technology. 

Topic. 6: Music in Hollywood

Research Aim: The main aim of the research would be to make a standard music format that is followed in Hollywood. The type of music produced in Hollywood is different from other major film industries. The researcher will analyze and evaluate the music and create a generic algorithm of music production followed by music composers in Hollywood. 

Topic. 7: The obsolete music instruments

Research Aim: Today, not all musical instruments are in their original shape. In fact, most of them have been buried inside a land do a lack of marketing and usage. The researcher will conduct thorough research to investigate the obsolete musical instruments that are unfamiliar to most people of a specific area. 

Topic. 8: pros and cons of legal music sharing platforms

Research Aim: The aim of the research will be to find out and highlight the advantages and disadvantages of legal music-sharing platforms. It will also investigate their impact on the music itself and discover the user’s inclination or motivations for using the platforms.   

Topic. 9: Music piracy in the age of the internet

Research Aim: Music piracy has always existed, but in the age of the internet, it has become predominant. The aim of the research will be to explore and find out how easy or difficult it has become to pirate music because it has significant outcomes in both ways. 

Topic. 10: Role of music in human life

Research Aim: When we are happy, we listen to music. When we are sad, we listen to music. Music has something to offer to each of our moods, and therefore, it is an integral part of our lives. This research will deeply analyze the role of music in human life and in what ways it affects our feelings, mood, actions, behaviors, and mundane activities. 

How Can ResearchProspect Help?

ResearchProspect writers can send several custom topic ideas to your email address. Once you have chosen a topic that suits your needs and interests, you can order for our dissertation outline service which will include a brief introduction to the topic, research questions , literature review , methodology , expected results , and conclusion . The dissertation outline will enable you to review the quality of our work before placing the order for our full dissertation writing service !

Topic. 11: How does music therapy work:

Research Aim: Music therapy is practiced in a large proportion of the world. The researcher will monitor people taking music therapy and identify its level of effectiveness. 

Topic. 12: Music and economy:

Research Aim: Good music transcends boundaries and therefore gets most disseminated and widespread. As a result, it is able to generate more money. The counties whose music is listened around the world have music as a key contributor to their Gross domestic product. The aim of the research is to survey and find out the statistics of music and its contribution to the economy. 

Topic. 13: music and culture

Research Aim: There are different kinds of music produced around the world, much of which depends on the culture of the respective area. The research will study the influence of culture on music and vice versa. 

Topic. 14: Role of music in spirituality

Research Aim: Music has a unique and close relationship with spirituality. Music is an instrument used to invoke feelings of spirituality. The researcher will study different religions and their way of connecting to God through music. 

Topic. 15: Music bands- their relevance today

Research Aim: The popularity and craze of music bands were very high in the 90s than what it is today. The aim of the research is to find out the potential of music bands in the contemporary music industry in different ways. 

Topic. 16: Music and patriotism

Research Aim: Music and poetry are used all around the world to boost the patriotism and nationalism of the inhabitants. The researcher will broadly study and investigate the instrumentation of music for patriotism and how music is used for political gains and at avenues. The researcher can do case studies and find accurate answers to the research questions. 

Topic. 17: Understanding the music market

Research Aim: The music market is just like any other product market: it is vast and diverse. You cannot make an audience persona for music, but you can make audience personas for different genres of music. And this research will do that. The research will aim to make audience personas of varying music genres understand the music market. 

Topic. 18: Most influential musicians today

Research Aim: The main aim of the research would be to explore and understand the current trends in music and pinpoint the most influential musicians today. Different musicians will be evaluated against different variables such as music they have produced, outreach, and followers, etc. 

Topic. 19: Music in the 21st century

Research Aim: Music has evolved significantly over the period of time, and there is no doubt that it will keep on transforming in the coming years. The aim of the research is to study and evaluate the current nature of music produced in the world and, more particularly, about the taste of people. 

Topic. 20: The evolution of music:

Research Aim: The researcher will delve into the history of the music to learn about its roots. The main aim of the research is to find and evaluate the evolution of music than how it developed over time and the phases that it went through to reach its current position. 

Free Dissertation Topic

Phone Number

Academic Level Select Academic Level Undergraduate Graduate PHD

Academic Subject

Area of Research

Frequently Asked Questions

How to find music dissertation topic.

To find a music dissertation topic:

  • Explore genres, history, or cultural aspects.
  • Analyze music theory, composition, or performance.
  • Investigate technology’s impact on music.
  • Consider social or psychological dimensions.
  • Review recent research in musicology.
  • Select a topic that resonates with your passion and expertise.

You May Also Like

A drama dissertation must be fully reflected in its topic. Here’s a list of the 65 most interesting dissertation topics on drama for you.

Here is a list of sports dissertation topics to help you choose the one studies any one as per your requirements.

As a computer networking student, you have a variety of networking topics to choose from. With the field evolving with each passing day.

USEFUL LINKS

LEARNING RESOURCES

researchprospect-reviews-trust-site

COMPANY DETAILS

Research-Prospect-Writing-Service

  • How It Works

IMAGES

  1. Music Dissertation Topics

    dissertation music definition

  2. Dissertation In Music Education

    dissertation music definition

  3. Pronunciation of Music

    dissertation music definition

  4. Music research paper thesis proposal

    dissertation music definition

  5. How to Write a Dissertation

    dissertation music definition

  6. Masters Dissertation Proposal Example

    dissertation music definition

VIDEO

  1. Thesis 101: Building a Theoretical Framework

  2. How to write a good introduction #research #thesis #dataanalytics #dissertation #introduction

  3. The Music That Defined James Bond

  4. Understanding Music Composition

  5. Film Scoring: The Role of Music in Film

  6. Dissertation Defense

COMMENTS

  1. PDF Treatise and Dissertation Handbook

    An ETD (Electronic Thesis or Dissertation) is a document that explains the research or scholarship of a graduate student. It is expressed in a form simultaneously suitable for machine archives and worldwide retrieval. The ETD is similar to its paper predecessor: It has figures, tables, footnotes, and references.

  2. (PDF) Music Definition and Music Education: many ...

    Music Definition and Music Education: many perspectives, many voices, many questions. January 2022. Publisher: Greek Society for Music Education (GSME) ISBN: 978-618-83465-6-7. Authors:

  3. PDF Liberty University School of Music

    Steps to Completing the Dissertation. This section discusses the steps required to complete the Doctor of Philosophy in Music Education. Step 1: Submit Dissertation Topic for Approval. Both MUSC ...

  4. Dissertations

    Music: Dissertations. Oxford dissertations have traditionally been deposited in hard-copy in the Bodleian and are treated as manuscripts. All doctoral dissertations now have entries on SOLO and many more recent theses are available in full-text through Oxford's research repository ORA. Composition degrees also involve the deposit of portfolio ...

  5. AMS—Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology

    What it is. Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology (DDM) is an international database of bibliographic records for completed dissertations and new dissertation topics in the fields of musicology, music theory, and ethnomusicology, as well as in related musical, scientific, and humanistic disciplines. Search.

  6. Research Guides: Music Research Guide: Dissertations and Theses

    A central, open-access repository of research (including dissertations and scholarly articles) by members of the Harvard community. A bibliography of completed dissertations and proposed topics in musicology, music theory, ethnomusicology, and related disciplines. Maintained by the American Musicological Society.

  7. Research Guides: Finding Music Materials: Find dissertations

    The American Musicological Society's Doctoral Dissertations in Musicology (DDM) is an international database of bibliographic records for completed dissertations and new dissertation topics in the fields of musicology, music theory, and ethnomusicology, as well as in related musical, scientific, and humanistic disciplines.

  8. PDF Toward a Framework for a New Philosophy of Music Education: Logstrup as

    James C. Scott, Dean of the College of Music Sandra L. Terrell, Dean of the Robert B. Toulouse School of Graduate Studies ... underpinning of our profession in an irreconcilable way.6 It is the purpose of this dissertation to 1 Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, s.v. "Philosophy," by Thomas Mautner.

  9. Yale University Library Research Guides: Music: Dissertations

    The Music Library has purchased many copies of dissertations from other universities. Most Yale dissertations that are not full-text in ProQuest (above) are available in paper or microfilm for reading, scanning, or printing. Dissertations can be located in Quicksearch by: (1) Entering the author or title in the Basic Search box.

  10. Music Research: Dissertation and Thesis Guidance for Topic Selection

    Music library personnel are available to assist PhD, DMA, and master's students who need help with any of these aspects of working on their dissertations or theses. Please send your questions to [email protected] or come by the library to meet with us in person.

  11. Research and Recent Dissertations

    The Eastman theory faculty pursues a broad range of research interests, including Schenkerian theory, studies in the theory and analysis of 20th-century music, history of music theory, musical perception and cognition, computing and music, and jazz and other popular music. An annual lecture series serves to expand research horizons still further.

  12. Creativity and Wellbeing in Music Education

    The thesis concludes with the conviction that Music Education preserves a rich potential for realising and expressing the core values of progressive education today: promoting for the children in our schools the experiences of creativity, health, resilience and wellbeing which matter so much for surviving and attaining the good life in our ...

  13. Music Dissertations, Theses, and Recording Projects: a guide

    Music Dissertations, Theses, and Recording Projects: a guide: Dissertation and Theses Databases. Get Started; ... Cover Art ; Dissertation and Theses Databases; Iowa Research Online. Iowa Research Online . Dissertations and Theses written here at Iowa, available open access and scoped to Music. Learn more here >> ProQuest Dissertations and ...

  14. Student Perspectives on the Music-Learning Culture in a Competitive

    contemporary popular music such as rap, rock, and pop, and the music they typically study while attending school such as classical, jazz, and other "art" music (Snead, 2010). With an increased interest in music related activities during the teenage years, it may be

  15. Full article: Concepts, Terminology and Methodology in Music

    A music performance may be defined as the live presentation of a music event by musicians and other participants or stakeholders at a given time and place, usually in the presence of an audience. The concept of music performativity, on the other hand, includes not only the artist's/artists' production of sounds and movements, persona (stage ...

  16. PDF A Guide to Completing the Music Education Thesis

    Masters Thesis is typically between 50 and 150 double-spaced pages in length. It is recommended that the research design be qualitative in nature. It is further recommended that students enroll in ME 685: Research in Music Education in preparation for the completion of the Master's thesis. Students are also referred to the following texts:

  17. What Is a Dissertation?

    A dissertation is a long-form piece of academic writing based on original research conducted by you. It is usually submitted as the final step in order to finish a PhD program. Your dissertation is probably the longest piece of writing you've ever completed. It requires solid research, writing, and analysis skills, and it can be intimidating ...

  18. ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst

    ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst

  19. Scholars Crossing

    Discover the scholarly works of Liberty University faculty and students in various disciplines. Access dissertations, theses, and publications online.

  20. The Philosophy of Music

    The Philosophy of Music. Philosophy of music is the study of fundamental questions about the nature and value of music and our experience of it. Like any "philosophy of X," it presupposes knowledge of its target. However, unlike philosophy of science, say, the target of philosophy of music is a practice most people have a significant ...

  21. Music Theses and Dissertations

    Theses/Dissertations from 2021. PDF. School Music Administration During the COVID-19 Pandemic: Trauma, Loss, Meaning, Change, and Innovation, Christopher Burns. PDF. Development and Validation of a Scale to Measure Songwriting Self-Efficacy (SSES) with Secondary Music Students, Patrick K. Cooper. PDF.

  22. "Factors that lead students to study music education : a descriptive st

    Hamilton, Alexander T. II, "Factors that lead students to study music education : a descriptive study." (2016). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 2399. The purpose of this study was to survey music education students in their first year of undergraduate studies to learn what influences and/or musical experiences affected their choice ...

  23. 20+ Music Dissertation Topics

    More Music Dissertation Topics. Topic. 1: Major music platforms in the world: Topic. 2: Impact of music talent shows on music: Topic. 3: Health benefit of music: Topic. 4: Pop music in the contemporary world. Topic. 5: Role of technology in music. Topic. 6: Music in Hollywood.